BAILII is celebrating 24 years of free online access to the law! Would you consider making a contribution?
No donation is too small. If every visitor before 31 December gives just Β£5, it will have a significant impact on BAILII's ability to continue providing free access to the law.
Thank you very much for your support!
[Home] [Databases] [World Law] [Multidatabase Search] [Help] [Feedback] | ||
Irish Law Reform Commission Papers and Reports |
||
You are here: BAILII >> Databases >> Irish Law Reform Commission Papers and Reports >> Sentencing, Consultation Paper on (LRC CP 6-1993) [1993] IELRC 1 (March 1993) URL: http://www.bailii.org/ie/other/IELRC/1993/1.html Cite as: [1993] IELRC 1 |
[New search] [Help]
THE LAW REFORM COMMISSION
AN COIMISIΪN UM ATHCHΣIRIΪ AN DLΝ
CONSULTATION PAPER
ON
SENTENCING
March 1993
IRELAND
The Law Reform Commission
Ardilaun Centre, 111 St Stephen's Green, Dublin 2
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=0 |
© Copyright The Law Reform Commission 1993
First Published March 1993
Cover: The Courthouse, Washington Street, Cork.
(photo courtesy of Cork Examiner)
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=0 |
THE LAW REFORM COMMISSION
The Law Reform Commission was established by section 3 of the Law Reform Commission Act, 1975 on 20th October, 1975. It is an independent body consisting of a President and four other members appointed by the Government.
The Commissioners at present are:
The Hon. Mr. Justice Anthony J. Hederman, Judge of the Supreme Court, President;
John F. Buckley, Esq., B.A., LL.B., Solicitor;
William R. Duncan, Esq., M.A., F.T.C.D., Barrister-at-Law, Associate Professor of Law, University of Dublin;
Ms. Maureen Gaffney, B.A., M.A. (Univ. of Chicago), Senior Lecturer in psychology, University of Dublin;
Simon P. O'Leary, Esq., B.A., Barrister-at-Law.
The Commission's programme of law reform, prepared in consultation with the Attorney General, was approved by the Government and copies were laid before both House of the Oireachtas on 4th January, 1977. The Commission has formulated and submitted to the Taoiseach or the Attorney General forty four Reports containing proposals for the reform of the law. It has also published eleven Working Papers, five Consultation Papers and Annual Reports. Details will be found on pp.415419.
Alpha Connelly, B.A., LL.M., D.C.L., is Research Counsellor to the Commission.
Ms. Emily Egan, LL.B., B.C.L. (OXON), Ms. Clνona Kimber, LL.B., LL.M., Mr. James Kingston, LL.B., LL.M., Barrister-at-Law, and Ms. Julianne O'Leary, B.A., LL.B., Barrister-at-Law are Research Assistants.
Further information from:
The Secretary,
The Law Reform Commission,
Ardilaun Centre,
111 St. Stephen's Green,
Dublin 2.
Telephone: 715699.
Fax No: 715316.
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=iii |
|
As part of its First Programme for examination of different branches of the law, which was laid before both Houses of the Oireachtas on 4th January, 1977, the Commission proposed to examine various aspects of the criminal law and criminal procedure, including in particular the law on the matters proper to be taken into account in sentencing convicted persons.
On the 6th March, 1987, the then Attorney General, Mr John Rogers S.C., requested the Commission to formulate proposals for reform of the law in relation to a number of areas. These included the law relating to certain aspects of the criminal law, and, first and foremost, sentencing policy.
During the course of its research on sentencing, the Commission noted that a clear statement of the matters proper to be taken into account in sentencing convicted persons is closely dependent on the policy governing the sentencing of offenders first being clearly articulated: where the policy is vague or incoherent, any number of matters may without impropriety be taken into account by reference to that policy. The Commission concluded that the primary matter to be dealt with, therefore, was the formulation of a coherent sentencing policy, which, once in place, would indicate what matters ought properly be taken into account in sentencing.
In the present Consultation Paper we begin by setting out in Chapter 1 the existing law and practice of sentencing and touch briefly upon the difficulties encountered in this area. In Chapter 2 we then examine the role of sentencing policy and the effect which incoherent policy has on existing sentencing law and practice. In Chapter 3 we examine the respective roles of the legislature and the courts in sentencing reform, and in Chapter 4 we discuss the role of the existing components of our sentencing policy making some provisional recommendations for reform of sentencing policy which would be more purposive, consistent and
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=1 |
just. Chapter 5 examines the types of matter proper to be taken into account in
sentencing, and Chapter 6 looks at the importance of prior criminal record.
Chapter 7 contains a review of sentencing policy in other jurisdictions.
Chapter 8 examines continental European responses to sentencing disparity.
Chapter 9 discusses in detail means of implementing sentencing policy, drawing
on the rich vein of comparative experience. Subsequent chapters are concerned
with the statutory context of sentencing (Chapter 10); matters of procedure
(Chapters 11, 12, 13 and 14); the co-ordination of penal and sentencing policy
(Chapter 15); and sentencing information and studies (Chapter 16). We conclude
by setting out our provisional proposals for reform.
On the 30th of September, 1992 when the Commission was on the point of going to print, the Minister for Justice presented the Criminal Justice Bill, 1992. The Commission had to decide at that stage whether to ignore or examine the Bill.
We decided to examine it, even if this delayed publication. Our examination led in particular to a re-appraisal of the Commission's approach to Victim Impact evidence. The Commission was unable to agree on a provisional recommendation so we have simply set out below arguments for and against the introduction of mandatory victim impact statements and have sought views.
In the Whitaker Report on the Penal system, it is concluded that complexities are the reality of the criminal justice system but that given the present state of criminal justice statistics, their frequency cannot be measured.
This lack of information is not merely a nuisance which hinders research. It is a feature of the criminal justice system that decisions are taken at one stage in ignorance of what is occurring elsewhere in the system.1 |
Unfortunately, this situation remains unchanged. Any provisional recommendations in this paper or recommendations ultimately made in our Report will be rendered comparatively ineffective by the absence of proper information. Details of every sentence imposed in every court and of every instance of election for trial venue by judge, prosecution or accused should be recorded and speedily retrievable. It would not be possible to attain this by relying on occasional research.
A distinct national office or agency should be established under the aegis of the Department of Justice, the Gardaν or the DPP, staffed by experts in criminological research to conduct the necessary research and provide statistics. This office, which could be given a statutory basis, would have to secure the trust and confidence of the aforementioned bodies and of the judiciary in order to ensure that the relevant information would readily be made available, if necessary by affording access to files and orders.2
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=2 |
While the President of the Commission, Mr. Justice Hederman, was appointed before this paper went to print, he took no part in its preparation and it would be unfair in the circumstances to associate him with any provisional recommendation made in the Paper. Happily, the Commission will have the benefit of his extensive experience in this area when it comes to make its final Report.
We emphasise that the proposals for reform contained in this Consultation Paper are provisional in their nature. We invite written submissions in relation to any of these proposals and the material contained in this Consultation Paper. Any such submissions received by us will be assessed with great care before we present our final proposals to the Attorney General. We also hope to hold a Seminar which will enable a full discussion of the Consultation Paper to take place.
We would be grateful if submissions on the Consultation Paper were sent to us at the Commission's Offices not later than 1st June, 1993.
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=3 |
1.1
What is sentencing? While there exists a general consensus as to the etymology of the expression sentence from the Latin sententia, meaning literally feeling or opinion1 there appears to be very little in the way of coherent Irish statement as to the nature of sentencing. Little assistance is to be gained from the definition of sentence which appears in section 21 of the Criminal Appeal Act, 1907:
The expression sentence includes any order of the court made on conviction with reference to the person convicted or his wife or children, and any recommendations of the court as to the making of an expulsion order in the case of a person convicted, and the power of the Court of Criminal Appeal to pass a sentence includes a power to make any such order of the Court or recommendation, and a recommendation so made by the Court of Criminal Appeal shall have the same effect for the purposes of section three of the Aliens Act, 1905, as the certificate and recommendation of the convicting Court. |
1.2
As well as being, perhaps, somewhat verbose, this explanation would exclude from the ambit of sentencing many orders made by the District Court under the Probation of Offenders Act, 1907 which do not require conviction before they may be made.2 Nowadays, conviction is not always a prerequisite for the imposition of sentence; rather what is always required is a finding of guilt. A number of more helpful formulations appear in recent sentencing reform literature. The British Government, for example, describes sentence thus:
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=4 |
The sentence of the court prescribes the punishment for criminal behaviour.3 |
1.3
JUSTICE, the British section of the International Commission of Jurists has said:
A sentence is the order of a criminal court imposing punishment on an individual for an offence of which he has been found guilty.4 |
1.4
Sentencing might thus be described as the act of a criminal court imposing punishment on an individual found guilty of an offence. Other formulations of sentencing, however, avoid the concept of punishment. The Victorian Sentencing Committee said:
Sentencing is the process by which people who offend against the criminal law have sanctions imposed upon them in accordance with that law. Many of those sanctions involve punishment, others involve the exercise of mercy and yet others represent means by which a person's conduct or attitudes may be altered so they do not offend in the future.5 |
1.5
The Canadian Law Reform Commission also took this approach, defining sentencing as:
that process in which the court or officials, having inquired into an alleged offence, give a reasoned statement making clear what values are at stake and what is involved in the offence.6 |
1.6
That certainly is not the case in Irish courts; rarely do our courts give reasoned statements of the values at stake in sentencing.7 The most cogent, perhaps, of this kind of formulation is that of the Canadian Sentencing Commission:
Sentencing is the judicial determination of a legal sanction to be imposed on a person found guilty of an offence.8 |
1.7
This description highlights the most important element of sentencing: judicial determination. Sentencing involves a decision by a judge9 as to what the criminal justice system should do to a person found guilty of an offence. Occasionally, as we shall see, the District Court may decide simply to dismiss
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=5 |
the information or charge.10
1.8
This type of formulation is also to be preferred at an early stage of discussion because it avoids reference to punishment. The notion of punishment implies, as we shall see, a certain ideological approach to the question of sentencing: i.e. retribution. Another approach, that of rehabilitation, prefers to view the imposition of legal sanction not as punishment, but as treatment. Later, we shall examine the merits of these differing views,11 but for the present it may be of some assistance to discussion if we do not commit ourselves to any one ideological approach.
1.9
Also, by avoiding reference to punishment, it is easier to conceive of orders, such as indefinite adjournment and absolute discharge, as forming part of the sentencing process12 even though they may not impose such a measure of pain as to properly be described as punishment in the ordinary sense.
1.10
We prefer to describe sentencing, therefore, as the judicial determination of the sanction, if any, to be imposed on a person found guilty of an offence.
1.11
The sentencing hearing may begin once there has been a plea or a finding of guilt. The proceedings may have taken a number of courses prior to this: the defendant may have pleaded not guilty at the trial but subsequently have been found to be guilty by the judge or jury; or may have changed his or her plea to guilty during the course of the trial; or he or she may have pleaded guilty at the outset. The court may then proceed to sentence, or it may adjourn for the compilation of reports and to allow the parties to call witnesses to the court. If the plea or finding of guilt was made in the District Court, the District Judge may have sent the offender forward to the Circuit Court for sentencing in order to avail of that court's wider jurisdiction.
1.12
We now examine the procedures which may be implemented in the course of the sentencing hearing. It should be observed that not all sentencing hearings will follow this pattern, since neither the rules of court, legislation nor judicial precedent set out a course of procedure to be followed at every sentencing hearing. Indeed, in some cases, particularly at District Court level, it is difficult to distinguish the sentencing hearing from the determination of the substantive issue of guilt since the District Judge may decide the sentence to be imposed on the evidence adduced during the course of the trial. Nonetheless, practice has over the years established a pattern of procedure which is generally followed at sentencing hearings in the superior courts.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=6 |
1.13
It is normally the prosecution which opens the sentencing hearing by presenting the facts of the offence to the court. When an offender pleads guilty to the charge at an early stage of the trial, the court may know little about the circumstances of the offending behaviour. Similarly, if the offender has been sent forward to the Circuit Court by the District Court for sentencing, the Circuit Court Judge will know little about the case. Occasionally, in District Court sentencing hearings, the District Judge may have learnt many of the details during the course of a preliminary examination, particularly if there has been some question as to whether or not the offence was minor in nature and fit to be tried summarily, and, thus, may feel that it is unnecessary to rehear all the circumstances of the offence.
1.14
The prosecution will explain to the court what the case involves by summarising the evidence which has been heard during the trial, or, if the offender has pleaded guilty, the evidence which the prosecution would have presented at the trial normally starting with the circumstances of the crime and finishing with the offender's apprehension and charge. It is usual for the prosecution to call a Garda witness to give sworn testimony as to these matters.
1.15
If the defendant pleads guilty but disputes the prosecution's version of the facts, the defence may either contact the prosecution prior to the hearing to see if they are prepared to modify their version of the facts, or, if the prosecution is not prepared to do so, the defence may address the court on the facts in dispute. There is no clear authority as to how the court should resolve such a conflict, but it seems from English decisions that the court will not order a trial on a verdict of not guilty simply to enable the sentencer determine a question of fact which does not affect the outcome of the trial itself.13 There is also some English authority to the effect that the sentencing court may either hear evidence and come to a conclusion on the matter14 (both sides calling witnesses and cross examining them in the usual way, if appropriate15), or hear no evidence, but listen instead to the submissions of counsel and come to a conclusion.16 If the latter course is followed, the benefit of any doubt must be given to the defence.17
1.16
There is no established rule as to the standard of proof which should be attained by the prosecution and defence at the outline stage. In England,
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=7 |
however, if the sentencing court chooses to hear evidence from both sides, the usual standard of proof in criminal trials is applied (i.e. beyond any reasonable doubt),18 but this carries only the weight of English precedent and there seems to be no Irish authority on the matter. The usual requirements as to corroboration should also be applied, although this may have the peculiar consequence of the trial judge issuing a corroboration warning to himself.19
1.17
Where an offender pleads not guilty, the court will usually have received evidence on all the germane facts during the course of the trial. The judge must make his own decision as to what were the true circumstances of the case. Where the defendant has been found guilty by a jury and the factual basis for the verdict is implicit in that verdict, it seems that the sentencer is bound to accept this and sentence accordingly.20 A dispute as to the facts may still arise, however. For example, if the finding of guilt results from a jury verdict, the basis of the verdict may remain unclear. Similarly, if the sentencing hearing is taking place in the Circuit Court following a finding of guilt in the District Court, the basis of the District Judge's verdict may remain unclear. Again, the task of the sentencing judge is to make his or her own decision on the evidence as to what were the true circumstances of the case,21 and, seemingly, giving the offender the benefit of the doubt where any doubt lies.22
1.18
It is not normal practice for the sentencing judge to question the jury so as to clarify the basis upon which it arrived at its verdict, although some older authority exists for doing so in murder trials where a verdict of guilty of manslaughter is returned without the factual basis of the verdict being made apparent.23 In R v Solomon and Triumph,24 the extent to which it is permissible or desirable for a sentencer to question a jury about the basis on which it arrived at a particular verdict was considered. Beldam J concluded that it is generally undesirable to ask a jury to explain an otherwise ambiguous verdict,25 since the jury may not have been unanimous on the basis for the particular verdict although in agreement on the general verdict.26 A sensible precaution,27 however, where the trial is on a charge of murder, is for the trial judge to follow the procedure used in R v Frankum.28 In that case the jury was directed, (prior to reaching its verdict), that if it found the appellant guilty of manslaughter instead of murder, it would be asked to indicate whether the abnormality arose as a result of inherent causes or as the result of the effects of drugs, or both; if the diminished responsibility arose from the effects of a drug
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=8 |
then imprisonment would probably not be appropriate. The jury returned a verdict of guilty of manslaughter on the grounds of diminished responsibility arising out of inherent causes. The defendant was sentenced to life imprisonment, and on appeal tendered medical evidence which tended to support the claim that it was the effects of a drug which caused the abnormality. The Court of Appeal held, however, that the fresh evidence did not justify the court in reaching a conclusion different to that of the jury.
1.19
The prosecution will then present to the court evidence of the offender's antecedents (criminal record) and character.29. It is normal practice for the prosecution to call a witness, usually a Garda officer, to given sworn evidence of the offender's age, domestic and family circumstances, education, employment, previous convictions, date of arrest, and whether he or she has been on bail.
1.20
Where previous convictions are to be relied upon they must be either:
|
In respect of each and every alleged conviction, the offender should have been given an opportunity of admitting or denying it before putting the information to the court.31 In respect of any conviction disputed by the offender, proper evidence such as the court order of the previous conviction would be required to be presented to the court, and the defendant allowed an opportunity to controvert that evidence.32 Hearsay evidence, such as a copy of the Garda criminal history record, would not be sufficient to prove convictions in dispute.33 In respect of convictions not in dispute, however, a copy of the Garda record will suffice.34
1.21
There is no hard and fast rule as to what constitutes evidence of character at the sentencing stage, but generally included are personal details such as age, family background, education and work record, and other details such as income and personal situation since arrest, including whether or not the offender was on bail or in custody.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=9 |
1.22
The rules of evidence are relaxed in relation to character evidence, so that hearsay evidence may be relied upon. In The State (Stanbridge) v Mahon35 Gannon J quoted from a judgment of the English Court of Criminal Appeal delivered by Goddard LCJ in R v Marquis:36
The other thing to which I desire to call attention is that the learned Recorder seems to have had some doubt whether he could accept what he called 'hearsay evidence' of character after conviction ... It would be a very unfortunate thing if evidence of that kind could not be given, because it would prevent evidence from being given in favour of the prisoner, and would prevent a police officer from saying: 'I have made inquiries of the prisoner's employer, he works well and his character is good'. After conviction, any information which can be put before the Court can be put before it in any manner which the Court will accept. |
1.23
It is generally accepted that the role of the prosecution in sentencing is to provide the court with information not to seek to influence the court's sentencing decision in any way.37 However, a problem which may occur when evidence of antecedents is being given by prosecution counsel or a Garda officer is that damaging general remarks about the defendant's character, which are not capable of substantiation, are made, having the effect of damning the offender in the eyes of the court. For example, the officer may state that the defendant associates with known criminals or is known to the police (i.e. he has often been in trouble with the police) or even that there is a lot of this type of crime in the locality. These types of remarks can be seen as attempts by the prosecution to influence the decisions of the sentencing court.
1.24
English precedent may again prove persuasive here. In R v Van Pelz, evidence was given that the appellant was a prostitute who was an adventuress ... a very dangerous woman ... completely unscrupulous. Caldecote CJ held that a police witness should not be allowed to make allegations which are incapable of proof and which he has reason to think will be denied by the prisoner.38 The present English rule is that witnesses should confine themselves to the details of the antecedents, and any adverse comments should be contained in the antecedents form.39 Any such adverse evidence should not be given as part of the antecedents unless it is first hand information about which the officer giving the information can be questioned.40 There is no Irish authority on the matter.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=10 |
1.25
At this stage of the hearing, the court will consider any reports which it has requested or ordered. These will have taken time to prepare, so an adjournment will invariably have been required for this purpose.
1.26
The social inquiry report is prepared by the Probation and Welfare Service. If the offender is already on probation, it is likely that his supervising officer will prepare the report if not, the offender will be assigned an officer to interview him and make appropriate inquiries into the offender's domestic situation and social background. As well as outlining the offender's attitudes and responses to the offence, the report evaluates how further crime may be avoided and what services and forms of intervention can be utilised towards this end. Following this analysis, a supervision programme may be proposed (if considered feasible) which will both continuously monitor the behaviour of the offender and involve him or her in a constructive use of time through availing of community resources. Recommendations can then be made to the court concerning what type of supervision would underpin such a programme as well as the terms and conditions of sentence that would be appropriate in the particular case.41 The Probation officer's recommendations will be based on his or her assessment of the offender's likely reaction to a particular sentence. The court, however, is not bound to accept the officer's recommendations as it will have other factors to take into account, such as the public interest.42
1.27
There is only one situation in which such a report is a prerequisite, that is prior to the making of a community service order.43 However there are certain types of order, such as adjourned supervision,44 or orders under s28 of the Misuse of Drugs Act, 1977,45 which cannot be made without consultation with the Probation and Welfare Service in effect requiring a social inquiry report.
1.28
The social inquiry report is accorded some degree of confidentiality in that it is not read aloud in court. However, whereas in England the prosecution is never allowed to see the contents of the report, in Ireland it is not uncommon for the prosecution to be given a copy of the report to peruse.46 The defence will, of course, be given a copy to read, and will have opportunity to question the probation officer in court if any matter contained in the report requires clarification, or if a dispute arises.47 Of necessity, this requires that the report
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=11 |
be presented to the judge in open court in the presence of the accused.48
1.29
If the court is of the opinion that an inquiry ought to be made into the physical or mental condition of the offender then it may adjourn49 to enable a medical examination and report to be made.
1.30
It used to be that such reports had to be furnished in respect of all offenders under certain sections of the Misuse of Drugs Act, 1977,50 but this is no longer the case.51 However, the extended sentencing powers52 under that Act are only exercisable upon consideration of a medical report and social inquiry report, so a medical report will be required if the court considers that one of these extended penalties is viable option. The reports will be prepared by a health board, Probation and Welfare officer or other body or person, considered by the court to be appropriate.53
1.31
If the defendant has served a custodial sentence, a report from that institution will be available to the court. Likewise, if the defendant has served a term of community service, the court may request a report from the Probation and Welfare officer responsible for the supervision of the particular scheme. Such reports will outline how the defendant responded to the particular regime, if he failed to respond, or if any problems arose. Very often these reports will already have been used by the probation officer when preparing a social inquiry report.
1.32
The prosecution having outlined the facts of the offending behaviour and the character and circumstances of the accused, and all disputes in relation to the foregoing having been made known to the court, the defence now has a duty to address the court by way of a plea in mitigation. Despite the reference to 'mitigation' in the name of the plea, the defence, in making the plea, is not limited to factors relevant solely to the mitigation decision,54 and may raise matters relevant to the decision as to which approach the court should adopt in determining sentence.55
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=12 |
1.33
There is no defined or exclusive list of matters which are relevant to the mitigation decision, or to the sentencer's choice of approach for determining sentence (an infinite variety is thought to exist56). Thus, the defence will be left to rely on its own ingenuity and experience when deciding what factors to raise during the plea in mitigation. It is far from unlikely that the defence will from time to time overlook a factor which the trial judge would have found persuasive; or, alternatively, that the defence will burden the court with a large range of factors, only some of which in the event will prove to be relevant. It appears, however, that the sentencing judge should permit the defence an opportunity to do so,57 listening patiently and not interrupting, even if the defence has earlier put forward a lying defence.58
1.34
Boyle and Allen give the following list of factors commonly raised by the defence during the plea in mitigation:59
|
1.35
Where appropriate, the offender may be called to the stand to give evidence, particularly if his or her bearing, personality and desire for reform are likely to impress the court. It is clear that the likelihood of reform is not a factor relevant to mitigation; but it is of crucial importance in determining the correct
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=13 |
approach to adopt when sentencing. In The People (DPP) v Conroy (No 2)60 Finlay CJ said of the likelihood of reform:
Such evidence could never be in mitigation of the crime but could be a ground for supposing that there was a reasonable chance that he could be rehabilitated provided he was induced by the length of his sentence to have an expectation of eventually returning to ordinary society.61 |
1.36
The defence may present, if appropriate, character evidence as part of the plea in mitigation, and may call character witnesses such as the local priest, youth club leader, school teacher, or employer (particularly if the employer is willing to keep the offender in his or her employ).
1.37
At this stage, the defence may also wish to have other charges taken into consideration to which the offender has pleaded guilty. The Court may then take them into consideration at its discretion.62
1.38
The sentencing decision is essentially a matter for the judge, not for the jury, and while it is permissible for the jury to offer a rider to its verdict, such as a recommendation that mercy be shown, the judge is in no way bound by it.63
1.39
As to the procedure to be followed at the sentencing hearing, there is little in the way of legislative or judicial ruling on the decisions which must be made by the sentencing judge.64 Cryptic guidance is to be found, however, in various judicial pronouncements to the effect that the sentence to be imposed must not only be appropriate to the particular circumstances of each case, but also to the particular offender.65
1.40
Of course, it is not possible to say with precision what goes on in the mind of every sentencer when choosing a sentence appropriate to the characteristics of both the particular offender and offence. The judicial reluctance to state reasons for choice of sentence does not help us in our analysis.66 However it is possible to identify some of the various decisions which may be made by sentencers in coming to a final conclusion. Thus, during the 1970s in England, Thomas was able to construct a three stage decision model generally followed by the English Court of Appeal and the lower courts in
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=14 |
determining sentence.67 Thomas's analysis was accepted by the English courts as being accurate, and in the twenty one years that have followed, has been accepted as an authority on the matter. Our examination of Irish sentencing decisions suggests that Irish sentencers follow a broadly similar pattern in making their decisions. The Irish pattern may be outlined as follows:
|
1.41
The first task of the sentencing judge is to determine the factual basis of the offence upon which to assess the appropriate sentence. A principle of fundamental importance in determining the factual basis upon which to assess the appropriate sentence is expressed in the ancient maxim nulla poena sine lege, i.e. no one is to be punished on a charge for which they have not been tried and found guilty. In The People (Attorney General) v O'Callaghan,68 Walsh J gave this the weight of a constitutional prescript:
In this country it would be quite contrary to the concept of personal liberty enshrined in the Constitution that any person should be punished in respect of any matter upon which he has not been convicted.69 |
1.42
Thus, the sentencing judge must sentence only on the facts supporting the offence in hand, and must ignore any other evidence which would tend to
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=15 |
support the commission of other or more severe offences. English case law has recently produced a number of subsidiary principles based on the principle of nulla poena which, because they share the same foundation, may be considered a fortiori declaratory of Irish law. They can be summarised as follows:
|
1.43
The second task of the sentencing judge is to choose the appropriate penalty based on the facts of the case. It is rare that the sentence for an offence is fixed by law.78 The sentencer must, thus, be aware of his or her sentencing options and any legal restrictions which apply to them, such as the statutory maxima which govern the sentence for that particular offence, the limits on the jurisdiction of his or her court, or the separate provisions for young offenders or drug abusers.79 But within this framework there is a considerable degree of discretion for sentencers in choosing sentence in individual cases.
1.44
Making this choice is a two stage process. The first stage involves
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=17 |
choosing the correct principle or approach to adopt in the instant case according to the particular characteristics of the offender and offence. This is decided by reference to the traditional objects or purposes of sentencing.80 The second stage then involves choosing the particular penalty or measure appropriate to the offender by reference to the approach adopted in the first stage.
1.45
The primary decision the sentencer has to make is to choose which approach to adopt in sentencing the particular offender. Traditionally, there have been four approaches to the sentencing of offenders, corresponding to the four traditional objects or purposes of sentencing, namely retribution, rehabilitation, deterrence or incapacitation, i.e. the offender should be punished for crime; the offender should be given an opportunity to mend his or her ways; the offender and others should be deterred from committing similar crimes in the future; and the offender should, if necessary, be prevented from repeating his or her crime.81 Of these four, only the first three have been expressly favoured by the Irish courts. In The State (Stanbridge) v Mahon82 Gannon J said:
The first consideration in determining sentence is the public interest, which is served not merely by punishing the offender and showing a deterrent to others but also by affording a compelling inducement and an opportunity to the offender to reform. |
1.46
Thus the sentencing judge must decide whether to impose a sentence of sufficient severity to punish the offender, or of such severity so as to deter the offender and others from committing similar offences in the future, or, alternatively, to choose an individualised measure, i.e. a sentence based not on the severity of the offending behaviour but on the individual needs of the offender; i.e. a sentence likely to reform the offender.
1.47
There is no clear legislative or judicial policy which governs how the sentencing judge will decide which approach to adopt. The decision represents what the Victorian Court of Criminal Appeal described as an instinctive synthesis83 of all the various aspects of the offending behaviour and the circumstances of the offender.
1.48
This lack of coherent policy has a perplexing consequence for the sentencing judge. The problem is that there are a number of competing objects which are used to determine the sentence which may be imposed, and these approaches frequently conflict. For example, a sentencing judge when faced with
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=18 |
a young addict who is caught peddling drugs to feed his or her habit might rationally decide to impose a lengthy prison sentence to deter, although the sentencer may as easily decide to impose a short sentence in the interests of rehabilitating the offender. Ultimately a choice has to be made to follow one object the expense of another, yet, when faced with conflicting principles, sentencers have no principle to guide them:
Nothing tells us, however, when or whether any of these several goals are to be sought, or how to resolve such evident conflicts as that likely to arise in the effort to punish and rehabilitate all at once.84 |
1.49
In this jurisdiction, Walsh J gave some general guidance to assist sentencers by favouring rehabilitation as the most positive aim. In The People (AG) v O'Driscoll, he said:
The objects of passing sentence are not merely to deter the particular criminal from committing a crime again but to induce him as far as possible to turn from a criminal to an honest life and indeed the public interest would be best served if the criminal could be induced to take the latter course.85 |
1.50
However, even though it would seem from this that sentencers should generally favour a rehabilitative approach, it is not clear when such an approach would be inappropriate and a different approach more appropriate. Some small amount of guidance may be divined from decided cases, but, since the decision represents an instinctive synthesis, sentencers are by no means bound by decided examples, and are free to adopt any approach they wish.
1.51
In O'Driscoll, a rehabilitative approach was appropriate where the offence was the offenders' first crime of violence. Recently, in The People (DPP) v Conroy (No 2)86 a rehabilitative approach was found to be appropriate where the high standard of behaviour on the part of the appellant while on remand in custody could be a ground for supposing that there was a reasonable chance of reform.
1.52
One's bearing in court may be accepted as an important indicator as to the likelihood of reform.87 However a rehabilitative approach may not be appropriate where the offender has not availed of an opportunity to reform under a prior sentence, e.g. where he or she has committed a further offence while on probation.88
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=19 |
1.53
Also, as Finlay CJ noted in The People (DPP) v Tiernan:
an admission of guilt may, depending upon the circumstances under which it is made and the extent of the evidence apparent to an accused person as being available against him, also be taken in some circumstances as an indication of remorse and therefore as a ground for a judge imposing sentence to have some expectation that if restored to society, even after a lengthy sentence, that the accused may possibly be rehabilitated into it.89 |
1.54
Rehabilitative considerations commonly lead the sentencer to impose a reduced sentence. However, since a rehabilitative approach involves an attempt by the sentencer to find a sentence which is most likely to induce reform, a rehabilitative sentence may sometimes appear to be more severe than a sentence imposed following some other approach. In J v District Justice Sean Delap90 the applicant was applying to the High Court for judicial review of a sentence of detention in a reformatory school for a term in excess of three years in length. The District Justice who tried the case had done so upon summary conviction of the applicant, i.e. for a minor offence; despite the fact that the Supreme Court had previously held that an offence carrying a sentence of three years detention in St Patrick's Institution (which is not a reformatory school) could never be considered minor nor tried summarily.91 Barr J in the High Court held, however, that since the object of a period of detention in reformatory school was the rehabilitation of the offender, and not the punishment of the offender, the offence was legitimately tried summarily as a minor offence. He said:
An obligation to remain at a place for the education and training of young offenders does not, in my view, convert a school into a penal institution analogous to a prison, nor ought the period of education and training which a young offender spends there be regarded as a period of imprisonment in the penal sense of that term. I accept that such detention has in it an element of punishment, but its primary purpose is educational and, most importantly, the period of detention is in the main related to the function of the school as a place of instruction and correction. The duration of a prison sentence on the other hand is primarily related to the gravity of the offence which gave rise to it and the character of the convict.92 |
1.55
For some offences, a deterrent sentence may be more appropriate; in
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=20 |
The People (DPP) v Preston93 it was recognised that it is important in sentencing under the Misuse of Drugs Acts that penalties of a deterrent nature be imposed to display society's revulsion at drug abuse and drug trafficking. Similar considerations apply to offences of possession of controlled substances.94 It is clear that public opinion has a large role to play in the decision to impose a deterrent sentence. In The People (AG) v Buckley95 Maguire CJ said of the offences of house breaking, larceny and malicious damage:
There is much disturbance in the public mind at present about such offences and I would not like it to be thought that this court would deal leniently with them. |
1.56
Where the offender shows no likelihood of reform, and a deterrent sentence is not appropriate, the correct approach may be to impose on the offender a sentence appropriate to his degree of guilt,96 in other words, a sentence which is proportionate to the seriousness of the offending behaviour by reference to the retributive principle of desert the offender gets the sentence he or she deserves.97 In The People (AG) v Giles,98 the appellant was sentenced to six years imprisonment for conspiracy to rob. The Supreme Court held that despite the rule of general practice not to award a period of imprisonment greater than the substantive offence would carry if the accused had been convicted of that, a retributive sentence was appropriate, Walsh J saying:
In my view the sentence imposed by the learned trial judge in the present case was a very proper one, having regard to the seriousness of the offence, and was a lawful sentence.99 |
1.57
Having adopted the most suitable approach with regard to the circumstances of the offence and the characteristics of the offender, the sentencer will apply the principles appropriate to that approach to determine the precise penalty or measure which is to be imposed on the offender. As we shall see, only the most general body of such principles exists.100 However, it is clear that the general principles of each approach differ considerably, depending on the approach taken. For example, the application of retributive principles
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=21 |
requires the sentencer to find the sentence which most accurately reflects the offender's culpability.101 Mitigating circumstances may be taken into consideration in reducing the severity of such a sentence. Also, because the retributive approach relies heavily on the theory of desert, the sentence imposed should not be more severe than that which the offender deserves.102 On the other hand, rehabilitative principles require the sentencer to find the measure which will most likely induce the offender to reform.103 Thus, the gravity of the offending behaviour is irrelevant to such an approach, and the sentence will reflect an assessment of the probable future conduct of the offender and his likely response to various measures.104 Finally, deterrent sentences reflect neither the gravity of the offending behaviour nor the characteristics of the offender, but rather, they depend on an assessment of the likelihood of the offender and others committing further similar offences.105
1.58
It follows that a sentence which would be considered inappropriate as an application of the principles of one approach may be considered entirely correct when seen in terms of another approach. This is clearly illustrated in cases concerning co-accused, who although of equal complicity in the offending behaviour, receive significantly different sentences.
1.59
In The People (AG) v Poyning,106 the appellant was arraigned in the Circuit Court in Cork on a number of counts relating to an armed robbery. He pleaded guilty and was sentenced to four years penal servitude on the first count (armed robbery), 12 months imprisonment on the second (conspiracy) and to six months imprisonment on the fifth (taking a vehicle without authority); the prosecution having entered a nolle prosequi in respect of counts 3 and 4. Two other men, Motherway and Twomey, were also indicted but their trial was transferred to the Central Criminal Court where each pleaded guilty and was sentenced to six years penal servitude suspended upon each prisoner entering into a bond to keep the peace for five years, and each was then released. The appellant appealed to the Court of Criminal Appeal on the grounds that there was a gross inequality of treatment of himself as compared to the other two accused in a case in which the circumstances indicated that he was no more culpable than the other two and his previous record was no worse.
1.60
However, the Court of Criminal Appeal could not justify altering the sentences on those grounds; Walsh J said:
When two persons are convicted together of a crime or of a series of crimes in which they have been acting in concert, it may be (and very often is) right to discriminate between the two and to be lenient to the one and not to the other. The background, antecedents and character |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=22 |
of the one and his whole bearing in court may indicate a chance of reform if leniency is extended; whereas it may seem that only a severe sentence is likely to serve the public interest in the case of the other, having regard both to the deterring effect and the inducement to turn from a criminal to an honest life. When two prisoners have been jointly indicted and convicted and one of them receives a light sentence, or none at all, it does not follow that a severe sentence on the other must be unjust. If in any particular case one of such joint accused has received too short a sentence, that is not per se a ground on which this court would necessarily interfere with the longer sentence. Of course, in any particular case the court must examine the disparity in sentences where, if all other things were equal, the sentences should be the same; it must examine whether the differentiation is justified. The court, in considering the principles which should inform a judge's mind when imposing sentence and having regard to the character and antecedents of the convicted persons, will seek to discover whether the discrimination was based on those differences.107 |
1.61
The fallacy of this neat explanation of differing treatment of offenders is that there is no uniform set of principles or policies which the appellate court may refer to in considering the 'factors which should influence a judge's mind' when imposing sentence, having regard to the character and antecedents of the offender.108 Almost any approach may be justified by reference to some or other characteristic of the character and antecedents of the offender since there is no uniform consensus on the weight which should be given to one factor or the other. The problems of this incoherence, as we shall see109 are profound. Justice and equality of treatment require sentencers to adopt a uniform system for choosing the approach to be adopted,110 but such uniformity is sadly lacking in Irish sentencing practice. Thus reform of this area should strive to inject coherence and uniformity into choice of approach in sentencing.
1.62
How the sentencer, having decided upon the correct approach to adopt in the particular circumstances, decides upon the appropriate penalty or measure to impose belongs to the realms of mystery. It is trite to say that the sentencer, following a retributive approach, will impose a sentence which punishes the offender; or, if a rehabilitative approach is adopted, that the sentencer will impose a sentence likely to induce reform. There is no formal 'scale' or 'tariff' of sentences from which a sentencer can choose the appropriate penalty or measure, although there is some evidence that sentencers occasionally construct
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=23 |
their own personal informal tariffs or 'rules of thumb'.111 What is unclear, therefore, is how the sentencer decides that a particular penalty or measure will achieve chosen objects.
1.63
One practice which is discernible, however, is that of sentencers considering those factors which aggravate or mitigate112 the seriousness of the offending behaviour. In finding a sentence which appropriately corresponds to the seriousness of the offence under consideration, it appears that the sentencer will, not uncommonly, begin by determining the sentence which is appropriate to the ordinary circumstances of that offence in general e.g. if the offence is one of assault occasioning actual bodily harm, then the court may determine the sentence appropriate to an assault occasioning what it perceives as the ordinary or usual consequences of actual bodily harm committed with full intention to commit such harm. The courts have given on occasion some indication of the relative seriousness of various types of offence.113 Following this, the sentencer then considers those elements of the particular offence which aggravate or mitigate its seriousness in comparison to the usual offence: such as the extra harmful consequences (aggravating) or the recklessness, as opposed to specific intent, of the offender (mitigating). The sentencer then adjusts the sentence for the ordinary offence to suit the specific circumstances of the instant case.
1.64
A useful illustration of this practice in operation is to be found in the judgment of Finlay CJ in The People (DPP) v Tiernan.114 The appellant was one of three men who forcibly entered a car where the complainant was in the company of her boyfriend. They locked the boyfriend into the boot of the car; took the complainant to a nearby field where two of them raped her; and subjected her to other sexual assaults. The appellant was convicted and sentenced on a charge of rape, for which he received a twenty-one year sentence, and against which he appealed. In the course of his judgment, Finlay CJ followed the practice outlined above. He began by considering the nature of the crime of rape, its consequences, and the appropriate sentence for the commission of the offence without aggravating or mitigating factors: the bodily harm to the victim; the psychological, psychiatric and emotional distress which would ensue; the distortion of the victim's approach to her own sexuality; and the possibility of unwanted pregnancy. He concluded:
All these features, which I mention in summary and not as an attempted comprehensive account of the character of rape, apply even when it is committed without any aggravating circumstance. They are of such a nature as to make the appropriate sentence for any such rape a |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=24 |
substantial immediate period of detention or imprisonment.115 |
1.65
The learned Chief Justice then went on to consider those factors of the appellant's conduct which aggravated or mitigated the seriousness of the instant offence:
Unfortunately, the facts of the rape to which this appellant has pleaded guilty contain very many aggravating circumstances. They are:
|
He continued:
The mitigating circumstances in rape are indeed limited. The only single mitigating circumstance which arises in this case, I am satisfied, is the fact that when interviewed by the Garda Sνochαna the appellant immediately admitted his complicity in the crime and made a full statement. His attitude at that time was followed by a plea of guilty I have no doubt, however, that in the case of rape an admission made at an early stage in the investigation of the crime which is followed by |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=25 |
a plea of guilty can be a significant mitigating factor. I emphasise the admission of guilt at an early stage because if that is followed with a plea of guilty it necessarily makes it possible for the unfortunate victim to have early assurance that she will not be put through the additional suffering of having to describe in detail her rape and face the ordeal of cross-examination.117 |
1.66
The Chief Justice then considered the sentence appropriate to the circumstances of the appellant's case. He concluded:
I would have little hesitation in upholding a sentence of twenty-one years on the facts of this case had this appellant put the victim to trial and to the ordeal of giving evidence. When he did not, under circumstances from which it is possible to infer that he might have had some chance of escaping conviction for want of identification on a trial, it seems to me that the sentence is excessive. In these circumstances I would allow this appeal on the basis that the appropriate sentence for the offence in this case is seventeen years' penal servitude.118 |
1.67
What is clear, however, is that there is little in the way of legislative or judicial guidance to assist the sentencer in finding the appropriate sentence. As we shall see, the maximum penalties for most offences are far more severe than would be required in general,119 so they provide little practical guidance to the sentencer as to how serious an offence should be viewed when he is imposing a retributive sentence (i.e. a sentence proportionate to the seriousness of the offence). Yet maximum penalties are the only form of legislative guidance available to sentencers there exist no statutory provisions which indicate how a suitable rehabilitative or deterrent sentence should be found. It has been observed that:
The statutes granting such powers characteristically say nothing about the factors to be weighed in moving to either end of the spectrum or to some place between.120 |
1.68
This predicament is exacerbated by the paucity of reported judicial decisions and precedents which are available in this area. But even decided examples are of little help. To begin with, the concurrent jurisdiction of sentencers in the same courts means that a sentencer is free to disregard the decisions of his or her colleagues. But furthermore, even decisions of superior courts must be treated with caution, for as Finlay CJ noted in The People (DPP) v Tiernan:
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=26 |
having regard to the fundamental necessity for judges to impose a sentence which in their discretion appropriately meets all the particular circumstances of the case (and very few criminal cases are particularly similar) and the particular circumstances of the accused I doubt that it is appropriate for an appellate court to appear to be laying down any standardisation of tariff of penalty for cases.121 |
Thus, the sentencer receives little guidance from examples of previous choices made by other sentencers.
1.69
The sentencer, when applying a rehabilitative approach, may receive some assistance from the reports of Probation and Welfare officers, who, from their experience, may be able to suggest a sentence likely to induce reform. However such advice will be of little relevance to a retributive or deterrent approach.
1.70
It is far from clear what principles govern the choice of particular penalty or measure. The decision represents another instinctive synthesis122 of the offence, the characteristics of the offender, and the past experience of the sentencing judge. Here too, then, reform should strive to introduce coherence and uniformity to the principles which govern the choice of penalty or measure.
1.71
Mitigation refers to the process of making such allowance for mitigating factors as may be just by reducing the sentence level below the level appropriate to the facts of the particular offence committed by the offender.123 Mitigating factors are matters such as the character and history of the offender, the pressures which led to the commission of the offence and the consequences of conviction and sentence for the offender, rather than variations in the immediate circumstances of the offence, such as the value of the goods stolen, or the relationship between the offender and the victim.124
1.72
Mitigation in this context is to be distinguished from mitigation in the sense of making allowance for factors which reduce the seriousness of the offending behaviour125 the former we shall call mitigation of sentence, the latter mitigation of seriousness although the end result of both is a reduction in the severity of sentence. Factors which mitigate seriousness are those elements of the offending behaviour which are thought to reduce the seriousness of the particular conduct below the ordinary level of seriousness for that offence for example, the fact that the offender was less culpable because he was
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=27 |
provoked;126 or the fact that the harm caused by the offender was less than the ordinary consequences of that offence.127 Factors which mitigate sentence, on the other hand, are those characteristics of the offender which are thought to reduce the severity of the sentence merited by that offender below the level of sentence merited by the particular offending conduct for example, the fact that the offender has not exhausted all possible credit for previous good character;128 or the fact that the offender is a single parent and there is no other person to look after the child other than the offender.129 Factors which mitigate seriousness are, thus, not relevant to the determination of a rehabilitative sentence,130 which focuses on the likelihood of successful re-integration of the offender into society rather than on the circumstances of the offending conduct; conversely, factors which mitigate sentence are not strictly relevant to the determination of a retributive sentence which focuses on the seriousness of the offending behaviour rather than on the circumstances of the offender.131 The importance of this distinction will become clear later when we examine the merits of making one approach to sentencing paramount to the exclusion of the others: if, for example, a retributive approach is to be favoured in preference to a rehabilitative one, then there is a danger that some desirable factors which mitigate sentence might be excluded in the process.132
1.73
There is no exclusive list or defined principle determining the factors which are relevant to mitigation. An infinite variety appears to exist.133 Irish decisions do not generally make an express distinction between factors which mitigate seriousness and factors which mitigate sentence. Thus, in The People (DPP) v Maloney134 the Court of Criminal Appeal flatly rejected the argument that a plea of guilty by the accused automatically entitled him to a reduction in sentence on the grounds that the plea had been motivated by a hard headed tactical response to being apprehended red-handed rather than by a genuine feeling of remorse. Similarly, in The People (DPP) v Johnston,135 where the accused had denied complicity until told that a co-accused had implicated him whereupon he admitted guilt immediately, the Court of Criminal Appeal refused
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=28 |
to allow mitigation of sentence, stating that the plea was a business-like and hard-headed assessment of the situation in which the applicant was and was lacking in any sense of remorse. Decided examples of mitigating factors include an early admission of guilt in rape cases;136 being as helpful to the court as possible in cases of contempt;137 and evidence that the appearance of the girl led the offender to believe she was over seventeen years of age in cases of unlawful carnal knowledge of a girl under fifteen years of age.138 Also, in The People (DPP) v Maloney the court indicated that co-operation by an accused or convicted person with the police authorities in finding other persons who are involved in the crime may be a ground, and often is a ground, for imposing a more lenient sentence than would otherwise be appropriate.139
1.74
The practice of allowing a reduction in sentence on the basis that the offender shows a likelihood of successful integration into society must surely be flawed in this country. One imagines that a prisoner after 17 years of imprisonment has not got a much greater chance of re-integration into society than a prisoner who has served 21 yeas. In this context it is important to realise that imprisonment has very few, if any, positive effects,140 and that any significant sentence of imprisonment is almost certain to defeat the benefits which a reduction in sentence is thought to achieve. One may well ask if it is fair to allow a reduction at all if it rests on little more than a pious aspiration.141
1.75
It is not clear how the sentencer decides the particular amount by which to reduce sentence when mitigating factors exist. Thomas remarks that because mitigating factors rarely occur singly, and the weight of a combination of mitigating factors will usually be greater than the sum of their individual values considered separately, it is not possible to construct a negative tariff of mitigating factors showing that a particular factor will normally justify a reduction of a specified proportion of the notional level of sentence fixed by reference to the facts of the offence.142 All we can say, therefore, is that certain factors can be identified as mitigating factors likely to lead to some reduction in the overall severity of sentence.
1.76
A recent decision of the Central Criminal Court combined unusual examples of mitigating factors with sentencing specificity. Mr Justice Carney, imposing a sentence of three years penal servitude after a plea of guilty to incest, suspended two years of that sentence to make (his) disapproval of specific features of the prosecution. One year was suspended because, in the opinion of the judge, there was no evidential basis for the preferring of rape charges, which had earlier been dropped. The other year was suspended because the judge did not accept the explanation given by the DPP for a six month delay in
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=29 |
initiating charges (a)fter a complete confession had been obtained and a false allegation of rape had been cleared up.143
1.77
The decision as to the appropriate measure or penalty is characterised by a wide degree of discretion on the part of the sentencer in relation to both the nature and extent of the penalty or measure to be imposed.
1.78
Table A sets out the range of options as to the nature of sentence available to sentencers upon conviction.
1.79
The District Court also has a number of sentencing options available to it which may be imposed upon proof of guilt, but without the need for conviction. Table B sets out the options available to the District Court without conviction.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=30 |
TABLE A: OPTIONS UPON CONVICTION
Type |
Varieties |
Authority |
Jurisdiction |
A. Custodial |
1. Penal Servitude |
Statutory |
Higher Courts |
|
2. Imprisonment with hard labour |
Statutory |
Higher Courts |
|
3. Imprisonment simpliciter |
Common Law/statute |
All144 |
|
4. Detention |
Statutory |
All145 |
B. Suspended |
1. Bound by recognisances |
Judicial |
All |
|
2. Recognisance and conditions |
Judicial |
All |
C. Adjourned Sine Die |
|
No express Authority |
All |
D. Fine |
1. Generally |
Common Law/statute |
All146 |
|
2. With Imprisonment |
Statutory |
All147 |
E. Probation |
1. Recognisance |
P.O.A. 1907 s1(2) |
Higher Courts |
|
2. Supervised |
P.O.A. 1907 s2(1) |
Higher Courts |
F. Deferred Sentence |
|
No express Authority |
All |
G. Community Service |
|
Criminal Justice (C.S.) Act, 1983 |
All148 |
H. Medical Treatment |
1. Recognisance |
s28 M.O.D. Act, 1977 |
All |
|
2. Custody |
s28 M.O.D. Act, 1977 |
All |
I. Disqualification |
|
Statutory |
All |
J. Compensation |
|
P.O.A. 1907 |
All |
K. Charges considered |
|
s8 Criminal Justice Act, 1951 |
All |
L. Confiscation |
|
Statutory |
All |
M. Other options for Juveniles |
1. Reformatory School |
s58 Children Act, 1908 |
District Court |
|
2. Whipping149 |
s4(1) Summary Jurisdiction over Children (Ireland) Act, 1884 |
District Court |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=31 |
TABLE B: OPTIONS WITHOUT CONVICTION IN DISTRICT COURT
Type |
Varieties |
Authority |
E. Probation |
1. Dismissal |
P.O.A., 1907 |
|
2. Recognisances |
P.O.A., 1907 |
|
3. Recognisances and conditions |
P.O.A., 1907 |
|
4. Formal Probation |
P.O.A., 1907 |
K. Compensation |
|
P.O.A., 1907 |
M. Juveniles |
1. Care of Relative |
s58, Children Act, 1908 |
|
2. Industrial School |
s58, Children Act, 1908 |
|
3. Monetary Payment by Parent/Guardian |
s99, Children Act, 1908 |
|
4. Good Behaviour |
s99, Children Act, 1908 |
N. Adjourned Supervision |
|
No express Authority |
We shall now examine in more detail the law governing the imposition of these various sentencing options.
1.80
Convicted persons may be deprived of their liberty by being sentenced to penal servitude, imprisonment, or, in the case of certain young persons, detention.
1.81
Penal servitude was substituted for deportation to convict settlements in the British colonies after the abolition of slavery by section 2 of the Penal Servitude Act, 1857.
1.82
Section 2 of the Prisons (Ireland) Act, 1856, provided for the Minister for Justice to set apart certain places of confinement known as 'convict prisons' for prisoners serving a sentence of penal servitude, but no such order was ever made, so nowadays, for all practical purposes, there is no distinction in the treatment of prisoners sentenced to penal servitude and those sentenced to imprisonment.150 Penal servitude was abolished in England by the Criminal Justice Act, 1948, and the last Irish statute to prescribe a sentence of penal servitude was the Criminal Justice Act, 1964, s2.151
1.83
Penal servitude may only be imposed under statute, and in most cases
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=32 |
the particular statute will specify the maximum term which may be imposed. If not, the maximum term is to be five years, except for felonies created by statutes in force on 5th August 1891, for which the maximum term is to be seven years.152
1.84
A person undergoing penal servitude may not be elected to either House of the Oireachtas.153 Since penal servitude was introduced in direct substitution for the sentence of transportation, it cannot as such be imposed in a manner not applicable to transportation.154 Therefore unlike imprisonment, it cannot be ordered to commence at a date prior to the date on which sentence is pronounced.155 Bearing in mind that there is no difference in the treatment of offenders undergoing sentences of penal servitude and those serving terms of imprisonment, it is undesirable that these residual disqualifications for persons undergoing penal servitude should be retained. It may be suggested that penal servitude is to be considered a stronger punishment than imprisonment simpliciter, but the indications are that penal servitude is an anachronism and in that case, in the interests of fairness and consistency, penal servitude should be abolished in favour of imprisonment.
1.85
Imprisonment may be awarded in lieu of penal servitude for a term not exceeding two years, unless any act provides otherwise.156 Some older statutes provided for imprisonment with hard labour, and it has been held that in such cases, the maximum term is to be two years.157 Imprisonment with hard labour attracts many of the disqualifications which carried by penal servitude, and since the indications are that it too is a relic of bygone times, it may well be taken off the statute books.
1.86
Since 1964, imprisonment has been favoured over penal servitude and imprisonment with hard labour in statutes creating offences, and such statutes have stated the maximum158 term which may be prescribed. There was no limit at common law to the term of imprisonment which could be imposed, and that remains the case for all common law offences.159 However, the maximum sentence of imprisonment which may be imposed in the District Court is twelve months,160 except in certain circumstances governed by the Criminal Justice Act, 1984, in which a consecutive sentence may extend the aggregate sentence to a maximum of twenty four months. Section 102 of the Children Act, 1908, forbids sentencing persons under 17 years of age to penal servitude or imprisonment.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=33 |
However an exception to this exists in relation to young persons between the ages of fifteen years and seventeen years who are of so unruly a character or so depraved a character that they are not fit persons to be detained in special places for the detention of young persons.161 Under s5(1) of the Summary Jurisdiction Over Children (Ireland) Act, 1884 district judges are confined to sentencing young persons (between fifteen and seventeen years of age) convicted of an indictable offence to no more than three months imprisonment (with or without hard labour) following conviction of an indictable offence tried summarily.162
1.87
Detention in St Patrick's Institution163 may be prescribed against a juvenile offender between the ages of seventeen and twenty one in lieu of imprisonment. A young person between the ages of fifteen and seventeen may only be sent there in exceptional circumstances.164 A child between the ages of seven and fifteen may not be sentenced to a term in St Patrick's Institution, but may be sent to a reformatory or industrial school.165 In all of the cases set out above, detention is merely one option from a number of methods of sentencing young offenders, and the choice is at the discretion of the court.166
1.88
The Whitaker Committee of Inquiry into the Penal System noted that there exists an over-reliance on the use of imprisonment and custodial sanctions despite a general effort by the courts to use their imprisonment powers sparingly.167 The Committee found that imprisonment accounted for one-fifth of all sentences in the District Court, and about half of all sentences in the superior courts. Also noted was an increase in the average length of prison sentences since the 1970's, which was further facilitated by the increase in the sentencing powers of the District Court by sections 11 and 12 of the Criminal Justice Act, 1984.168 The Committee predicted that this combination of factors would lead to a prison crisis due to a rising prison population and overcrowding. The Annual Report on Prisons and Places of Detention, 1988 bears out these predictions:
The prisoner population has been increasing steadily in recent years with the result that considerable stress has been placed on available accommodation. The emergence in prisons of offenders with the HIV positive virus has also had to be dealt with within the limits of existing accommodation.169 |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=34 |
1.89
The Whitaker Committee felt that imprisonment should be imposed merely to deprive the prisoner of liberty, not to deprive him of any other rights, i.e. offenders are sent to prison as punishment, not for punishment:170
Nothing should be done to inflict hardship or punishment beyond that inevitably consequential on the deprivation of liberty involved in imprisonment.171 |
1.90
However, in reality, it appears that prison conditions and overcrowding make this an ideal beyond reach, and it is not inconceivable that prison conditions due to overcrowding could become so bad as to ground an action under Article 3 of the European Convention on Human Rights (i.e. inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment).172
1.91
With this in mind Ireland recently ratified the European Convention for the Prevention of Torture and Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment,173 which empowers an international committee of experts chosen among persons of high moral standing, known for their competence in the field of human rights or having professional experience in the areas covered by the Convention to visit any place of detention in the State. The Committee will draw up a detailed report on the conditions in the place of detention and transmit this to the Government with recommendations for improvement. If the State refuses to carry out the recommendations the Committee may make a public statement on the matter, with the aim, it seems, of embarrassing the Government into taking positive action.
1.92
Other international obligations include the UN International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights which provides in Article 10 that all persons deprived of their liberty
shall be treated with humanity and with respect for the inherent dignity of the human person.174 |
1.93
The impending accommodation difficulties coupled with the severe loss of liberty in forbidding surroundings,175 and the enormous cost of imprisonment to the State,176 all led the Whitaker Committee to conclude that
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=35 |
imprisonment should only be imposed as a last resort:
Broadly, the Committee's view is that imprisonment should be imposed only if the offence is such that no other form of penalty is appropriate ...177 |
1.94
To facilitate this move, the Committee recommended the extension and strengthening of existing forms of non-custodial sanctions. Imprisonment would only be imposed after consideration of a full personal report on the offender from the Probation and Welfare Service, supplemented, where appropriate, by a psychological and medical/psychiatric report,178 so as to be certain that no other penalty was appropriate.
1.95
A suspended sentence is imposed by prescribing a custodial sentence and then suspending its operation on condition that the offender enters into a recognisance, with or without sureties, to keep the peace and to be of good behaviour for a specified period. Further conditions may be imposed, at the court's discretion, such as an obligation to pay compensation, or to stay away from a certain person or place.
1.96
Unlike England, there is no statutory authority in Ireland for the suspension of prison sentence.179 However in The State (McIlhagga) v Governor of Portlaoise Prison, O Dαlαigh CJ declared that the suspended sentence had been long recognised as a valid and proper form of sentence.180 In fact, in People (DPP) v Dennigan,181 the Court of Criminal Appeal recognised a power to suspend even the consecutive sentences required by s11, Criminal Justice Act, 1984.
1.97
Sometimes the court may adjourn the matter of sentence for a certain time to allow the offender to show good behaviour, and then pass a derisory sentence. Alternatively, the court may remand the accused in custody prior to sentence in order to give him a taste of prison.182
1.98
The Whitaker Committee of Inquiry into the Penal System said of suspended sentences:
Suspended sentences are unsatisfactory as alternatives because they lack a clear status. There is no mechanism by which non-compliance with the court's conditions is automatically brought to the attention of the |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=36 |
court. The District Court Rules, moreover, effectively limit the period of a suspension to six months. If these defects were removed, a suspended sentence might, at the same time, be more acceptable to the judiciary and more obviously a penalty to those on whom it is imposed.183 |
1.99
The practice of adjourning indefinitely has been used by the Circuit Criminal Court to circumvent some of the restraints placed on it by the Probation of Offenders Act, 1907.184 In effect the case is completed although no formal disposal is indicated in the court records.
1.100
At common law, the court has discretion to impose fines upon conviction for any misdemeanour and there is no limit on the amount of the fine which may be imposed.185 In cases of felony the court has no such power except where the crime is manslaughter.186 Fines are normally provided for by statute, and many statutes provide for a higher amount to be imposed when conviction is on indictment. Statutes providing for the fining of offenders commonly state the maximum amount of the fine, and in most cases a fine or imprisonment or both may be imposed at the discretion of the court. The only guidance in the exercise of this discretion is to be found in the District Court Rules,187 which state that the means of the offender should be taken into account when determining the size of a fine. Default in the payment of a fine will incur imprisonment or detention, and the District Court Rules, 1948,188 set out the exchange rate between fines and prison sentences as follows:
For any penalty |
The imprisonment not to exceed |
|
not exceeding 10/- |
|
7 days |
exceeding 10/- |
but not exceeding £1 |
14 days |
exceeding £1 |
but not exceeding £2 |
One month |
exceeding £2 |
but not exceeding £5 |
Two months |
exceeding £5 |
but not exceeding £10 |
Three months |
exceeding £10 |
but not exceeding £30 |
Four months |
exceeding £30 |
|
Six months |
1.101
The law in relation to fines thus appears to be much in need of reform.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=37 |
Some of this has been dealt with in the Commission's Report on Indexation of Fines.189 The Whitaker Committee noted:
In the case of fines, the sentencing ranges available to the courts are frequently fixed in sums that are far below what would be regarded as reasonable at the present time .... Given the cost to the community of imprisonment, it would be sensible to remove from the offender the option of accepting prison and, wherever practical, to employ other means of enforcement, such as confiscation of property or attachment of income. |
1.102
Probation is governed by the Probation of Offenders Act, 1907. The Act invests in the court the discretion to discharge the offender conditionally upon entering into recognisances, with or without sureties, to be of good behaviour and to appear for sentence if called at any time during a nominated period not exceeding three years in length.190 In the exercise of this discretion the court is to have regard to the character, antecedents, age, health, or mental condition of the person charged, or to the trivial nature of the offence, or to the extenuating circumstances under which the offence was committed, and it must appear inexpedient to inflict any punishment or any other than a nominal punishment or expedient to release the offender on probation.191 The District Court is given discretion to dismiss the information or charge, or to release the offender on probation, and may do so at any time prior to or consequent upon conviction, provided it is satisfied that the charge is proved. Superior courts, on the other hand, do not have discretion to dismiss the information or charge, and may only use the Probation Act once a conviction has been obtained. However, the Circuit Criminal Court has circumvented this statutory limit by adjourning cases indefinitely.192
1.103
The court may also order the offender to pay damages for injury or compensation for loss, and to pay the costs of proceedings. The court is given the discretion to attach conditions to the recognisance that the offender be under the supervision of such person as may be named in the order during the period specified in the order and such other conditions for securing such supervision as may be specified in the order. Further conditions may be attached by virtue of s2(2), such as prohibiting the offender from associating with thieves and other undesirable persons, or from frequenting undesirable places; the abstention from intoxicating liquor, where the offence was drunkenness or an offence committed under the influence of drink; and generally for securing that the offender should lead an honest and industrious life.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=38 |
1.104
Failure to observe the conditions of a recognisance will lead to a warrant for arrest being issued against the offender. The Whitaker Committee of Inquiry into the Penal System recommended that failure to observe the conditions of a recognisance, or to find securities, should result in imprisonment in only the most serious cases. The 1907 Probation Act required revision, the Committee said, to reflect current court practices; the present range of non-custodial alternatives; and the recommendations of the Committee.193
1.105
The Act provides for the appointment of Probation Officers whose function is to monitor the progress of the offender on probation. The Probation Officer may apply to the court to vary the conditions of release contained in the recognisance and the court may do so if satisfied that the conduct of the offender has been such as to make further supervision unnecessary.194
1.106
The Court of Criminal Appeal has somewhat limited the discretion of the court in its application of the Probation Act. In The People v Buckley,195 Maguire CJ disapproved of repeated application of the Act to the same offender for serious offences, saying:
It is difficult to see why the Probation of Offenders Act was applied more than once, and if the framers of the Act were justified in allowing an opportunity to reform, and if, as in this case, an opportunity to reform was allowed, it was not availed of. That this opportunity should have been availed of is shown by the fact that these people come before the Court again. In such cases it is farcical that the Probation Act should be applied again. |
1.107
A deferral may occur where a person is sentenced to a custodial term but a warrant of custody is ordered not to issue for a specific length of time. If the defendant is of good behaviour during this period the sentence is deemed to have been administered; if not, the court retains the ability to enforce the penalty.196
1.108
The Criminal Justice (Community Service) Act, 1983 gives the court197 the discretion to make a community service order in respect of any offender over sixteen who has been convicted of an offence for which the appropriate sentence would otherwise be custodial. A community service order ('CSO') requires the offender to perform unpaid work for a specified number of hours between 40 and 240 hours. The court's discretion in this decision is guided by the provisions of
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=39 |
s4(1):
A court shall not make a community service order unless the following conditions have been complied with:
|
1.109
A Probation and Welfare Officer is responsible for the offender complying with the CSO. An offender who does not turn up for the work specified on the days agreed will then be brought before the courts. The judge may then activate a different form of sentence or fine the offender for not complying with the order.198
1.110
At present, community service is available only as an alternative to imprisonment for criminal offences, although there is much to be said in favour of extending it as an alternative to imprisonment for non-payment of fines or, indeed, non payment of compensation.199 The Whitaker Committee noted that there is much to recommend greater use of community service, and recommended that the progress of CSOs be carefully monitored to ensure that (a) the number of hours worked is a realistic alternative sanction, (b) the work arranged is both of benefit to the community and a positive experience for the offender, and (c) they are effective in keeping offenders out of crime for at least the period covered by the order. By doing so, the CSO would be easily accepted by the community and the judiciary as a valid sanction.
1.111
Section 28(1)(a) and (b) of the Misuse of Drugs Act, 1977 (as amended) allows the court, if having regard to the circumstances of the case the court thinks it appropriate to do so,200 to request a health board, probation and welfare officer or other body or person considered by the court to be appropriate to furnish the court with:
|
Having considered such reports the court may exercise the extended sentencing powers of section 28(2).
1.112
Section 28(2) provides that a court may substitute the following in lieu of other penalties available for the relevant offences:
|
1.113
The provisions of s28(2)(b) are in any case theoretical; the reality is that no custodial treatment centre yet exists. The nearest things are centres such as Coolmine, which are residential treatment centres attended on a voluntary basis.201
1.114
Another form of treatment is to be found in Section 26 of the Children Act, 1908 which empowers the court to order that a parent, who is convicted of certain offences under that Act and who is an habitual drunkard, be detained in a retreat. Again, there is not any centre for custodial treatment, although there are certain organisations which will help voluntary attenders, such as the Stanhope Street Clinic and the Rutland Centre.
1.115
Apart from these inept statutory provisions, the only course of action available to a sentencer who feels that an offender should receive psychiatric treatment is to sentence that person to custody with a recommendation that he be sent to the Central Mental Hospital. The Interdepartmental Committee on Mentally Ill and Maladjusted Persons observed:
... many persons are dealt with by the courts as 'normal' offenders who are either not responsible (or not fully responsible) for the conduct charged against them or who, even if fully responsible for such conduct, are in need of psychiatric or other special treatment. The inability, or |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=41 |
the restricted ability, of the courts to order that convicted persons receive appropriate psychiatric treatment is a grave defect in the present state of the criminal law.202 |
1.116
The Road Traffic Acts, 1961 to 1977 give the courts the power to disqualify an offender guilty of an offence under those Acts from holding a driving licence for such period as the court thinks fit. In all cases the disqualification is ancillary to some other form of penalty. In some cases such disqualification is mandatory, but for other offences the disqualification may be imposed at the discretion of the court. For such offences the Acts set out a minimum term of disqualification to guide the court. Section 27 of the 1961 Act empowers the court to disqualify a person from holding a driving licence if the person is convicted of any offence and used a motor vehicle in the course of commission of the offence. Such discretion may only be exercised upon hearing the appropriate evidence as a separate matter, and the disqualification should not be treated as the imposition of an additional punishment for an offence under the Act of 1961.203
1.117
Other forms of disqualification, such as disqualification from jury service204 or from becoming a director of a company,205 are consequential upon being convicted and receiving some other form of penalty.
1.118
An order to pay compensation can only be imposed with statutory authority at present as an ancillary order attached to a Probation Act disposal206, or an order for Community Service.207 The District Court is limited in the exercise of this discretion in that the maximum amount of compensation payable is fixed at £10, unless the specific enactments relating to the particular offence set a higher limit.208 A compensation order may also be made a condition of a suspended sentence, in which case it appears that there is no maximum limit on the amount of compensation payable, save in the District Court where the amount must not be so great as to bring the offence outside the minor offence category.209 The Whitaker Report recommends210 that
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=42 |
compensation be given a clear statutory basis in its own right. Such reforms in England have helped to give the penalty an independent standing, by relating the amount of compensation to the degree of injury inflicted.211
1.119
The Criminal Justice Bill, 1992, recently initiated, includes detailed provisions for the payment of compensation to any person convicted of an offence. Section 6 provides inter alia:
|
1.120
The court may, at its discretion, take other offences into consideration when passing sentence on a charge for which a conviction has been entered, provided the defendant pleads guilty to the other charges. S8 of the Criminal Justice Act, 1951 reads:
|
1.121
When a sentencer takes another offence into consideration it appears that he or she should pronounce the appropriate sentence for that offence as well as the sentence for the offence charged, and not simply include the sentence in the sentence for the offence charged.212
1.122
In England, where the practice of taking other offences into consideration has no statutory basis, the court cannot, in sentencing the offender, impose a sentence beyond the maximum allowed by law for the offence of which he stands convicted simply because other offences have been taken into consideration.213 In Ireland the provisions of section 8 cannot be applied where the offence of which the offender stands convicted carries a mandatory sentence;214 nor can they be relied upon where the court has no jurisdiction to try the offender on the offences admitted to, e.g. where a person convicted of a trifling road-traffic offence in the District Court seeks to invoke the section to have a murder taken into consideration.215
1.123
A number of statutes confer on the court the discretion to order the forfeiture of property connected with the commission of an offence.216
1.124
The Whitaker Committee saw much in favour of confiscation of the proceeds of crime for offences such as drug trafficking and white collar crime,
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=44 |
where offenders may profit substantially from their criminality and where the victim(s) cannot be identified:
It is unacceptable that offenders or their immediate families should be allowed to retain such ill-gotten gains, whether or not the offenders are given prison sentences. The courts should have the power and access to any financial advice needed to ensure the confiscation of assets of this kind.217 |
The Commission has examined this topic separately in its Report on Confiscation of the Proceeds of Crime.218
1.125
The courts are given enormous discretion in their choice of method for dealing with young offenders. A full list219 of the ways in which a child or young person may be dealt with is given in section 107 of the Children's Act, 1908, which provides:
Where a child or young person charged with any offence is tried by any Court, and the Court is satisfied of his guilt, the Court shall take into consideration the manner in which, under the provisions of this or any other Act enabling the court to deal with the case, the case should be dealt with, namely, whether (a) by dismissing the charge; or (b) by discharging the offender on his entering into a recognizance; or (c) by so discharging the offender and placing him under the supervision of a probation officer; or (d) by committing the offender to the care of a relative or other fit person; or (e) by sending the offender to a reformatory school; or (g) by ordering the offender to be whipped; or (h) by ordering the offender to pay a fine, damages, or costs; or (i) by ordering a parent or guardian of the offender to pay a fine, damages or costs; or (j) by ordering the parent or guardian of the offender to give security for his good behaviour; or (k) by committing the offender to custody in a place of detention provided under this Part of this Act; or (1) where the offender is a young person, by sentencing him to imprisonment; or (m) by dealing with the case in any other manner in which it may be legally dealt with; |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=45 |
Provided that nothing in this Section shall be construed as authorising the Court to deal with any case in any manner in which it could not deal with the case apart from this section. |
1.126
Section 107 is a consolidating section it does not legislate, but merely summarises the methods of dealing with young offenders which already exist elsewhere in the law. Thus in the case of certain methods, the court will be guided in the exercise of its discretion by the law in relation to the particular method, e.g: The Probation of Offenders, Act 1907 in relation to options (a) or (b) supra.220
1.127
The sentencing of youthful offenders is an area of the law much in need of comprehensive review; much greater, indeed, than that which can be efficiently and fairly conducted within the ambit of this report.221 Such analysis would most likely form part of an examination of the entire juvenile justice system, particularly when reforms in other jurisdictions have fundamentally questioned the need for any criminal stigma to attach to child offenders by introducing family involvement in reprimanding and dealing with such offenders. Suffice it to say that for the purposes of this analysis the methods of disposal of youthful offenders are so broad and varied that the court is vested with enormous discretion in the choice of method, although this discretion is commonly hampered as was reflected by the recent turn of events which led to the sentencing of fifteen year old girls to imprisonment by the corresponding lack of suitable alternative places of detention for such offenders.222
1.128
This occurs when a defendant is remanded on establishment of guilt and is placed under the supervision of a Probation and Welfare Officer. In effect, the offender is requested to co-operate with the Probation and Welfare Service. However the request cannot be enforced either by the court or the Probation Officer, and the practice has no statutory authority.223
1.129
When determining the extent of sentence, the courts are required to operate within certain parameters, i.e. (a) within the maximum, minimum or mandatory limits and (b) within the limits upon the jurisdiction of the particular court.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=46 |
1.130
The general rule of practice of the sentencing courts is that maximum sentences are reserved for only the most serious cases.224 It is very rarely that the maximum penalty is imposed in a case. Most statutes which create an offence will lay down a maximum penalty which may be imposed. At common law there is no limit to the term of imprisonment which may be imposed,225 however in the case of an offence such as attempt to commit, and normally in the case of conspiracy to commit, the term should not exceed the maximum term of penal servitude or imprisonment which might be imposed for the substantive offence.226 Also, there appears to be no limit on the size of a fine which the court may impose for a misdemeanour at common law.227 However a child is not to be fined more than £2, and a parent or guardian of a convicted child cannot be fined more than £10 in respect of the child's offence.228
1.131
Statutory minimum sentences are not a common feature of modern Irish criminal statutes although there have been occasions in the past when the legislature prescribed minimum sentences, usually because it was felt that sentencers might not take a sufficiently serious view of the offences.229 Generally, such minima were imposed in combination with a maximum, e.g. The Larceny Act, 1861 provided for terms of penal servitude for any term not exceeding seven years and not less than three years. However, it is also possible for the legislature to express sentences as minimum penalties without imposing a maximum. Another possibility is the combination of a life sentence with a minimum in which case it becomes an indeterminate sentence beyond a minimum base. A recent example of such a measure is contained in s4 of the Criminal Justice Act, 1990, which provides:
Where a person (other than a child or young person) is convicted of treason or of a murder or attempt to commit a murder to which section 3230 applies, the court
|
1.132
For some offences, statute deprives the court of all of its discretion in the determination of the extent of sentence e.g. murder, under the Criminal Justice Act, 1990, carries a mandatory sentence of life imprisonment.231 Mandatory sentences are rare, as Griffin J noted in DPP v Gray:232
Apart from revenue and excise offences and offences under the Customs Acts, there do not appear to be many offences in respect of which only one penalty may be imposed murder, capital murder and treason immediately come to mind. |
1.133
Mandatory imprisonment for a term of life is the sentence which is to be imposed for the latter, and there appear to be no other offences in respect of which a mandatory custodial sentence for a lesser term is to be imposed.
1.134
If an offender is found to have been insane at the time of commission of a treason, murder or felony, then the correct verdict is one of guilty but insane.233 However, it has been long accepted that such a verdict constitutes in law an acquittal despite the wording of the verdict.234 Thus, none of the sentencing alternatives described supra may be imposed. However the court may not discharge the accused it is obliged to order detention, both for the offender's good and the good of the public. The order of the court in such cases is, technically speaking, not a sentence, since there has been no finding of guilt. However, we will set it out here for the sake of completeness.
1.135
Where such verdict has been returned the court must make an order within the terms of section 2(2) of the Trial of Lunatics Act, 1883:
Where such special verdict is found the court shall order the accused to be kept in custody as a criminal lunatic in such place and such manner as the court shall direct235 till the pleasure of the Government |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=48 |
of Ireland shall be made known; and it shall be lawful for the Government of Ireland thereupon and from time to time to give such order for the safe custody of the said person during pleasure in such place and in such manner as to the Government of Ireland may seem fit. |
1.136
Until recently it had been common for the courts to order the accused to be detained until further order of this court.236 That practice was expressly disapproved of by the Supreme Court in Gallagher237 where it was held that the decision as to the release of an insane prisoner was a matter for the executive.238
1.137
The District Court has greater limits on its discretion in the determination of the extent of sentence than the superior courts. Generally, the maximum term of imprisonment which may be imposed by the District Court for any one offence is 12 months. However, in certain circumstances, a consecutive sentence extending the aggregate term to two years may be imposed under the provisions of sections 11 and 12 of the Criminal Justice Act, 1984. The maximum fine for indictable offences tried summarily by the District Court is set at £1,000 by section 17 of the Act.
1.138
These restrictions stem from the fact that the District Court is a court of summary jurisdiction, and may only try 'minor offences' fit to be tried summarily. The established test for distinguishing between minor offences and non-minor offences is the severity of punishment authorised to be imposed.239 Severity is gauged by reference to the loss of liberty or the intentional penal deprivation of property by means of fines or other direct means of deprivation.240 Therefore the court is not only limited in the length of custodial sentence or the amount of fine it may impose, but also in the amount it may confiscate.241
1.139
The Circuit Court, on the other hand, does not have such inherent limits
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=49 |
upon its sentencing jurisdiction, although at present the Circuit court cannot try offences of rape,242 treason, murder, piracy or genocide.243 Because of this wider jurisdiction, District Courts will commonly send forward to the Circuit Court persons who have pleaded guilty in that court and who the District Judge believes are charged with offences of such seriousness as to warrant more severe sentences than the sentencing restrictions of the District Court allow.244
1.140
The High Court, when it exercises its original criminal jurisdiction, is known as the Central Criminal Court,245 and at present has exclusive jurisdiction to try prosecutions for treason and related offences, murder and related offences, piracy, genocide, certain offences under the Offences Against the State Act, 1939, and certain sexual offences under the Criminal Law (Rape) (Amendment) Act, 1990. However, there is no constitutional prohibition against the legislature conferring exclusive jurisdiction to try indictable offences on the Circuit Court or District Court thereby depriving the High Court of authority to try those cases, so long as the High Court retains its supervisory jurisdiction over the lower courts.246
1.141
The Special Criminal Court was provided for by Part V of the Offences Against the State Act, 1939. It was established in August 1939 and remained in existence until 1962. It was re-established in 1972247 and has remained in existence since then. Its jurisdiction is generally exercised in respect of scheduled offences set out in the 1939 Act, i.e. all offences under the 1939 Act and all offences under the following: Malicious Damage Act, 1861; Explosive Substances Act, 1883; Firearms Acts, 19251971; and s7 of the Conspiracy and Protection of Property Act, 1875. The most severe sentence which may be imposed under these Acts is penal servitude for life. The Court also has jurisdiction to try any case which the Director of Public Prosecutions brings before it, certifying that, in his opinion, the ordinary courts are not adequate for trying the accused on the charge.248
1.142
From this discussion of the range of choice available to sentencers both as to the nature of sentence to be imposed and the extent of sentences imposed, it clearly emerges that there is little in the way of developed principles for the imposition of sentence, in the form of either legislative or judicial
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=50 |
pronouncements. Thomas gives a succinct summation:
Modern sentencing legislation, with few exceptions, confers extensive discretion on the sentencing judge, both in the range of punitive sentences which may be imposed and in the choice of alternative dispositions. Criminal statutes generally authorize terms of imprisonment far longer than are normally imposed in practice, and Parliament, in creating an increasing variety of non-custodial sentences, has generally been content to establish relatively broad conditions of eligibility without requiring sentencers to use particular measures in any specified class of case. With the exception of a few general indications of legislative preferences in the choice of sentences, statutes do not seek to influence the details of sentencing practice.249 |
1.143
Almost every type of sentence discussed above is, as we have seen, in need of some reform or other, and the legislative details of each give little more than the most general indication of the area of application of the given option. Thus, it is difficult in many cases to say whether a given set of options are simply alternatives to each other, (i.e. interchangeable) or whether each should be confined to a specific area of application.
1.144
The legislature's provision of penal policy in relation to the sentencing process shows itself to have been haphazard and to lack co-ordination.250 New measures which have been introduced have not been properly grounded in either penal theory or sentencing practice, and so no guidance can be given to the courts on the types of offence and offender for whom the measures might be appropriate.251 The great difficulty for the legislature, however, is that there is no uniform consensus on sentencing practice because there is no systematic policy which sentencers follow.
1.145
A court, when passing sentence on an offender is not required to give any reasons for its decision. Occasionally, however, the sentencer will indicate that certain factors of the offending behaviour or of the offender's character or antecedents led the court to choose a particular approach, be it retributive, rehabilitative or deterrent. For example, the sentencer may indicate that the offender's exemplary behaviour while in custody led the court to adopt a rehabilitative approach; or that the crime in question was so prevalent as to merit a deterrent approach.252 Rarely, if ever, however, does the court give its reasons for choosing a particular penalty or measure, beyond stating that it is
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=51 |
satisfied that the chosen penalty or measure is appropriate in the circumstances. Some understanding of the judicial reluctance to state reasons may be gained from the words of Mansfield LC (170593) who gave this general advice:253
Consider what you think justice requires and decide accordingly. But never give your reasons: for your judgment will probably be right but your reasons will certainly be wrong. |
1.146
Not surprisingly, however, such reluctance to state reasons has a number of unsatisfactory consequences which we will examine at a later stage.254
1.147
The Court is, however, obliged to ensure that the offender is given an opportunity to be made known of his obligations under the sentence. In The State (Kiernan) v de Burca255 a Circuit Court judge heard an appeal from the District Court. He affirmed the fine and expenses awarded by the District Judge but did not say anything about imprisonment if the fine was not paid. Provision for this was made subsequently by the County Registrar when drafting the order. Maguire CJ, delivering the unanimous opinion of the Supreme Court, said it was a fundamental rule that pronouncement of sentence following a conviction was an essential part of the administration of justice in the case. In Molloy v Sheehan256 the Supreme Court, referring to Kiernan's case, restated this fundamental rule as the sentence must be spoken in court.
1.148
Unless the Central Criminal Court otherwise directs, every order made by that court shall take effect from the date on which the order is made.257 Sentences imposed in the Circuit Court shall run from the date specified in the judge's order; if no date is specified the order is bad and may be quashed in judicial review proceedings.
1.149
A sentence of penal servitude may be ordered to take effect from the date on which sentence is pronounced, or at some time in futuro258 following the determination of a term of imprisonment or penal servitude;259 but cannot be ordered to take effect from a date prior to the pronouncement of sentence.260
1.150
Conversely, imprisonment can be ordered to take effect from a date prior to the pronouncement of sentence, and commonly is, to take account of the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=52 |
period of remand spent in custody pending trial and determination of sentence.
1.151
The question of whether custodial sentences should be ordered to run concurrently or consecutively can arise in a number of situations. The offender may have been convicted on a number of counts in the same indictment or at the same sittings; he may already be serving a sentence; or there may be a prior suspended sentence or conditional discharge which may have to be considered for activation. The general rule for imposition of concurrent sentences is that all sentences in respect of two or more offences committed in the course of a single transaction should be concurrent rather than consecutive.261 For example, in The State (Brien) v Kelly,262 where the accused pleaded guilty to five counts of rape, buggery, unlawful carnal knowledge, indecent assault and assault occasioning actual bodily harm, all of which related to the same person, place and occasion, the Supreme Court upheld the concurrent sentences of three years detention in respect of counts 1 and 2 and two years detention in respect of count 3 which were imposed by the Circuit Court. However, difficulty may often arise in establishing a sufficiently precise definition of whether or not the charges relate to a single transaction, and there appears to be no rule of law or practice which identifies the limits of the single transaction concept.263
1.152
When the offences arise out of the same transaction the sentencer should pronounce sentence individually for each offence and not merely take them all into consideration in determining the sentence for one. In The People (AG) v Higgins,264 the accused was charged on a number of counts arising out of the same incident but varying in seriousness. The trial judge imposed sentence on him in respect of one count, taking the others into consideration. In delivering the opinion of the Supreme Court, Finlay CJ said obiter:
Having regard to the possibility that always exists of a court of appeal setting aside on some technical or other ground the conviction an a particular count, but leaving undisturbed the convictions reached on other counts on the same indictment, even though they arise out of the same incident, this would appear to be an undesirable and unsatisfactory procedure. Appropriate sentence should, in my view, be imposed on all counts in respect of which an accused person is convicted by a jury. |
1.153
Where, however, the offences do not arise out of the same transaction the court has a discretion as to whether the sentences should be consecutive or concurrent. Where the offender is convicted of a subsequent offence whilst serving a sentence of imprisonment or penal servitude, he may be sentenced to a consecutive term of imprisonment or penal servitude to commence on the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=53 |
expiry of an existing term,265 even though the aggregate may exceed the maximum which may be imposed for either offence. A consecutive sentence is mandatory for offences committed while on bail.266
1.154
On the issue of concurrent and consecutive sentences, the English Court of Appeal has developed a principle known as the Totality Principle. The effect of the totality principle is to require a sentencer who has passed a series of sentences, each properly calculated in relation to the offence for which it is imposed and each properly made consecutive or concurrent in accordance with the single transaction rule, to review the aggregate sentence and consider whether it is just and appropriate.267 In R v French,268 Lane LCJ gave the following guidance:
We would emphasise that in the end, whether the sentences are made consecutive or concurrent, the sentencing judge should try to ensure that the totality of the sentences is correct in the light of all the circumstances of the case. |
1.155
In England, therefore, where the sentences are made consecutive, the final duty of the sentencer is to make sure that the totality of the consecutive sentences is not excessive.269 In the recent case of The People (DPP) v Healy,270 the Irish Court of Criminal Appeal appears to have approved of a similar approach being taken by Irish sentencers where consecutive sentences are concerned. The Court was considering the effect of section 11 of the Criminal Justice Act, 1984 which requires a consecutive sentence to be imposed for all offences committed while on bail. McCarthy J, for the Court, took the opportunity to indicate how section 11 should be approached:
In the application of s 11 of the Criminal Justice Act, 1984, the sentencing court should determine the sentence appropriate to the offence or offences on the indictment to which the section applies, without regard to the fact that it must be a consecutive sentence under the provisions of s11, and direct that such a sentence shall be consecutive on any sentence for a previous offence. That is not to say that, in a proper case, the sentencing court, in the case of grave offences, should not adjust the sentence downwards where not to do so would impose a manifestly unjust punishment on the accused. |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=54 |
1.156
An offender who is dissatisfied with the severity of a sentence imposed on him by the sentencing court may have a right of appeal to a superior court against sentence. A right of appeal may only be conferred by the Constitution or by statute271 and it may be noted at the outset that the prosecution has no statutory right to appeal a lenient sentence.
1.157
The appellate courts for criminal appeals in Ireland consist of:
|
1.158
It will be noted that a person convicted and sentenced in the Central Criminal Court has a choice of appealing to either the Court of Criminal Appeal or the Supreme Court; but having appealed to the one he cannot appeal to the other.273 The High Court may also hear appeals by way of case stated from the District Court once the District Judge has given his decision,274 and the Supreme Court may deal with appeals by way of case stated from the Circuit Court275 on matters pending in that court.
1.159
The right of appeal to the Circuit Court is conferred on the appellant as of right by statute.276 An appeal in the Circuit Court is a full re-trial (the judge sitting alone without a jury). Thus it has been held that the appeal cannot be against conviction only277 and the court may increase the sentence notwithstanding the fact that the appellant did not appeal against sentence.278 The Circuit Court will re-hear the case, both on the facts and the law, though in an appeal against sentence it will confine itself to the factors relevant to sentencing.279 The prosecution has no such right to appeal against conviction or sentence.280
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=55 |
1.160
A person convicted on indictment has no absolute right of appeal to the Court of Criminal Appeal against conviction or sentence: leave to appeal must first be obtained.281 Such leave may be granted by the trial judge, or, if the trial judge refuses, from the Court of Criminal Appeal by way of an application for leave to appeal.282 The grounds on which the accused seeks leave to appeal are generally substantially the same as those of the appeal, so the Court usually treats the preliminary application as the hearing of the appeal. This is particularly the case in appeals against sentence, so that such appeals are seldom the subject of considered judgments and the decisions are delivered extemporaneously. The judgment is pronounced by only one member of the three judge court, and unless the court otherwise directs, no judgment with respect to the determination of any question may be pronounced separately by any other member.283
1.161
Unlike appeals to the Circuit Court, an appeal to the Court of Criminal Appeal is heard on the basis of the transcript of evidence taken at the trial of the appellant, though the court may request a report from the trial judge as to his opinions, and may requisition the original indictment, depositions, exhibits and record from the trials book. Also, unlike an appeal to the Circuit Court, an appeal to the Court of Criminal Appeal may be against conviction only in which case the appellant is dominus litis and the court is not entitled to deal with sentence.284 It is only in appeals against sentence only or against conviction and sentence that the court may remit, reduce or increase or otherwise vary the sentence.285Ryan and Magee sum up the current situation in regard to appeals against sentence to the Court of Criminal Appeal thus:286
There are few reported decisions of the Irish courts dealing with the principles on which they will act in relation to appeals against sentence, since such appeals are seldom the subject of considered judgments. The Court of Criminal Appeal has, however, repeated, in line with its English counterpart, that it will not interfere with a sentence, even though the members of the Court might themselves have been more or less severe if dealing with the case themselves, unless the trial judge has erred in principle287 although in practice the Court may seem occasionally to make an exception to prove its rule. The fact that a co-accused may have received too lenient a sentence is not a ground for interfering with a sentence properly imposed on an appellant.288 The Court will, however, vary the sentence if the trial judge was not informed or |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=56 |
misinformed as to some material factor,289 and if there is merely a technical flaw in the sentence, the proper course is for the Court of Criminal Appeal to vary it, for example by substituting a sentence of imprisonment for one of penal servitude.290 |
In The People (DPP) v Michael Walsh,291 the Court of Criminal Appeal emphasised that there exists a clear division between the function of the court in revising sentence, which is to see if an error has occurred, and the function of the Executive in granting remission. Here, a plea for leniency and mercy for the applicant in all the circumstances that had happened since his imprisonment were matters appropriate to a petition to the Minister for Justice.
1.162
A person convicted and sentenced in the Central Criminal Court may appeal to the Supreme Court by virtue of Article 34.4.3 of the Constitution which provides that the Supreme Court shall, with such exceptions and subject to such regulations as may be prescribed by law, have appellate jurisdiction from all decisions of the High Court.292
1.163
The prosecution has a corresponding right of appeal to the Supreme Court, but the Supreme Court has held that in appeals against conviction it will not disturb a verdict properly arrived at and supported by evidence, such as an acquittal duly recorded by a jury on consideration of the evidence.293
1.164
Whether, in an appeal against sentence by the prosecution, the Supreme Court will disturb a sentence imposed by the Central Criminal Court thus giving the prosecution an effective right of appeal against leniency of sentence remains to be determined. However, some indication as to the likely response of the Supreme Court to such an appeal may be divined from the case of The People (DPP) v Quilligan and O'Reilly (No. 2),294 where a Supreme Court majority held that the jurisdiction to hear an appeal did not ipso facto carry with it the jurisdiction to order a re-trial, even though the trial judge had erred in law in directing an acquittal. The majority was persuaded by the fact that if a re-trial was ordered, the defendants could complain that they were not being treated equally with other persons whose acquittals had been appealed by the prosecution under the provisions of s34 of the Criminal Procedure Act, 1967, which allows for the prosecution to make a case stated without prejudice to the verdict. Also persuasive was the fact that the legislature had not conferred any
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=57 |
specific jurisdiction to order a re-trial on the Supreme Court.
1.165
It can be argued, thus, that the Supreme Court could adopt a similar non-interventionist approach to prosecution appeals against sentence. Indeed the whole tenor of the Supreme Court's rulings in Quilligan (No. 2) and in The People (DPP) v O'Shea295 would seem to suggest a dissatisfaction with the entire idea of prosecution appeals other than those which decide a point of law without disturbing the findings of the lower court. However, on a stricter reading of Quilligan (No. 2) it can be argued that, since there is no equivalent of s34 of the Criminal Procedure Act, 1967 in relation to sentence, there would be no reason for other defendants to complain that they were treated unequally, and consequently, the Supreme Court could safely disturb a sentence imposed by a lower court. Also, unlike Quilligan (No. 2) where there could be found no inherent or legislatively conferred jurisdiction to order a re-trial, the Supreme Court has inherent jurisdiction to disturb a sentence imposed by a lower court, and had done so in appeals against sentence by the defence.296 Finally, there would be less likelihood of the danger of double jeopardy, (a danger which the Supreme Court found persuasive in Quilligan (No. 2)), since, a review of sentence does not amount to a breach of the double jeopardy rule.297 This is an area, thus, which would benefit from some judicial or legislative statement.298
1.166
A sentence imposed by the Court of Criminal Appeal may be appealed to the Supreme Court if the Court of Criminal Appeal, the Attorney General or the DPP certifies that the decision involves a point of law of exceptional public importance.299 An example of such an appeal is the recent case of The People (DPP) v Tieman300 where the point of law of exceptional public importance was certified by the Attorney General to be the guidelines which the court should apply in imposing a sentence for rape. Although such appeals are technically by way of case stated, since the foundation for appeal is a point of law, the Supreme Court is not limited to the point of law certified as being of exceptional public importance, but may also consider other grounds of appeal.301
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=58 |
2.1
A sentencing policy may operate at any number of levels however, the most fundamental issues which a sentencing policy should at least address are:
|
2.2
It is central to a consistent and just sentencing system that a coherent sentencing policy on how the criminal justice system sentences offenders be clearly articulated, since sentencing policy governs the decisions made at two stages in the criminal process. In fact, the question of how offenders are to be sentenced is at the heart of the sentencing process and will receive the greater part of our attention in this paper. As we have seen,1 sentencing policy shapes the decisions made by the sentencing judge when choosing the approach to adopt in individual cases, which in turn affects both the nature and extent of the sentence imposed. Incoherence in policy governing these matters can lead to inconsistent sentencing decisions being made. Secondly, sentencing policy comes into play when the legislature is formulating penal policy such as deciding what type and amount of penalties to attach to newly created offences in criminal statutes, or creating new forms of penalty or sentencing alternatives for the courts to implement. The introduction of new measures can be effectively set at nought by the judiciary if it is not done in close co-ordination with sentencing policy; but if that policy is not coherent then they may still fail to meet their objectives if they conflict with the policies of the sentencers who individuate them.
2.3
However, consistency in sentencing is of little value if the sentences
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=59 |
imposed cannot legitimately be justified, and therefore decisions about how we sentence offenders must be made within the context of what we know about why we sentence offenders. No sentencing policy can be complete and useful if it is not formulated within this context.
2.4
In this chapter we identify the need for coherence in sentencing policy by examining the consequences of incoherence. Before we start, let us first clarify the nature of sentencing policy.
2.5
Sentencing policy governs the sentencing decision by providing the sentencer with a framework within which to operate by prompting him or her towards one approach or another depending on the circumstances of the case:2 for example, a general policy might require that drug offenders should be given deterrent sentences.3 In short, sentencing policy governs the choice of approach in the sentencing decision by indicating the type of approach to be adopted and providing some indication of the type of principles which should govern the choice of penalty or measure. It is clear, therefore, that in order to have meaning in practice, a general sentencing policy must be supplemented by specific principles governing the choice of penalty or measure which mechanically provide set answers which must be given when certain circumstances exist: for example, a specific principle might be such that sentencers following a retributive approach are required to impose a sentence of 17 years' imprisonment on any offender responsible for a violent rape, but who admits guilt at an early stage in the investigation.4 In other words, specific principles govern the choice of a particular penalty or measure by providing a set of consequences which are to follow upon the existence of certain factors being established.5
As we shall see, an acceptable set of specific principles governing the imposition of sentence cannot be developed without there first existing a coherent general policy governing sentencing.6 It is not within the scope of our remit to come up with a set of specific sentencing principles; rather, the aim of this paper is to propose a coherent general framework from which a set of specific principles may be developed.
2.6
Let us also make the observation at this point that in this jurisdiction neither our sentencing policy nor our specific principles governing the imposition
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=60 |
of sentence are adequately developed; as we have seen, existing sentencing policy does not always assist sentencers in deciding what approach to adopt when sentencing a particular offender, and there are few specific principles upon which a sentencer may rely to find the appropriate penalty or measure having adopted a particular approach.7
2.7
Let us now examine the importance of a coherent sentencing policy in a rational sentencing system.
2.8
If no sentencing policy existed then there would be no right or wrong answers to the two questions of why and how offenders are sentenced, and the sentencing system would be bereft of any useful sentencing principles. The criminal law would consist merely of criminalising statutes with attached penalty scales and a general mandate for the courts to sentence within the prescribed ranges. The courts could sentence for any reason, in any manner, and upon any basis they saw fit.8
2.9
Where two or more considerations may be relied upon to decide 'why' and 'how' offenders are sentenced, and all of these considerations are equal and interchangeable, then an incoherent sentencing policy exists. Since one consideration may lead to a sentence dramatically different to that which another may have led to, like cases may be treated differently, and justifiably so, but there is nothing to determine which consideration is the correct one and which one should prevail. The end result is inconsistency in the way in which the criminal justice system deals with offenders, exhibiting what may be perceived as disparity, and undermining confidence in the criminal justice system.
2.10
Traditionally, in Ireland and many other jurisdictions, sentencing policy has been formulated by reference to the traditional objects of sentencing. The traditionally recognised objects or purposes of sentencing are retribution, rehabilitation, deterrence and incapacitation, although some modern writers make reference to less well recognised objects such as reparation or compensation of the victim.9 These expressions are commonly embodied in the penal codes of other jurisdictions.10 Although sometimes there have been general attempts to prioritise certain objects by the judiciary,11 the objects are generally interchangeable and there is usually no principle which governs how one object should be found to be more suitable than another in a given case, so our sentencing policy is best described as incoherent. What follows is an
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=61 |
examination of some of the problems presented by an incoherent sentencing policy.
2.11
In a sentencing system such as ours which has an incoherent policy governing the choice of approach by the sentencer, the resulting inconsistent decisions can do violence to notions of Fair Notice as when a defendant who reasonably expects a trivial sentence receives a lengthy one, giving the defendant, as Finlay CJ described it in Conroy (No. 2), a substantial sense of grievance at unfair treatment which may be caused by apparently unequal sentences.12 What is unfair is that in the absence of a coherent policy, the defendant and his or her counsel will have to rely on their own ingenuity in deciding what factors to bring to the attention of the sentencer which they feel will influence him or her to choose one approach over another. This is not an easy task, since, essentially, the goalposts are not defined if sentencers themselves do not have a policy on which factors should influence their choice of approach, how, then, are defendants to inform sentencers of the factors relevant to their particular case? In Conroy's case,13 for example, the Supreme Court found on appeal that the trial judge had overlooked evidence of a high standard of behaviour on the part of the offender while on remand in custody, which, if considered, should have led to the adoption of a rehabilitative approach. Conroy had the good fortune to have this factor recognised on appeal and his sentence reduced accordingly; but one may ask how many other offenders are sentenced without consideration of such factors because they and their counsel do not have fair notice of the importance or relevance of these factors?
2.12
A sentencing judge could wittingly or unwittingly usurp the legislature's penal policy by imposing a trivial sanction for a crime which the legislature has presumed would call for a more severe one say insider trading. The legislature may have allowed for a high maximum penalty in the hope that severe sentences would be imposed to deter, yet the judge may impose a trivial sentence in order to promote rehabilitation. The problem becomes more acute when the legislature introduces new penal measures (i.e. new types of sentence) which may have the aim of fostering one approach or aim; the courts may misuse them or completely ignore them if they do not correspond with their personal sentencing policies. The legislature and the judiciary could end up acting at crossed purposes.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=62 |
2.13
Ashworth comments on the effect this problem has had on English penal policy:
It is clear, not only from the period 1979 1981 but also from 1967 onwards, that the introduction of new forms of sentence will only achieve the policy objectives of their proponents if close attention is paid to their integration into sentencing practice. In blunt terms, the courts can make or break a new penal measure. This indicates the desirability of providing guidelines for sentencers, once it has been decided exactly how the new measure ought to fit into sentencing practice. The great difficulty is that there exists no systematic knowledge about sentencing practice.14 |
He concludes:
It therefore follows that co-ordination of policy, from prosecution through to parole (including procedural issues such as expediting criminal trials), is essential if the criminal justice system is to be shaped so as to achieve agreed policy objectives.15 |
2.14
It is clear, therefore, that although sentencing is but one stage in the criminal process, the policies at play there may have profound repercussions on the other stages. If there is not a coherent policy in operation at the sentencing stage then it becomes increasingly unlikely that the other stages will achieve their objectives. This is of importance not simply to the other stages in the criminal justice system but to sentencing itself. If there is not a coherent policy governing sentencing practice then it is increasingly difficult for the legislature to introduce penal measures which will fit neatly into sentencing practice.16 Certainly, it will be impossible to co-ordinate policy throughout the entire process without at first clarifying the policies of the individual components.
2.15
Incoherent sentencing principles can accommodate abuse since each judge is virtually free to impose any sentence he or she feels appropriate. A sceptic might conclude that the use of the objects to justify a chosen sentence is a convenient means of rationalising results for which the sentencer has another reason window dressing as Robinson describes it.17 Under this cynical view, the objects offer hidden flexibility to sentencers helped by the lack of a single overriding principle. Although we do not share in this scepticism, we agree that in our incoherent sentencing policy, the absence of a single guiding principle means that the choices made will be, at best, inconsistent.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=63 |
2.16
Yet, while it is hoped that our sentencers would not knowingly allow a particular personal bias to affect their sentencing decisions, it remains questionable whether there is widespread unconscious bias; it is unlikely that sentencers nowadays allow their choices to be influenced by demographic factors such as sex, politics, religion or race,18 but there is some evidence that the age of the sentencer19 or the degree of urbanization of the community in which the sentencer lives,20 may lead towards an invisible bias in favour of one approach over another. For example, Hogarth found that in Canada urban magistrates tend to favour a retributive approach more than their rural counterparts.21 In the absence of a coherent policy, thus, there is greater room for demographic factors to have an influence on the sentencer's choice of approach to sentencing an offender, since there is no standard or accepted policy to point him or her in the direction of any single approach.
2.17
When several conflicting principles are pursued simultaneously, the resulting sentence may frustrate them all.22 The sentence may rely too much on rehabilitation to satisfy retributive factors, yet it may not use deterrent factors enough to have any use as a preventive strategy. When the principles of sentencing are in conflict, as they are, following a little of each may achieve no purpose at all.
2.18
When conflicting principles are simultaneously relied upon, the public will almost certainly experience the sentencing system as exhibiting disparity. The public assume the system to be coherent and probably suppose that sentences will reflect common-sense principles of desert (i.e. that the severity of the sentence will reflect the seriousness of the crime).23 Thus when similar offenders who have committed similar crimes receive dissimilar sentences the public tends to see this as disparity.24 Part of the public's concern is expressed as dissatisfaction that certain offenders (in particular violent offenders) are not dealt with harshly enough by the system,25 or in calls for a prosecution right to appeal against a lenient sentence.26
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=64 |
2.19
This distrust may owe part of its existence to the manner in which the news media inform the public of sentencing decisions. Generally, the media tend to devote more attention to sentences that are seemingly unusual in some way unusually lenient or unusually harsh which leaves the public with less opportunity to form a rounded opinion of sentencing. Ashworth remarks:
Newspapers tend to print headlines such as 'Rapist gets only 18 months' rather than 'First offender of exemplary previous character imprisoned for 18 months'.27 |
2.20
Most journalistic comment fails to recognise the distinction between inequality of sentence severity based on the type of offence and inequality of sentence severity based on differences in the seriousness of the offending behaviour and the character of the offender. But not all the blame for public distrust of the sentencing system must be laid at the door of the media. Sentencers themselves rarely give any indication of the factors of the offending behaviour and character of the offender which led them to impose (to continue with the above example) an 18 month sentence on the particular offender when others of a less righteous character receive 5 years. The failure to provide reasons may equally be construed by the public as illustrating that sentencers themselves are unsure of the criteria which govern their choices. Certainly the public cannot rest secure in the knowledge that there is no coherent policy which sentencers follow in making their choices.
2.21
In this context it is hardly surprising that the public does not understand the sentencing system and is critical of it. This has profound consequences for the criminal justice system, because sentencing is:
... the punchline of the criminal justice system. It is at this point that the law is seen to have its impact. The sentencing stage provides the most tangible, public demonstration that the criminal law is not just a declaratory model code, but is a set of rules which are to be enforced by punishment. The whole apparatus of investigation, prosecution and trial is in many respects simply a prelude to the punishment of the guilty. And similarly, a range of institutions and personnel which makes the correctional component of the criminal justice system is largely about administering the sentencing decisions of the courts. The importance of the sentencing stage can hardly be overstated.28 |
2.22
Victims of crime, too, commonly remark that the system does not respond to their dilemma. The incoherence of the principles pursued renders sentences unpredictable and very often the victims of a crime will complain that
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=65 |
justice was not done, and express distrust of the criminal justice system.
2.23
A positive response to the victim's dilemma was contained in section 5 of the Criminal Justice Bill, 1992 which provided:
|
2.24
If a similar section became law, courts in sentencing should make clear what proportion of their sentences in these cases is referable to the effect of the offence on the victim.
2.25
Incoherent sentencing principles can lead to what is perceived as disparity. Disparity, simply put, is a difference in sentencing which cannot be justified. But without a single over-riding policy or approach to say what is or isn't justified, it is very difficult to say that disparity exists. Disparity depends on one's theory of sentencing:
Since disparity is a notion of formal justice, it presupposes a distinction between relevant and irrelevant factors. The distinction requires substantive criteria about what is relevant and irrelevant.29 |
2.26
Forst comments:30
Anyone who wants to show disparity in sentencing must demonstrate |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=66 |
that the different sentences meted out to persons committing the same offence under similar circumstances cannot be justified by reference to some legally relevant variables, that is, to factors that have some rational relationship to the aims of the criminal law. This is a tall order to fulfil, since the aims of the criminal law are rarely clearly articulated. |
2.27
There is no single policy or approach in our system, so like cases may be treated differently, and justifiably so. Two judges suggesting different sentences for an identical case might both be right (or, for that matter, wrong) if one accepts the legitimacy of different priorities being given to different approaches to sentencing.31 Disparity would be enormously difficult to detect because almost any factor can be of relevance to one of the alternative objects of sentencing:
Particular offence or offender characteristics may well justify different sentences, in terms of either type or severity, for apparently similar offences. Whether such differences will amount to disparity will depend on their compatibility, not with one another, but with the stated goals and policies of the sentencing process. For example, on 2 July 1987, in Limerick Circuit Court, a 24-year-old man was sentenced to 4 years imprisonment when convicted of raping a 62-year-old woman. On the same day, in Dublin Circuit Court, a 60-year-old man was sentenced to 9 years when convicted of raping a 25-year-old woman and received a 5 year concurrent sentence for indecently assaulting the same victim. Did this amount to disparity? It is impossible to say in the absence of criteria against which to evaluate them.32 |
2.28
Without a coherent policy, thus, the value of conducting research on the extent of disparity in sentencing must come into question. Kapardis, who conducted what many consider to be the most extensive evaluation of the evidence and research on sentencing disparity,33 concluded that nearly every method of conducting research on disparity may be criticised on a number of grounds. In order satisfactorily to prove the existence of disparity, a research
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=67 |
project would have to satisfy a large number of minimum requirements34 which as a practical matter are virtually impossible to fulfill simultaneously. The fundamental problem is that there is simply no consensus on the factors which point to the suitability of one justification or approach in any given case which would show that the sentencing practices under investigation indicate disparity. There is not, thus, a ready means by which sentencing disparity can be proven to a satisfactory level.35
2.29
It is nonetheless inevitable that a high level of inconsistency will occur when sentencers make the choice as to the particular approach upon which to base their choice of sentence. Radzinowicz and Hood observe of inconsistencies that:
They have been demonstrated again and again, in terms of areas, courts, of individual judges and magistrates. The North of England, for example, uses probation more sparingly, fines and imprisonment more readily than the South. Federal Courts in Brooklyn impose sentences for robbery averaging half as long again as those in Manhattan. A recent analysis revealed that the proportion of robbers in Birmingham getting more than 4 years was 6 times as high as that in Bristol. Magistrates impose far lower fines for motoring offences in some English courts than in others. We cannot immediately jump to the conclusion that the whole of these differences stems from unjustified prejudice, harshness, or ignorance on the part of the courts ... But even when allowance has been made for such factors, evidence remains of unjustified discrepancies ....36 |
2.30
The worst type of inconsistency is inconsistency in the way in which sentencers decide on which approach to adopt when making the sentencing decision as where one sentencer decides that a particular offender should receive a short sentence on the grounds of rehabilitation and another sentencer
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=68 |
decides that the same offender should receive a lengthy sentence on the grounds of deterrence because it leads to unequal treatment of offenders by the criminal justice system. The existence of such inconsistency is easily determined by taking a look at the perceptions of those who sentence and the actual results of their sentencing dispositions. Palays and Divorski describe the results of a Canadian exercise which, in the absence of an Irish analogue, we may find compelling.37
2.31
The study was conducted by furnishing over 200 Provincial Court judges with the same basic facts relating to the offence and the characteristics of the offender in five hypothetical specimen cases. The judges were individually asked to indicate the sentence they would recommend in each case and the reasons for their conclusions. In all cases there was inconsistency in the sentences recommended in many the degree of inconsistency was quite dramatic. The study revealed the way in which sentencing judges differ in their philosophical approach to sentencing some choosing rehabilitative approaches and others choosing retributive ones. Those sentencers who were generally more lenient tended to rely on rehabilitative reasoning while those who were more severe emphasised the seriousness of the crime.
2.32
Other studies of actual sentencing dispositions found similar inconsistency.38 We have every reason to believe that in Ireland, a fortiori, considering the similarities in sentencing structure, similar inconsistencies would be displayed here. Intuitively, the existence of inconsistency here is a certainty.
2.33
An incoherent sentencing policy hinders the rationalisation of sentencing generally. Because there is no universal agreement as to the paramount aim or approach to sentencing, it is impossible to construct any other than the most general and piecemeal set of principles which should have application in any given case, or at all; and, consequently, it is very difficult to construct a purposeful repertoire of principles to assist sentencers in making the decision as to the appropriate penalty or measure.
2.34
Because sentencing remains an instinctive synthesis of the particular characteristics of the offender and the particular characteristics of the offence, it is not appropriate to lay down any standardisation or tariff of penalty for cases.39 Thus, for example, it is impossible to say that just because the penalty for a given case far exceeds the average sentence for that offence, the sentence on hand is wrong;40 nor, therefore, can sentencers have recourse to decided
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=69 |
examples or averages of sentence for that offence to assist him or her in the choice of penalty or measure.
2.35
This lack of guidance, coupled with the scant legislative guidance which exists on the use of the various sentencing options, has a number of undesirable consequences.
2.36
To begin with, sentencing judges are left to their own devices when determining the extent of the sentence imposed. How, one may ask, does a sentencer know that, say, three years imprisonment is appropriate for a given offender having regard to the seriousness of the offending behaviour? How does a sentencer know that 100 hours of community service is more likely to induce reform than 40 hours? Different judges may choose different degrees of severity when deciding on the extent of sentence for similar offenders or offences.
2.37
Secondly, sentencing judges, deciding on the nature of sentence, are given no indication of when or how to use individual sanctions open to them. How does a judge decide that, say, community service would be more appropriate than probation? There is no consensus as to whether some of the sentencing options available to the court are simply alternatives to other options, or whether they exist in their own right as the most appropriate penalty for a certain case. In some cases, sentencers may even regard a particular alternative as quite inappropriate and not use it for any offences.41 The end result may be an over-reliance on imprisonment.42 Also, different judges may impose different alternatives in sentencing similar offenders for similar crimes.
2.38
Thirdly, sentencing judges, the accused, counsel and the public are given no consistent indication as to the seriousness of particular crimes, or as to how the seriousess of crimes should be gauged. In general, the only indication of how seriously a crime is viewed by the Oireachtas is the maximum sentence which it carries.43 But even these are inconsistent and out of date, and of little assistance in gauging offence seriousness.
2.39
Finally, the worst consequence of this dearth of principles is inconsistency, and all the problems associated with it, such as sagging public confidence, and confusion for those involved in the sentencing process. In order to reverse these problems, it is necessary that a meaningful and uniform set of principles be constructed to assist sentencers. But without first laying down the underlying policy of sentencing, this would be a pointless exercise, merely replacing an unfair level of inconsistency with an equally unfair level of consistency. This happened in the USA. There, the Federal Guidelines Commission set out a list of guidelines which laid down the presumptive sentence for every crime on the statute books; the presumptive sentence was to be
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=70 |
followed in all cases save in exceptional circumstances. However, the presumptive sentences were set by the Commission without it first agreeing on the underlying rationale and as a result, they embody a degree of past irrationality since they were set by reference to prior averages and not by reference to any policy. Without a policy to define what makes a case un-exceptional, an enormous volume of appeals is being generated to determine whether each case is exceptional (so as to allow departure from the guidelines) or not.44Galligan points out that reasons for departure are themselves relevant to the broader policies which inform the specific rules, and therefore they are good reasons for changing or extending the rules to take account of new or unforeseen circumstances.45 If the reason for the departure is so personal to the offender that it is incapable of being generalised and related to broader sentencing policies, then it is hard to see why it should be allowed to form part of the sentencing decision.
2.40
A coherent policy is, thus, a necessary precursor to the development and implementation of principles to assist sentencers.
2.41
A coherent sentencing policy is simply a general framework of standards which clearly articulates the object or approach to be adopted in all cases, or in any given case. It goes a long way towards eliminating the problems set out above because it lays down a defined course of action to be followed by the sentencing courts when dealing with particular offenders and offences. A defendant will have fair notice of the particular circumstances of his or her case which are relevant to the sentencing decision. The legislature and judiciary would be acting in concert because they would both be taking the same approach. There would be little possibility of abuse since there would be no room for the sentencer to take irrelevant considerations or personal bias into account. There would be no chance of failure to achieve any object because there would be no reason for the court to seek to follow more than one object simultaneously. The public would be given a clear basis for the sentencing choices made by the criminal justice system, and there would be less room for inconsistency, because the relevant characteristics of the offender and offence would be clearly identifiable in like cases, and the approach adopted in like cases would be uniform. Finally, a coherent sentencing policy would provide the framework within which a rational and consistent set of guiding principles could be constructed.
2.42
A coherent sentencing policy may be brought about in a number of ways; Jareborg identifies the following three:46
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=71 |
|
2.43
It should be remembered that a coherent sentencing policy is not a panacea for all the problems associated with our sentencing process it desperately needs to be supplemented by a set of specific principles to guide sentencers in its individuation. For example, if, under a coherent policy, retribution was to be the sole object pursued in every case, two judges sentencing like offenders for like offences could still differ over the amount of punishment necessary to punish each.47 However, coherence is a fundamental of an efficient and just sentencing system without which the remaining difficulties cannot be resolved.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=72 |
3.1
A sentencer receives little or no guidance from the Oireachtas or from judicial precedent when choosing the correct approach to adopt in relation to a particular offender and a particular offence.1 Both the appellate courts and the Oireachtas have shown remarkable reluctance when it comes to making rules or passing laws which give helpful guidance on sentencing matters. The provision of maximum penalties alone has been of relatively little value.
3.2
The obvious route for reform is the introduction of statutory guidance for sentencers as to the factors which should influence their choice of approach in sentencing. The danger here, however, is that legislative involvement in the sentencing process may violate the constitutional separation of powers by entering the domain of the administration of justice which is the exclusive preserve of the courts in criminal matters.
3.3
In this chapter we examine the special position of the courts in the sentencing process under the Constitution to see what interference with judicial sentencing discretion would be an unconstitutional infringement of the separation of powers.
3.4
Judicial sentencing discretion has only emerged as a feature of the sentencing process in the last 150 years or so. Prior to the mid-nineteenth century, the sentencing judge was afforded no discretion in the case of a felony, for which the punishment was mandatory forfeiture of the lands and goods of the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=73 |
offender, and death.3 However in some cases judges would reprieve the convicted offender with a recommendation to royal clemency, usually on condition of transportation to the colonies.
3.5
Statutory reforms enacted between 1827 and 1840 gave judges the discretion to impose a sentence of transportation instead of the death penalty, and in the 1850s this discretion was widened to the imposition of penal servitude in substitution for transportation. The Consolidation Acts of 1861 established the basis for sentencing discretion as it exists today, by investing the courts with the discretion to choose the nature and extent of the sentence within broad parameters.
3.6
The task of the sentencing judge in the late nineteenth century was simply to mete out punishment in proportion to the gravity of the offence. However a marked change in attitudes became noticeable around 1907 with the introduction of The Probation of Offenders Act which empowered sentencers to adopt a rehabilitative rather than a punitive approach by dealing with the offender as an individual. In 1908 the Prevention of Crime Act introduced more individualised measures borstal training and preventive detention for habitual offenders which heralded the new ideal that the sentence must not only reflect the seriousness of the offending behaviour but also the characteristics of the individual offender. Subsequent legislative measures have continued in this vein, culminating in the introduction of Community Service in 1983.4
3.7
Article 34.1 of the Constitution ensures the independence of the judicial function from interference by the other organs of state by providing that justice is to be administered in courts and, in criminal cases, only in courts. The selection of the sentence to be imposed in individual circumstances has been held to constitute an intrinsically judicial function, and accordingly a function which may only be exercised by judges in courts. In Lynham & Butler (No 2),5 Kennedy CJ said:
[T]he judicial power is exercised in determining the guilt or innocence of persons charged with offences against the State itself, and in determining the punishments to be inflicted upon persons found guilty of the offences charged against them ....6 |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=74 |
3.8
It has been stated that:
It is a matter of considerable constitutional importance that the courts should be wholly independent of the executive, and they are. Thus, whilst the judges, as private citizens, will be aware of the 'policy' of the government of the day, in the sense of its political purpose, aspirations and programme, these are not matters which are in any way relevant to the courts' decisions and are wholly ignored. In matters of home policy, the courts have regard only to the will of Parliament as expressed in the statutes, in subordinate legislation and in executive acts authorised by Parliament.7 |
3.9
Thus, in Deaton v AG,8 where the plaintiff had been convicted under legislation which provided that sentence upon conviction for certain smuggling offences under that Act was to be either a fine of £100 or forfeiture of treble the value of the goods, including the duty payable thereon, at the election of the Revenue Commissioners, the Supreme Court unanimously held that the delegation of the power to choose penalty to the Revenue Commissioners contravened the separation of powers doctrine and the independence of judicial function guaranteed by Article 34.1. O Dαlαigh CJ said (for the court):
The selection of punishment is an integral part of the administration of justice and, as such, cannot be committed to the hands of the Executive ... The Section ... remains intact, but with the words at the election of [the Revenue Commissioners] deleted therefrom. Which of the alternative penalties prescribed by the section is proper to be imposed is, together with the issue of the guilt of time accused, a matter to be determined by the court that tries him. |
3.10
Similarly, in The State (O) v O'Brien,9 section 103 of the Children Act, 1908 which empowered the court to sentence a young offender guilty of murder to be detained at his Majesty's pleasure, was in issue. Counsel for the accused argued that the section breached the independence requirement of Article 34.1 if the correct construction of that section was to allow an offender to be sentenced for a term to be decided by the Minister for Justice. The Supreme Court agreed that the section would be unconstitutional if that was the correct construction however, it was not, and the section merely meant that the courts could impose an indeterminate sentence which may be remitted in accordance with Article 13.6 by the Government. Walsh J said of the wording of s103:
If they were a correct adaptation, then the sentence was authorised by |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=75 |
a section which purports to vest such an authority in the Executive, and, following Deaton's Case, such a statutory provision is inconsistent with the provisions of the Constitution ... |
3.11
Again, in The State (Sheerin) v Kennedy,10 a provision empowering the Minister for Justice to transfer juvenile offenders from borstal to prison was found to be unconstitutional in so far as it allowed the Minister to choose whether or not such subsequent imprisonment was to be with or without hard labour in effect a selection of punishment.
3.12
It is clear, therefore, that the Executive cannot choose the penalty to be imposed in an individual case, nor may it tell the courts how to sentence. Not only would it be interfering with the judicial function, but it would be impinging upon the offender's right of fair procedures, because the individual citizen needs the safeguard of the Courts in the assessment of punishment as much as on his trial for the offence. The degree of punishment which a particular citizen is to undergo for a offence is a matter vitally affecting his liberty.11
3.13
As Kelly points out,12 Article 34.1 cannot be read as guaranteeing the courts absolute discretion in the administration of justice. The same must be said of the sentencing decision which is part of the administration of justice. For most offences, the range of penalties which may be imposed is prescribed by the legislature by statute, which the Oireachtas can modify. Thus, in The People (DPP) v Cahill13 Henchy J said:
It is part of the judicial function to determine the nature and extent of the sentence whenever the general rule laid down by statute or common law gives a range of choice.14 |
3.14
It is accepted, therefore, that it is not a breach of Article 34.1 for the legislature to deprive the courts completely of their sentencing discretion by prescribing mandatory sentences.15. In Deaton's case O Dαlαigh CJ, delivering the unanimous opinion of the Supreme Court, said:
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=76 |
The Legislature does not prescribe the penalty to be imposed in an individual citizen's case; it states the general rule, and the application of that rule is for the Courts. If the general rule is enunciated in the form of a fixed penalty then all citizens convicted of the offence must bear the same punishment.16 |
3.15
In The State (O'Rourke) v Kelly17 the Supreme Court held that:
many of the statutory provisions on proof of certain matters make it mandatory on a court to make a specified order. Such legislative provisions are within the competence of the Oireachtas. |
3.16
However, these must be read in the light of Buckley v AG18 where it was held that the judicial process is inviolable while in actual operation. In Buckley, a dispute arose, over the ownership of about £20,000 the remains of a fund built up by the old Sinn Fιin organisation prior to fragmentation. While an action was pending in the High Court the Oireachtas passed the Sinn Fιin Funds Act, 1947 of which s10 provided that all further proceedings in the High Court should be stayed. The Supreme Court found that s10 amounted to an unconstitutional interference by the legislature in the exercise of the judicial function.
3.17
Thus, while it would be unconstitutional for the legislature to interfere with the court's sentencing decision in an individual case,19 it would not offend the separation of powers doctrine for the legislature to prescribe the penalty for a class of offence, or for all offences.20
3.18
The issue which remains to be examined, therefore, is the extent to which the legislature can make provisions which govern how sentencing discretion is to be exercised by the courts. What, for example, is the constitutional position of a statutory provision obliging sentencing judges, while exercising their judicial discretion to choose a penalty within the range provided by statute, to impose a sentence from that range which is most likely to deter the offender and others,21 and not to have regard to the possibility of reform of the offender, a possibility which might have induced the sentencer to impose a more lenient sentence?
3.19
It appears that the power to restrict sentencing discretion in this manner is inherent in the legislative power to grant or deprive the courts of sentencing
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=77 |
discretion. The legislature has already restricted the discretion of the courts to choosing a penalty from within the range provided for by statutory maximum and minimum sentences, and the constitutionality of such restriction has not been questioned by the courts. Also, the legislature has, in some instances, restricted the discretion of the courts to impose certain penalties. For example, an order requiring a drug addict to participate in a specified programme of treatment or therapy under s28(2) of the Misuse of Drugs Act, 1977, as amended, cannot be made unless the court first considers a medical report and a social inquiry report;22 and an order under the Probation of Offenders Act, 1907, cannot be made unless the court has regard to the character, antecedents, age, health, or mental condition of the person charged, or to the trivial nature of the offence, or to the extenuating circumstances under which the offence was committed.23 Thus it has been said that:
There is no constitutional rule or convention which prevents the Legislature from restricting or removing judicial discretion in sentencing: the simple fact is that Parliament has taken little interest in the matter and has rarely legislated so as to impinge on the discretion of the courts to impose any sentence beneath the statutory maximum.24 |
3.20
The prevailing practice of the Irish legislature of setting the maximum penalties and leaving the courts with wide sentencing discretion amounts to a de facto delegation of the sentencing policy-making function by the legislature to the judiciary. Would it be preferable that the legislature leave the formulation of sentencing policy to the courts, or would it be more practically wise for the legislature to provide the courts with sentencing policy?
3.21
It may be argued that the courts are in the best position to formulate sentencing policy because they deal with sentencing cases every day. However, the ability of the courts to formulate a coherent sentencing policy is to a large degree determined by the structure within which they must operate. In the Irish court system, where the principle of co-ordinate jurisdiction means that judges of the same court are largely free to disregard each other's sentencing decisions, it is in the appellate courts where sentencing policy is judicially shaped; in particular, in the Court of Criminal Appeal and the Supreme Court. Yet the appellate courts have found themselves to be largely unwilling and unable to formulate anything more than the most general of sentencing policies.
3.22
The appellate courts lack a sufficient volume of sentencing appeals from
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=78 |
which to develop a considered and principled sentencing policy. Appeals against sentence are infrequent. Rottman and Tormey found that in 1981 only 8.2% of cases were appealed from the Dublin Circuit Court to the Court of Criminal Appeal; 15.6% of cases from the Special Criminal Court; and 23.1% of cases from the Central Criminal Court a total of 70 appeals in all, out of 30,253 criminal cases heard that year.25 What percentage of these accounted for appeals against sentence is not clear. This leads to the conclusion that only fairly severe sentences are likely to be appealed, so the appellate courts have little opportunity to examine non-serious cases.26 The facility to appeal against conviction only reduces this opportunity further. Secondly, the fact that the prosecution may not appeal a lenient sentence means that the appellate courts will only have opportunity to hear a lop-sided set of cases. Its policies would, therefore, be based on a consideration of over-severe sentences, not on cases which were too lenient.
3.23
Moreover, the courts operate in a vacuum. They do not have the benefit of the views of criminologists, psychologists, sociologists or any of the other personnel who would be expected to have compelling arguments for or against the adoption of one policy over another. In Canada, Australia and several American jurisdictions the issues of policy have been fully examined by an independent sentencing commission, comprising persons thus qualified, and have been able to establish fully acceptable and appropriate aims and policies for sentencing.27
3.24
Furthermore, there is no satisfactory system of dissemination of appellate policy decisions to the lower courts and to those involved in the sentencing process. A high proportion of the sentencing judgments of the Court of Criminal Appeal are delivered extemporaneously so it is unlikely that many other than those present at the hearing will learn of their import. But even written judgments of the Court of Criminal Appeal are not well reported. For example, the seminal judgment of Walsh J in The People (AG) v O' Driscoll28 escaped reporting until the fortuitous publication of Frewen's Judgments of the Court of Criminal Appeal over six years later.29 The systematic reporting of sentencing judgments would be of some assistance in the development of sentencing policy; in England, the development of detailed policy did not begin until the extensive reporting of sentencing judgments in the Court of Appeal began in the Criminal Law Review in 1954, followed by Thomas's Principles of Sentencing in 1970 (which, even then, drew on many unreported decisions) and the ultimate establishment of the Criminal Appeal Reports (Sentencing) some time later. But even systematic reporting may not be enough. Despite the high level of reporting in England, their principles and policy of sentencing remain underdeveloped,
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=79 |
even though it might have been thought that the principles of sentencing would undergo rapid growth on a case-by-case basis.30Ashworth puts this down to three features of judicial sentencing decision making: the use (or non-use) of precedents; the limited coverage of appellate decisions (many of which are still delivered extemporaneously); and the limited control over decisions at the trial level.31 Many of the reported cases contain only obiter guidance, and many more may be distinguished upon the facts.
3.25
The legislature, on the other hand, has a number of conspicuous advantages which make it more suited to the formulation of coherent sentencing policy:
|
3.26
An argument against the legislative formulation of sentencing policy is that legislative rules may introduce a high level of inflexibility. If the rules are too rigid, then they may not be able to accommodate new or unforeseen circumstances. Thus, it is argued that there must be retained some degree of judicial discretion to accommodate new or unforeseen circumstances. This argument is better raised against the legislative provision of specific principles for the choice of penalty or measure rather than against the legislative provision of a general sentencing policy. It must be remembered that a sentencing policy is simply a general framework within which a sentencer must operate it provides a set of standards by which a sentencer has to justify the decision, thereby guiding him or her as to the correct approach to be adopted. New and unforeseen circumstances may still be accommodated within that framework, and
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=80 |
their inclusion may be justified by reference to the general policy.
3.27
Essentially, therefore, a legislatively formulated sentencing policy need not remove judicial sentencing discretion; rather what it would do is structure judicial sentencing discretion so that coherence may be introduced into the sentencing decision.
3.28
Other jurisdictions which have successfully achieved coherence in their sentencing policies have done so through the medium of statute;32 indeed, in England and Wales, where there exists a highly developed system of judicial pronouncements on sentencing, a legislative statement of policy was still considered necessary to achieve the necessary degree of coherence.33
3.29
Matters of policy are, in any case, the legitimate concern of the Legislature. Sir James Fitzjames Stephen is often quoted as having said that if the judiciary took on board the task of formulating sentencing policy:
they would be assuming a power which the Constitution does not give them.34 |
3.30
We accept Stephen's words as expressing the principle that the actual distribution of the policy making function between the legislature and the judiciary ought to be arranged in the most effective manner. We conclude that the legislature is better suited to the formulation of sentencing policy. We therefore provisionally recommend that the legislature undertakes the task of formulating a coherent policy governing sentencing to be set out in the form of a statute or statutes.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=81 |
4.1
What is the justification for the imposition of a criminal sanction? The objects of punishment have traditionally been classified under two broad headings:
|
4.2
Much perplexity has surrounded attempts to justify sentencing by focussing on a single justification, but, equally, much confusion surrounds the idea that a plurality of different values and aims should be recognised.1 Present Irish sentencing policy epitomises the latter. Recent philosophical attempts which seek to combine morality and utility, e.g. by advocating that sanctions provide redress for the victims of crime, appear to be more of a supplement than a replacement for the two mainstream trends.2
4.3
A further distinction should be mentioned. When discussing the objects of sentencing, normative objects, such as retribution, rehabilitation, deterrence
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=82 |
and incapacitation, should be distinguished from functional objects, such as the tailoring of sanctions to suit prison capacity or the cost of imprisonment.3 Normative objects are concerned with the desired external effects of sentencing; functional objects are relevant to the internal operation of the system.4 It is widely accepted that the functional objects should only be considered as being subsidiary to the traditional normative objects. For example, as the issue of prison capacity becomes critical, the normative goals may take second place to functional considerations. It may be the availability of prison accommodation which eventually determines whether an offender is sentenced to imprisonment, not the competing need for a custodial sentence on one of the normative grounds.5 This is undoubtedly a problem for sentencers in individual cases, but should not have a place in the formulation of general sentencing policy. Ashworth elaborates:
Sentencing by the courts is more than a tap by which to regulate the flow of offenders into our custodial institutions. Sentencing involves a public statement about an offender and an offence. It is a purposive activity, relating to the offence for which the offender has been convicted, the characteristics of the offender, and the aims of sentencing. It is not, and cannot be justified as, a mere response to economic constraints or planning failures... [I]t is surely incompatible with the nature and function of sentencing that it should be regulated by reference to whether a wing of one prison has collapsed, or whether the sewerage system of another prison has become inoperative... [I]n a system where proportionality is central, seasonal variations in sentencing policy according to the problems of the prison service are difficult to justify.6 |
4.4
Subsequent discussion will be confined to the normative objects of sentencing.
4.5
While the objects of sentencing concern why we impose criminal sanctions, principles for the distribution (or allocation) of sentence concern how those sanctions are imposed, i.e. who is to receive a sentence, what kind and how severe a sentence is to be imposed? While there must be some relationship between the ends and the means of sentencing, the linkage is not a simple one. Independent moral considerations may arise at the stage of distribution which
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=83 |
may sometimes appear to reduce the efficacy or impact of punishment.7
4.6
It may also be simplistic to assume that tailoring the means of distribution of criminal sanctions to suit the end or aim of any chosen object of sentencing will increase the degree to which that object's ends are attained. For example, if crime prevention by way of deterrence is the chosen end, then it may be assumed that increasing the level and frequency of sanctions imposed will achieve greater deterrence; or if incapacitation is the object, it is assumed that increasing the number of persons incarcerated will reduce the crime rate. It is now widely recognised that these simple-minded assumptions (to quote the Canadian Sentencing Commission)8 have little or no basis in fact. Experience has taught us that simple increases in the severity or frequency of sanctions in order to improve the achievement of a single object seldom lead to the social benefits presumed to result from them.
4.7
But just as the objects of sentencing do not easily resolve the question of distribution, principles of distribution such as proportionality and parsimony are equally inadequate in solving the issue of justification. Von Hirsch, the leading exponent of the just deserts philosophy (which provides that sanctions should be commensurate with the blameworthiness of the offending behaviour) argues that the imposition of sanction without the support of perceptible social benefits i.e. punishment in the purely retributivist sense is futile:
it is preferable to have a general justification for the criminal sanction that is expressly consequentialist in part. This makes the warrant for the existence of punishment dependent on that institution having significant crime-preventive benefits.9 |
4.8
The search for a consequentialist justification cannot be resolved by looking to principles of distribution as the Canadian Sentencing Commission observed:
The assertion that sanctions are commensurate with blameworthiness does no more to legitimise the existence of penal sanctions than the fact that income tax is proportionate to revenue justifies the practice of taxation in itself.10 |
4.9
A discussion of sentencing policy must, therefore, begin by addressing the question of the justification for imposing criminal sanctions in order to define the context in which decisions about distribution should be made. It would be wrong, however, to assume that once the problem of justification is solved (if, indeed, a solution is possible), the question of distribution is thereby also automatically resolved. While a sentencing policy must have regard to the overall
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=84 |
objectives of punishment, it may also have to take into account other considerations, for example, the need to have regard to the fundamental rights of the offender and to considerations of cost and practicality.
4.10
Let us now examine the traditional objects of sentencing in order to define the context in which decisions about the distribution of sentence must take place.
4.11
Retribution stresses the moral obligation of the criminal law to punish offenders. No further ground other than moral obligation is offered to justify the imposition of punishment. Thus retribution has often been criticised as mere vengeance seeking. What good, it may be asked, does it do to hang a murderer? It only leaves two people dead instead of one. As Bacon once said:
Revenge is a kind of wild justice which, the more man's nature runs to, the more ought law to weed it out. |
4.12
Utilitarians criticise retribution because of its apparent pointlessness. In Macaulay's words:
The suffering caused by punishment is, considered by itself, an evil, and ought to be inflicted only for the sake of some prepondering good. |
4.13
Since pure retribution is grounded on moral justifications, its success cannot be measured in terms of its achievements, but rather on the strength of its moral arguments. However, many scholars have queried whether any attempt to find a sound moral argument in favour of retribution does not end up in a vicious circle. This is ably illustrated in the following extract from the Canadian Sentencing Commission's report:
The question is this: Why should we punish a person? An obvious answer is Because that person has done something wrong. However, this answer raises another issue: should we actually impose legal sanctions on individuals for any kind of wrongdoing (being discourteous, lacking table manners, cheating at cards)? Obviously not. Only those who are guilty of the most serious forms of wrongdoing should be punished. What precisely are these? They are labelled criminal offences. And what, then, is a criminal offence? A criminal offence is a form of behaviour which is legally defined as subject to punishment. Such legal definitions vary from time to time (we do not burn witches anymore) and across countries. Finally, our original question Why should we punish a person? is given the uninformative answer: Because that person has done something which we now believe requires |
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=85 |
punishment.11 |
4.14
In one sense, however, retribution may give rise to a social benefit. A retributive response to wrongdoing is a strong expression of denunciation of the offence. [T]he criminal justice system must involve imposing on offenders punishments of sufficient severity that it is possible rationally to say that a breach of the law, when detected, is attended by significant consequences.12 It seems, therefore, that the place of retribution in the sentencing process is a natural phenomenon a response to a crime which fails to condemn the actor scarcely seems morally adequate.13 To leave an act unpunished is close to condoning it since punishment acts as a re-assertion that the law has been broken and it expresses the moral indignation of the community.14 Closely related to this idea, and again separate from the purely moral justification for retribution, is the modern moral utility justification, namely, that punishment is not only permissible, but desirable i.e. it is not just an inherent element in the moral idea of law but also socially necessary in order to maintain law:
Society has an interest in crime control that is, in ensuring that its laws are obeyed and this provides a justification for taking punitive measures against those who have broken the law. Thus, on this modified version of modern retributivism, punishment is justified not merely because it is deserved but also because it contributes towards crime control.15 |
4.15
One of the justifications of judicial punishment, therefore, is that without state punishment, it seems likely that victimising conduct would become so prevalent as to make life nasty and brutish, indeed.16 This justification, sometimes described as Montero's aim, after the Spanish jurist who articulated it, dictates that judicial punishment is necessary to protect offenders and suspected offenders against unofficial retaliation.17
4.16
The retributive theory of punishment is closely linked to the distributive principle of desert the idea that the offender's punishment should in some way
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=86 |
reflect the injury inflicted by him or her. The idea of subjecting the offender to the same wrong or injury which he has perpetrated seems offensive to most even refined versions which would require the same degree of suffering are commonly considered repugnant; viz the death sentence for murderers. Therefore, modern desert theory is concerned more with proportionality; the degree of punishment inflicted on an offender for a serious offence should be in proportion to the reprehensibility of the criminal behaviour; more severe than that which would be imposed for less reprehensible behaviour and less severe than that which would be imposed for more reprehensible behaviour even though none is equivalent to the degree of suffering resulting from the commission of the crime.
4.17
Retributive punishment should not impinge upon the personal rights of the offender beyond that amount necessary to exact retribution for the offence. The famous utilitarians Beccaria18 and Bentham19 described this as parsimony, i.e. imposing the minimum punishment consistent with the aims of the sentencing process. However, a problem arises in determining the minimum amount of punishment consistent with the aim of retribution. If we reject the idea of imposing on the offender an injury similar to that which he has inflicted, or a level of suffering equivalent to that caused by the offence, we are left with the very difficult task of assessing the level of punishment by reference to the degree of moral wrongdoing involved in the offence. But, as Hart remarks:
... undoubtedly there is, for modern minds, something obscure and difficult in the idea that we should think in choosing punishment of some right intrinsic relation which it must bear to the wickedness of the criminal's act ....20 We must start somewhere, he said, and in practice the starting point is apt to be just the traditional or usual penalty for a given offence.21 |
4.18
In conclusion, we find that the arguments in favour of retribution alone as a justification for the imposition of criminal sanctions are rather weak. Strict retributivism is unattractive in so far as it emphasises notions of revenge. On the whole, revenge represents a justification for the imposition of criminal sanctions which civilised society should strive to avoid. Undoubtedly, there is some room for the moral utility theory of retribution as a justification for the imposition of sanctions, but some limit is necessary on the claims of strict retributivism. The principle of desert places some desirable limits on the imposition of criminal sanctions. However, desert itself raises difficult issues, such as the question of starting points and the question of what constitutes deservedness.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=87 |
4.19
The rehabilitative ideal assumes that criminal behaviour is the product of antecedent causes which may be identified and controlled, and that measures may be employed to treat the convicted offender so as to effect changes in his behaviour for his own good and for the good of society. In other words crime is viewed as a disease capable of treatment and cure. This utilitarian theory of rehabilitation of offenders is by no means a new one; it is at least as old as Plato.22 However, the rehabilitative ideal did not permeate the sentencing process until early in this century when new ideas for the treatment of offenders were developed. The key change in legal thought was the displacement of the retributive slogan, Let the punishment fit the crime by the new principle Let the treatment fit the needs of the offender.23 This change in attitudes was accompanied by legislative measures such as the introduction of probation in 190724 and the establishment of juvenile courts and borstal training in 1908.25 The rehabilitative ideal was taken to the greatest lengths in the USA. In 1870, the National Congress on Penitentiary and Reformatory Discipline recommended complete indeterminacy in sentences, which would give the authorities unlimited time to reform prisoners.26 In effect, convicted offenders could be detained in prison until deemed cured. By 1949 this practice had spread to most of the states, and in the case of Williams v New York, the Supreme Court said:
Today's philosophy of individualizing sentences makes sharp distinctions, for example between first and repeated offenders. Indeterminate sentences, the ultimate termination of which are sometimes decided by non-judicial agencies, have to a large extent taken the place of the old rigidly fixed punishments. The practice of probation ... has been accepted as a wise policy .... Retribution is no longer the dominant objective of the criminal law. Reformation and rehabilitation of offenders have become important goals of the criminal jurisprudence.27 |
4.20
Rehabilitative programmes reached their peak worldwide in the 1960s and 1970s. Until 1975 all fifty American states, as well as the District of Columbia and the federal jurisdiction had indeterminate sentencing systems. The judge determined the nature of the sentence and, if imprisonment was ordered, stated the maximum or minimum sentence, or both. A parole board then
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=88 |
decided when the offender would be released.28
4.21
Since then, there has been a wide-spread and dramatic loss of faith in the rehabilitative theory, a development which has come to be known as the decline of the rehabilitative ideal.29 The 1970s and 1980s saw marked changes in the attitude of the law towards convicted offenders, who until then were considered to have forfeited all their rights upon conviction. He was thought to be at the disposal of the state to be used for whatever ends might be thought to be expedient... since he has put himself outside the law, the criminal has no basis for complaint.30 This utilitarian attitude changed when it became recognised that the state owed duties to criminals as much as other individuals.31 Criminal justice and punishment began to be regarded as systems concerned with the distribution, deprivation and restriction of rights, a perspective incompatible with the wide discretionary powers and indeterminate sentences associated with rehabilitation.32 It was disregard for the rights of the individual that led to the resurgence of the Kantian opposition to such forms of punishment:
Juridical punishment can never be administered merely as a means for promoting another good either with regard to the criminal himself or to civil society, but must in all cases be imposed only because the individual on whom it is inflicted has committed a crime. For one man ought never to be dealt with merely as a means subservient to the purpose of another.33 |
4.22
It was felt that rehabilitative sentencing gives rise to unwarranted variation or inconsistency in sentences since it looks to offenders' needs for treatment rather than to the character of their crimes. The US Committee for the Study of Incarceration illustrated the problem thus:
If one of two convicted burglars is thought likely to respond to community based treatment while the other seems more amenable to a prison based program, that would be a reason for putting one on probation and imprisoning the other. The difference in the two sentences is rationalised as necessary for the protection of the public: the two burglars will be less likely to return to crime if each is given treatment |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=89 |
suited to his particular need. The explanation holds, however, only if the programs work. Unless programs can demonstrably prevent recidivism, a discrepancy in the two dispositions remains unaccounted for. It is therefore essential to ask: How effective are treatment programs?34 |
4.23
Concern about unwarranted variations led to extensive research into the efficacy of rehabilatitive programmes. All showed rehabilitative sentencing to have failed in fulfilling its purpose of turning offenders away from further crime.35 In 1974, Martinson, in an influential article, concluded that nothing works:
With few and isolated exceptions, the rehabilitative efforts that have been reported so far have had no appreciable effect on recidivism. Studies that have been done since our survey was completed do not present any major grounds for altering that original conclusion.36 |
4.24
The US Panel on the Rehabilitation of Criminal Offenders confirmed these findings:37
There is not now in the scientific literature any basis for any policy or recommendations regarding rehabilitation of criminal offenders. The data available do not present any consistent evidence of efficacy that would lead to such recommendations. |
4.25
However, doubts about the reliability of research into rehabilitative effects have clouded the earlier view of the hopelessness of rehabilitative efforts. The Panel added:
The Panel concludes that Lipton, Martinson and Wilks were reasonably accurate and fair in their appraisal of the rehabilitation literature .... Two limitations, however, must be applied to their conclusions: first, inferences about the integrity of the treatments analysed were uncertain and the interventions involved were generally weak; second, there are suggestions to be found concerning successful rehabilitation efforts that qualify the conclusion that 'nothing works'. |
4.26
In 1979 Martinson was compelled to retract some of his earlier conclusions, leaving him to remark:38
The most interesting general conclusion is that no treatment now used in criminal justice is inherently either substantially helpful or harmful. The critical factor seems to be the conditions under which the program |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=90 |
is delivered. |
4.27
Although detailed research on the matter is not yet available, it appears that Irish sentences, (custodial ones in particular), do not have any improving effect on recidivism.39 The Whitaker Committee concluded:
Programmes for reform and rehabilitation have a positive value but clearly imprisonment cannot be justified merely on the grounds that it can be used to reform and rehabilitate.40 |
4.28
Also, the Whitaker Committee noted that rehabilitation programmes are very expensive, and it is questionable whether the capital investment in social correction is warranted by the expected profit, i.e. reduced recidivism, which does not seem to be forthcoming.41
4.29
Some have suggested that even where the sentence is justified on some other grounds, rehabilitative programmes can lead to victimisation, because the coercive treatment of an offender may distress him or her contrary to principles of equality.42 The issue here is whether it is justifiable to subject one offender to an onerous programme of rehabilitation simply because of his or her supposed likelihood of reform while another offender, supposedly less likely to reform, simply has to do time or vice versa. It has also been argued that it is wrong to try to change the beliefs and attitudes of an offender by any means other than argument, the giving of reasons, or by example.43 Again, the question here is whether the coercion involved in subjecting offenders to rehabilitative programmes amounts to an 'extra punishment' which those serving other sentences do not encounter.
4.30
Finally, a perplexing consequence of rehabilitative principles is that they can lead to longer sentences being imposed on offenders. Allen, one of the leading critics of rehabilitation theory, concluded:
... Surprisingly enough, the rehabilitative ideal has often led to increased severity of penal measures .... The tendency of proposals for wholly indeterminate sentences, a clearly identifiable fruit of the rehabilitative ideal, is unmistakably in the direction of lengthened periods of imprisonment .... Experience has demonstrated that, in practice, there is a strong tendency for the rehabilitative ideal to serve purposes that are essentially incapacitative rather than therapeutic in character.44 |
4.31
In conclusion, it is very difficult to accept rehabilitation as a justification
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=91 |
for the imposition of sentence, particularly since there is serious doubt as to whether or not rehabilitation works. Although some forms of sentence may have particular rehabilitative effects for some offenders, it is questionable whether rehabilitation can be pursued beyond those isolated effects so as to achieve particular results. In such circumstances, rehabilitation is little more than a general and limited effect of sentencing, and does not provide sufficient justification for variations in sentence. That said, however, there should be no objection in principle to the pursuit of rehabilitative programmes in dealing with sentenced offenders (except, perhaps, where such programmes are coercive) where sentence is justified on some other grounds. We are satisfied that there is a place for such programmes and would echo the recommendations of the Whitaker Committee of Inquiry that those incarcerated by society should have caring and developmental attention.45
4.32
Deterrence, like rehabilitation, is another utilitarian concept. The object of deterrent sentencing is to restrain or dissuade persons from future criminal action either by describing the potential punishment, or by applying the punishment in order to engender fear.
4.33
It is common in discussions on deterrent sentencing to distinguish between general and individual deterrence. General deterrence is used to describe threats directed at people who have not experienced the distasteful consequences of sentence, while individual deterrence refers to threats directed against persons who have. In some of the literature on deterrence, it is only general deterrence that is classified within the concept, it being argued that any change in the behaviour of the offender, as a result of the sanction being imposed, should be treated as rehabilitation rather than deterrence.46 Essentially, however, general and individual deterrence are attempts to do the same thing: the difference is merely that the former relies on imagination, the latter on memory.47
4.34
A second distinction is between absolute and marginal deterrence.48 Absolute deterrence refers to the deterrent effect of the criminal justice system as a whole, such as the effect of a larger police force or an increase in all the maximum penalties. Marginal deterrence, on the other hand, relates to the use of deterrence in sentencing, and, as such, is the main focus of our attention. The argument in support of marginal deterrence is that an increase in a particular sentence imposed on an offender will result in an increased deterrent effect within the community.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=92 |
4.35
Deterrence, both general and individual, has been one of the traditionally accepted aims of the criminal law. Nonetheless, moral objections have been raised against the deterrent theory, in particular against general deterrence49:
... punishment on the basis of deterrence is inherently unjust. For if an example is made of a person to induce others to avoid criminal actions then he suffers not for what he has done but on account of other peoples' tendency to do likewise.50 |
4.36
Recently there has been a growing awareness of the limits of the individual deterrent effects of sentences.51 Factors such as the high recidivism rate and the undeterrability of compulsive and impulsive offenders have called the success of the goal of individual deterrence into question. It is acknowledged that a large proportion of our prison inmates have been convicted on previous occasions.52 American research on career criminals has indicated that the threat of penalty was not an important factor to them.53 In fact some offenders find it easier to bear the consequences of subsequent sentences because the uncertainty and fear elements have been removed by the experience of punishment in the past. For this reason individual deterrence theories are widely discounted, and recent deterrent thought has focussed on general deterrence.
4.37
As regards the success of general deterrent strategies, however, the realisation has been that not enough is known about their effect. Little is known about the ways in which potential offenders arrive at probabilities of detection, conviction and sentence. The US National Academy of Science's Panel on Research on Deterrence and Hesitative Effects concluded:
In summary ... we cannot yet assert that the evidence warrants an affirmative conclusion regarding deterrence. We believe scientific caution must be exercised in interpreting the limited validity of the available evidence and the number of competing explanations for the results. Our reluctance to draw stronger conclusions does not imply support for a position that deterrence does not exist, since the evidence certainly favours a proposition supporting deterrence more than it favours one asserting that deterrence is absent. The major challenge for future research is to estimate the magnitude of the effects of different sanctions on various crime types, an issue on which none of the evidence available thus far provides very useful guidance.54 |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=93 |
4.38
Nagin (cited with approval by both the Canadian Sentencing Commission and the Victorian Sentencing Committee) was more blunt:
... despite the intensity of the research effort, the empirical evidence is still not sufficient for providing a rigorous confirmation of the existence of a deterrent effect. Perhaps more important, the evidence is woefully inadequate for providing a good estimate of the magnitude of whatever effect may exist. Policy makers in the criminal justice system are done a disservice if they are left with the impression that the empirical evidence, which they themselves are frequently unable to evaluate, strongly supports the deterrence hypothesis.55 |
4.39
Other studies have come to similar conclusions.56 The Whitaker Committee noted:
It is difficult to find convincing proof that imprisonment operates as a major or universal deterrent.57 |
Some of the argument against deterrence has rested on findings that many acts, particularly acts of violence, are impulsive, while other acts are compulsive, and as such cannot be influenced by deterrents.58
4.40
On the other hand, it has been contended that deterrence is an obvious effect of having a criminal justice system which imposes legal sanctions. Historical examples in support of this are the upsurges in looting, violence and corruption which took place in Melbourne in 1923 during a police strike, and in Denmark during German occupation when the Danish police force was interned.59 Who can ever say how many are deterred from a first offence?
4.41
It is also possible that Parliament may decrease the general level of crime simply by choosing to increase the minimum sentence for all crimes. If deterrence occurs in such situations, it is not because of individual sentences, but because the system as a whole treats offenders more seriously.60
4.42
None of the empirical research alluded to contradicts the proposition that the certainty of punishment is more likely to have a deterrent effect than the severity of punishment. Beyleveld concluded that:
recorded offence rates do not vary inversely with the severity of |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=94 |
penalties (usually measured by the length of imprisonment) ... inverse relations between crime and severity (when found) are usually smaller than inverse crime-certainty relations.61 |
4.43
Our conclusions coincide with those of the Canadian Sentencing Commission:
To summarise: it is plausible to argue that a general effect of deterrence stems from the mere fact that an array of sanctions are known to be imposed with some regularity. However, it can be questioned whether legal sanctions can be used beyond their overall effect to achieve particular results (e.g., deterring a particular category of offenders, such as impaired drivers). In other words, deterrence is a general and limited consequence of sentencing. It is not a goal that can be attained with precision to accommodate particular circumstances (e.g., to suppress a wave of breaking and entering dwelling houses).62 |
4.44
Incapacitation has been defined as:
... the effect of isolating an identified offender from larger society, thereby preventing him or her from committing crimes in that society.63 |
There are two species of incapacitation, collective (or general), and selective. The former refers to a strategy which would impose a prison term on all persons convicted of crime, whilst the latter refers to incapacitative policies which attempt to predict which offenders are more likely to re-offend i.e. dangerous offenders.64
4.45
It is obvious that incapacitation is an immediate and direct effect of custodial sentences since society at large is protected from the possibility of repeat offences so long as the prisoner is detained.65 There is, consequently, little convincing argument to the effect that incapacitation cannot be achieved
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=95 |
so long, that is, as places of detention successfully contain their inmates.66
4.46
However, in relation to selective incapacitation, which relies on predictions of dangerousness, there seems to be great difficulty in finding an accurate means of predicting recidivism; many offenders predicted to be dangerous turn out to be false positives, i.e. they do not commit their expected crimes when left at large.67 The Floud Report, commissioned by the Howard League for Penal Reform, conceded that the false positive rate for predictions under its scheme of proposals was at least 50% and possibly as high as 66%.68 Similar rates were found for the American strategies proposed by Dr Peter Greenwood of the RAND Corporation.69 Floud justified these inaccuracies on a principle of just re-distribution of risk society is entitled to be relieved of the risk of being harmed, at the cost of mistakenly imprisoning an offender. However, the justice begins to wear thin70 when the best prediction rates possible are so low.
4.47
After the Floud Report, the need for selective incapacitation was questioned. The general conclusion of the Home Office's Report Taking Offenders Out of Circulation71 was that serious crimes are so infrequent that predictive sentencing lends little to policies of crime reduction. A number of criminologists have therefore concluded that incapacitative sentencing is normally unacceptable in principle and incapable of just administration in practice. Norval Morris remarked:
Since we cannot make reliable predictions of dangerous behaviour, considerations of justice forbid us to confine people against their wishes in the name of public safety for longer periods than we can justify on other grounds.72 |
4.48
Radzinowicz and Hood add that the concept of 'dangerousness' is so insidious that it should never be introduced in penal legislation.73
4.49
It may be argued that incapacitation is at odds with our constitutional jurisprudence, since it punishes the offender without trial or conviction, contrary to the principles laid down by the Supreme Court in The People (AG) v O'Callaghan74 and Ryan v DPP.75 While, as we shall see, there is some
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=96 |
judicial support for that view, it cannot be regarded as conclusive. The better view would appear to be that, however frail incapacitation may be, viewed in penological or sociological terms, there is no good reason for treating it as constitutionally suspect.
4.50
In this context, it is essential to bear in mind the distinction between the situations addressed in O'Callaghan and Ryan and those now under consideration. Where an accused person is refused bail because of the alleged likelihood that he or she will commit offences while at liberty, this can only be on the factual basis that he or she has in the past committed crimes while on bail or because he or she now stands charged with crimes so serious that the risk cannot be taken, in the interests of society, of leaving him or her at large pending trial. The law must assume, however, that he or she has received the appropriate punishment for the crimes he or she has already committed. Thus, the only factual justification for depriving him or her of liberty is the possibility, or even the probability, that he or she will commit crimes in the future. He or she is thus, unarguably, being punished for crimes that he or she has never committed and, ex hypothesi, will never commit. There is thus an irreconcilable conflict with the constitutional imperative identified by Walsh J in O'Callaghan, i.e. that no person should be punished in respect of any matter upon which he or she has not been convicted.76
4.51
In contrast, in the cases now under consideration, the sentence in question is expressly imposed as a punishment for a crime in respect of which the person has been convicted. It is, of course, true that, in such cases, the court in imposing the sentence is expressly taking into account the fact that it will defer the accused's return to a life of crime. It may be that, as we have already observed, the actual incidence of recidivism renders dubious the penological justification for this approach, but that argument goes to the supposed efficacy of the sentence and not its constitutional propriety. It may even be that the form of sentence is constitutionally suspect, but, if it is, it must be for reasons different from those which invalidated the deprivation of bail in Ryan and O'Callaghan, where the imprisonment of the applicants constituted a punishment for offences which they had not committed and could never commit.
4.52
The fallacy underlying the constitutional criticism of incapacitation may be illustrated by an example. Two people are convicted of taking part in an armed robbery. Criminal A with no previous convictions, admits his guilt from the outset, co-operates with the Gardai and impresses the prison authorities during his period on remand with his desire for rehabilitation. Criminal B has a lengthy record of previous convictions, refuses to co-operate in any way and maintains a defiant plea of not guilty, but is none the less convicted. Criminal A is given a six year sentence and criminal B a ten year sentence. In passing sentence on A, the judge says that a lesser sentence is being imposed in the belief that, having regard to his lack of previous convictions and his conduct since
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=97 |
his arrest, there is some prospect that he will abandon the life of crime which he has embarked on when he is released.
4.53
This is an example of the rehabilitative approach which we have already discussed. No one has suggested that it is constitutionally frail. Indeed, it is in total harmony with the views expressed on a number of occasions in the Court of Criminal Appeal as to the objects which should be borne in mind when sentence is being imposed. Yet, by inevitable implication, B, in the example cited, is deprived of four years of liberty, precisely because the trial judge considers that the likelihood in his case is that he will return to his life of crime. If one were to use language in a loose and vague sense, one would then say that B is being punished for a crime he has never committed. But this analysis demonstrates how misleading and imprecise that description is: it would be more accurate to say that B is punished for a crime of which he has unquestionably been convicted, but the court, in imposing sentence, is having regard to the likelihood of his future conduct on release, based on the information available to the court, including his previous convictions.
4.54
The criticism on constitutional grounds of incapacitation also fails to take into account the fact that the sentencing process necessarily excludes the rigid application of certain norms of the criminal law which can be regarded as, in other contexts, essential aspects of the constitutional guarantee of fair procedures. Thus, it is a fundamental maxim of the law that a person may not be convicted twice of the same crime: nemo debet bis vexari pro eadem causa. Yet this maxim is in theory violated every time a trial judge imposes a heavier sentence because of the accused's previous criminal record. In many cases, particularly where more than one defendant is before the court, there is no difficulty in identifying the additional period which the court has added to a sentence because of the accused's previous convictions. Yet he or she has already received the appropriate punishment in respect of those convictions so that it is impossible to avoid a conclusion that he or she is being punished again for the same offence. There may indeed be those who would argue that there is a basic injustice in this system and that a person is entitled to be regarded as having a clean slate for every purpose, including punishment for a subsequent offence, once he or she has, in the familiar cliche, paid his debt to society.
4.55
But if that is in truth the position, then it has to be said that an enormous number of sentences which have been imposed by the courts since the foundation of the State were vitiated by a fundamental constitutional frailty. We unhesitatingly prefer the view that, in the matter of sentencing, the maxim nemo debet bis vexari must yield to the common good which requires that each individual should be punished according to his or her specific circumstances, including, where relevant, his previous criminal record.
4.56
As we have mentioned, there is one authority which might suggest a
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=98 |
different view, i.e. The People (DPP) v Carmody.77 In that case, the applicants were habitual criminals, the first applicant having convictions beginning in 1968 and the second applicant having convictions dating back to 1961. The convictions were, in the main, for burglary. They had served numerous terms of imprisonment imposed by the District Court, primarily for periods up to 12 months. In the instant case, they were charged with burglary and pleaded guilty to the charges in the Circuit Court. The Circuit Court judge, Judge Murphy, imposed a sentence of six years imprisonment on each applicant, stating that the applicants were not:
amenable in any manner to the ordinary constrictions of the society in which they live and ... are preying on innocent people ... my primary duty is to protect those people.78 |
4.57
The Court of Criminal Appeal substituted a sentence of three years imprisonment in each case. For the court, McCarthy J, having cited the remarks of the learned trial judge, went on to quote the passage from the judgment of Walsh J in O'Callaghan79 which we have already discussed. However, the learned judge also referred to the observation of Walsh J. in The People v O'Driscoll80 that the objects of passing sentence are not merely to deter a particular criminal from committing a crime but to induce him or her in so far as possible to turn from a criminal to an honest life. McCarthy J also referred to section 10 of the Prevention of Crime Act providing for the preventative detention of habitual criminals and to the fact that there were no facilities in the State for providing such detention. He then added:
The court is satisfied that the only justification for the radical departure from the previous measures of imprisonment, mostly at District court level, was an understandable attempt to procure reform by prevention. Absent the use of appropriate statutory provisions, however, such is not an acceptable basis for the particular sentence.81 |
4.58
It is not clear, accordingly, whether the Court was suggesting that an incapacitative approach was invalid having regard to the provisions of the Constitution, because of the principles laid down in O'Callaghan. That would seem to be one reading of the judgment. On the other hand, the reference by McCarthy J to the absence of appropriate statutory provisions would suggest, by implication at least, that, were such statutory provisions in place, they would not be constitutionally invalid. The judgment, with respect, does not make it clear why the courts, on whom the exclusive constitutional responsibility of imposing sentence rests, are in some sense precluded from laying down a rule which, it would seem, is within the competence of the Oireachtas to lay down. Apart altogether from that consideration, it is our view that the authority of the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=99 |
judgment is weakened by the fact that it does not address the arguable distinction that exists between the withholding of bail from an innocent person and the imposition of sentence on a guilty person and which, as we have already suggested, is a crucial distinction between the Ryan situation and the Carmody situation.
4.59
As we have pointed out, a number of criminologists have concluded that incapacitative sentencing is normally unacceptable in principle and incapable of just administration in practice. We would reiterate our view, however, that, if the burden of criminological opinion was to contrary effect, there would be no constitutional objection to the courts adopting an incapacitative approach where that was appropriate.
4.60
Another disturbing feature of incapacitative ideology is the fact that theories of selective incapacitation for serious offenders accept the notion of there being a certain class of offenders meriting different treatment to other offenders.82 It is unjust, if not unconstitutional to put someone in jail on the basis of a judgment about a class, however accurate, because that denies his or her claim to equal respect as an individual.83 It is even more heinous if the judgment is based (as it was proposed in some American schemes) not on the criminality of the offender at all, but on factors such as employment history or drug addiction.84 This notion can be strongly argued to be repugnant to our Constitution which places primary emphasis on the rights of the individual.85
4.61
The object of compensating the victim requires the offender to make reparation or to pay compensation for injury caused to his or her victim in circumstances where the conduct of the offender is criminal.86 It seems that the payment of compensation by the offender to the victim or the victim's kin formed the basis of the early criminal law. Payments were scaled in accordance with the seriousness of the injury and the social standing of the parties involved.87 As State involvement in the criminal law grew, so too did the notion that crime was an injury against the State rather than against the individual victim. So the State began to claim an increasing proportion of the compensation.88 Gradually, two distinct and separate types of proceedings arose out of criminal conduct; criminal proceedings, by the State for infraction of a public duty, and civil proceedings by the victim for infringement of a private right. Compensation of the victim became the principal remedy of the law of torts, which aims to achieve restitutio
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=100 |
in integrum, while the criminal law concerned itself with more penal considerations.
4.62
In recent times it has been thought to be absurd that the State should undertake to protect the public from crime and then, when crime occurs, take the entire payment but offer no effective89 remedy to the victim.90 Consequently, some statutory provisions were enacted to enable sentencers to order the offender to pay compensation to the victim.91 These, however, have been piecemeal and of little practical value to victims.92 In practice the courts have introduced the idea of compensation into the terms and conditions of other orders, such as postponed sentences, even though this practice has no statutory basis.93
4.63
Compensation seeks to justify sentencing on the basis that it addresses the primary concerns of the victim of crime. These are thought to be:94
|
The theory is, thus, both punitive and utilitarian; it seeks to punish the offender95 and to provide some benefits to the victim.
4.64
The theory is, however, beset by a number of practical difficulties which call the efficacy of compensation theories into question. To begin with, compensation depends on the economic means of the offender.96 The danger, thus, is that the offender will not have the means to compensate the victim. Secondly, not all crimes are against readily identifiable victims, e.g. traffic
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=101 |
offences. In many cases, therefore, it is difficult to determine who should be compensated. Thirdly, compensation theory fails to take into account the fact that the criminal law has other concerns such as ensuring that the law is observed.
4.65
Since compensation depends on the economic means of the offender, principles of sentencing which have compensation of the victim as their basis carry the danger of discriminating between wealthy and less wealthy offenders wealthy offenders being in a better position to escape punishment because of their economic status.97 The end result of this is disparity in the way in which offenders are treated. Another problem is the fact that under a compensation approach a detailed examination of the extent of the loss or injury suffered by the victim has to be conducted. This can lead to significant delays in the criminal justice process, requiring the criminal justice system to enforce what are essentially civil proceedings. Some jurisdictions have confined the use of compensation orders to situations in which no civil proceedings against the offender are contemplated by the victim.98
4.66
Sentencing, as a means of providng compensation, has a number of drawbacks. It is doubtful if sentencing can adequately achieve this objective in the great majority of cases. Sentencing is a haphazard means of securing compensation because the offender may, after all, be impecunious. It is, nonetheless, an undeniable fact that compensation of the victim is desirable where it may be achieved99 and we are at one with the Whitaker Committee on this. On the whole, however, there is only limited scope for this, and there is still the danger that wealthy or well heeled offenders may be able to buy their way out of justice.
4.67
Our examination of the way in which the traditional objects of sentencing answer the question why does the criminal justice system sentence offenders? leads us to a number of conclusions. The capacity of the utilitarian concepts of rehabilitation, deterrence, incapacitation, and, compensation (in so far as it is utilitarian) to achieve their objectives has been thrown into doubt by the results of research. On the other hand, retributive justifications for the imposition of criminal sanctions do not rest on a secure foundation. What we are left with are doubts about the traditional, utilitarian justifications for sentencing, one weak moral justification the success of which cannot be appraised and a general feeling, which cannot be substantiated, that the imposition of criminal sanctions may have some effect on crime prevention and crime control because of
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=102 |
deterrent or incapacitative effects. We know a lot about what punishment cannot achieve, but we know a lot less about what it can achieve. There is no simple answer to the question why does the criminal justice system sentence offenders?. It is in this context that decisions about the distribution of sentence will have to take place.
4.68
These conclusions suggest restraint in the distribution of sentence. Since criminal sanctions involve pain and deprivation, they should be used all the more sparingly if we are uncertain of their benefits either to society or to its individual members.100
4.69
It should also be remembered that the capacity of sentencing to achieve its objectives will be conditioned by other elements within the overall criminal justice system. Sentencing is only one stage in a number of stages concerned with the enforcement of the criminal law, each of which has its own decision making processes and its own personnel to make those decisions. Sentencers have little control over what happens to offenders in the pre-sentencing and post-sentencing stages of the criminal justice system, such as deciding when to initiate prosecution, or deciding when a prisoner should be released from prison. This places dramatic limits on what sentencing may achieve: for example, if a sentencer imposes a severe sentence in order to deter the offender, the sentence might later be deprived of deterrent effect by an executive decision to grant a full temporary release in order to rehabilitate (or, perhaps, simply to abate prison overcrowding).101
4.70
Another limit on the capacity of sentencing is the low percentage of offenders it actually deals with. To begin with, it is not known what percentage of the offences which actually occur are reported to the prosecuting authorities, although it is not unreasonable to assume that a sizeable proportion of offences against the person go unreported with the exception of high visibility, serious crimes such as murder.102
4.71
Nor will every offender who is detected come before the courts at the sentencing stage. The prosecutorial agencies may decide not to prosecute the matter, and even if they do, there may not be a conviction.
4.72
The fact that the application of the sentencing process is limited to a very small proportion of actual offenders casts further doubt on the idea that sentencing functions to protect the public and to prevent crime.103 The goal
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=103 |
of protecting the public from offenders and preventing crime is better viewed as the preserve of the entire criminal justice system, achieved through the work of the investigatory and policing agencies such as the Garda Sνochαna and the various Governmental agencies concerned with the control and regulation of agriculture, fisheries and health etc. rather than as the primary responsibility of the courts.
4.73
The principle of desert as a means of restricting the distribution of sentence in accordance with principles of fundamental justice and parsimony has proved attractive in jurisdictions in which reform of the sentencing process has taken place. This principle has become known as just deserts. Interest in the just deserts theory as a fundamental basis for sentencing reform has increased since the 1970s with the publication of several works on deservedness,104 and it has become influential in sentencing reform in the United States,105 Canada,106 Australian Federal Jurisdiction107 and Victoria,108 Sweden,109 Finland,110 and, lately, Britain.111 Such reform has begun with the recognition of just-deserts as an integral part of criminal sanction, regardless of its ultimate purpose, and has followed the just deserts premise that punishment should be imposed only in a just and fair manner. The main advantages of just deserts centre around the concept of justice (which, admittedly, can be somewhat nebulous in character). The following principal characteristics of the just deserts principle are generally accepted as promoting the aim of justice:112
|
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=104 |
4.74
In a recent English survey, Walker and Hough found that the most popular type of sentencing system was one which gives the offender what he deserves.113 Thus it is argued that a sentencing system based on just deserts is likely to improve public support for and confidence in sentencing and the criminal justice system.114
4.75
The just deserts principle of distribution requires the severity of the sentence to be in proportion to the seriousness of the offending behaviour. Just deserts has sometimes been suspected of simply being retribution revamped. But Andrew von Hirsch, the leading exponent of the philosophy, explains the difference thus:
The principle of commensurate-deserts addresses the question of allocation of punishments that is, how much to punish convicted offenders. This allocation question is distinct from the issue of the general justification of punishment namely, why the institution of punishment should exist at all.115 |
4.76
Seriousness, under the just deserts theory, is gauged by reference to two factors:116
|
4.77
The role of harm in gauging the seriousness of the offending conduct is nothing new: for example, the maximum penalty for murder has always been set at a higher level than that for assault because of the greater harm which results from the former. By focussing on the degree of harm, the just deserts theory directs sentencers to give more consideration to the harmfulness of the offending conduct within the scale of maximum or minimum penalties. This in turn should stimulate the development of more sophisticated doctrines on how to assess harm. In some jurisdictions, reforms have gone so far as to pre-determine these
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=105 |
relationships for the sentencing judges by getting sentencing commissions to produce elaborate grids or tables of appropriate sentences for given offences. Some research has already shown that the degree of harm caused or risked can be gauged by reference to the public perception of the seriousness of such conduct.117 Others have countered that the harmfulness of criminal conduct should not be measured by what people think it is, but by what it really is.118 A simple criterion might be the amount of violence involved but one can see the limitations of this when economic crimes (which do not, normally, involve violence) are considered.
4.78
Von Hirsch suggests a broader criterion well suited to both the judicial assessment of harm and the assessment of harm by a sentencing commission: harms may be graded according to the degree to which they restrict peoples' ability to direct the course of their own lives.119 Thus, for example, murder is the gravest harm, since it deprives the victim completely of his or her choices; and economic crimes are also accounted for, because they threaten peoples' choice of livelihood.120 Of course, this test needs to be developed to deal with crimes such as tax evasion which injure collective interests but it is doubtless a start.
4.79
Culpability is already a factor of some importance in the criminal law. Culpability refers to the factors of intent, motive and circumstance that determine how much the offender should be held responsible for his or her actions, and, as such, affects the assessment of harm: The consequences that should be considered in gauging the harmfullness of an act should be those that can fairly be attributed to the actor's choice.121 The substantive criminal law already provides some principles for the assessment of punishment on the basis of culpability duress, provocation, and ignorance of the law are not normally defences to liability for the crime itself, but are frequently availed of as excuses in mitigation of the severity of sentence.122 By explicitly emphasising culpability, the just deserts theory calls upon the sentencing courts (or sentencing commissions in jurisdictions where such bodies have been set up to establish sentencing guidelines) to calibrate the individual sentence more carefully according to the degree of harmfulness which may fairly be attributed to the offender's choice.123
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=106 |
4.80
An important characteristic of the just deserts theory is the assertion that the principle of proportionality must be given priority in deciding the level of sentence. Two forms of proportionality are involved in just deserts.
4.81
The first, cardinal proportionality, is concerned that the absolute level of the penalty scale should not be disproportionate to the magnitude of the offending behaviour. The US Committee for the Study of Incarceration observed that:
The principle of commensurate deserts imposes, in the first place, an ordering of penalties. Punishments are to be arranged so that their relative painfulness corresponds with the comparative seriousness of offences.124 |
4.82
The Australian Law Reform Commission added that:
A criminal justice system which delivered punishments that were excessively harsh would be as ineffective and unjust as one which delivered punishments that were too lenient. In the latter case, the law is likely to be simply disregarded. In the former, informal means may well be taken to avoid subjecting offenders to the excessively harsh punishments. The level of severity of punishment must strike a balance between these two extremes .... Striking that balance necessarily involves selecting a punishment that conforms to the so-called 'principle of parsimony' or 'economy' the punishment chosen should not exceed that which is necessary in the circumstances.125 |
4.83
The second limb of the proportionality requirement, ordinal proportionality, requires that a sentence should be determined by comparison with similar criminal acts and compared to crimes of a more or a less serious nature. The sentence ought to reflect the relative reprehensibleness of those acts .... [O]rdinal proportionality is concerned with preserving a correspondence between relative seriousness of behaviour and relative severity of sentence ....126 The Committee for the Study of Incarceration observed that:
Spacing is likewise important: penalties ought not, for example, to be crowded together so closely as to obscure distinctions in seriousness among offences. The principle also requires that infractions of equal seriousness be punished with equal severity. For a given category of offence, therefore, a specific penalty level should be set that is applicable to all instances, except when special aggravating or mitigating circumstances can be shown to have existed.... Commensurate deserts restricts severe punishments to serious crimes. The penalty scale ought not be inflated so much that non-serious crimes also receive severe |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=107 |
penalties (severe, that is, ... in [a] sense of being very unpleasant, given the prevailing tolerances for suffering). Severe punishments for non-serious offences overstate blame: the offender is being treated as more reprehensible than the harmfulness of his acts (and the extent of his culpability) justify. This objection holds even if the whole scale has been elevated so much that the penalty ranks low in comparative harshness alongside other penalties. Irrespective of other penalties, when an offender has been visited with much suffering the implicit condemnation is great ....127 |
4.84
It is the requirement of ordinal proportionality which elevates the just deserts principle from the status of a mere limiting principle to that of a determining principle.128 A limiting principle sets the upper limit of the penalty which may be imposed, but does not define its extent below that. For example, the pure retributive principle of desert is a limiting principle. It requires that punishment should not exceed the seriousness of the crime but it does not prevent punishment from being less severe than that merited by the crime. Just deserts, on the other hand, is a determining principle, because it actually defines the magnitude of the penalty; i.e. it must not be less severe than other penalties for less serious crimes. The US Committee for the Study of Incarceration commented:
Imposing only a slight penalty for a serious offence treats the offender as less blameworthy than he deserves. Understating the blame depreciates the values that are involved: disproportionately lenient punishment for murder implies that human life the victim's life is not worthy of much concern; excessively mild penalties for official corruption denigrate the importance of an equitable political process. The commensurateness principle, in our view, bars excessive leniency as well as disproportionate severity.129 |
4.85
First, there is the task of fixing the levels of proportionality which are required by the theory. There are three means by which these levels can be determined:
|
4.86
Since there is no fixed notion of how to fix the overall level of penalties so as to achieve cardinal proportionality, then, in order to fix a starting point, difficult decisions have to be made. The just deserts principle proceeds on the assumption that one can arrive at a degree of consensus concerning these issues.130 Some have argued strongly in favour of a reduction in the severity of the penal sanctions as part of their just deserts approach, whilst others have employed a greater use of custodial sentences as part of theirs.131 In the USA deterrence has been relevant in determining the appropriate scale.132 Commonly, confusion has arisen between the just deserts philosophy and the underlying justifying aims which some jurisdictions have continued to employ. Some jurisdictions have, pragmatically, adopted a descriptive system.
4.87
Next is the matter of ordinal proportionality. Since the just deserts theory requires that a serious offence not be punished more leniently than a less serious one, (i) a hierarchy of crimes has to be constructed i.e. crimes will have to be ranked in order of seriousness, and (ii) a hierarchy of penalties, i.e. all sanctions should be ranked in order of severity. Such hierarchies can be constructed either before a just deserts sentencing regime is effected, or they can be developed by the courts once such a system is put into operation.
4.88
Independently developing a hierarchy of penalties is not, as it may seem to be, such a difficult task; it could, theoretically, be measured by reference to public opinion.133 The approach of jurisdictions such as Michigan134 has been to use a descriptive rather than a prescriptive system of measurement to arrange a hierarchical ordering. This approach plainly necessitates the rigorous examination of current practice and the compilation of statistics but the task is by no means impossible.
4.89
In a hierarchy of penalties, all the sentencing options would have to be viewed in terms of the degree to which they deprive the offender of his rights. Imprisonment, naturally enough, would be the most serious penalty. The fine, would be well suited for offences in the middle of the range of seriousness where imprisonment is considered to be too severe.135 Similarly, community service may be viewed as a lesser sanction in that it deprives the offender of leisure and
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=109 |
exacts unpaid labour.136 Discharges would then suit the least serious offences. As for probation, the punitive element can be found in the conditions which are imposed. However, it would not be easy to accommodate the suspended prison sentence, since, in terms of discomfort to the offender, it has most in common with the conditional discharge; yet it involves a giant step in severity for the act of default. Clearly a sentencing framework based on deserts can incorporate extensive use of non-custodial sentences. They would no longer be associated primarily with rehabilitative aims nor be regarded merely as substitutes for incarceration.137 They would instead be seen as penalties in their own right, ranged on a scale below immediate custody, and involving varying degrees of punitiveness.138 The Whitaker Report shows much in favour of such a principle. It says of probation orders:
since they restrict the offender's freedom of choice and have specific guarantees of compliance they must be regarded as a form of punishment ...139 |
4.90
The task of constructing a hierarchy of crimes is complicated by the large range of crimes. Nonetheless, in the United States, sentencing commissions which have been given this task have been able to formulate rankings of seriousness for their guidelines without generating controversy, which may indicate that the task is a manageable one if approached rationally.140 A feature of the US rankings has been the construction of a sentencing grid or table.141 A disadvantage of these grids is their inflexibility, and their occasional failure to take important circumstances into account when addressing the seriousness of offending behaviour. The Australian Law Reform Commission was, thus, less than enthusiastic about such ranking of offences according to seriousness:
In the Commission's view, it is not possible to impose a rigid structure for this purpose. Individual variations, especially of the circumstances and characteristics of offenders, cannot be exhaustively listed. For this reason, the Commission accepts that the present role of the courts in exercising the sentencing discretion should remain.142 |
4.91
This is also the procedure envisaged by the British Government in its recent sentencing reform.143
4.92
However, in order to give the courts a starting point from which to
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=110 |
develop a structure for determining the seriousness of a given offence, many jurisdictions have reviewed their set of maximum penalties so as to produce a working hierarchy of maxima. This hierarchy gives sentencers some idea of the seriousness of an offence compared to other offences, and assists them in choosing the level of severity of sentence by giving them an example of the sentence suitable for the worst example of that offence.144
4.93
The Canadian Sentencing Commission undertook the ranking in order of seriousness of the over 300 offences in their Criminal Code, Narcotic Control Act, and Food and Drugs Act. The Commission said:
Ranking all the criminal offences under consideration by this Commission was a complex and time-consuming exercise. As in determining the scale of maximum penalties, reference had to be made to policy, theory and data on sentencing practice. The ranking also drew upon the diverse experiences of the Commissioners, the findings of public opinion research, similar exercises by sentencing commissions in other jurisdictions, and research on the penalty structures in other countries. Thus it was a multi-stage process in which the subsequent ranking was refined to reflect these diverse sources of information. The final step involved a comparison between the ultimate ranking by the Commissioners and rankings derived from members of the public. This revealed a high degree of consistency between the two populations. Hence, although one can never say with empirical certainty that a certain crime is worse than another in all circumstances, some consensus exists on the perceived seriousness of different offences.145 |
4.94
In its Discussion Paper, Sentencing: Penalties, the Australian Law Reform Commission agreed with the hierarchical ranking of maximum penalties in terms of offence seriousness:
Offences should be divided into specified categories according to seriousness. This ranking should take into account both public perception and sentencing practice. It is tentatively proposed that there be eight categories of offences. The proposed hierarchy is not comprehensive.146 |
4.95
In its final report, the Commission upheld this view, adding that:
In the long run, a review of this kind would make a significant contribution to the development of coherent and consistent sentencing |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=111 |
policy and practice.147 |
4.96
Another issue which has to be addressed in developing a just deserts approach is whether or not a prior criminal record is to be considered a relevant factor in determining the deservedness of a particular sanction by a particular offender. Most penal systems impose less punishment on first offenders than on those who have previous convictions. Yet desert theorists have argued that considering the prior offence record is not germane to an offenders deserts the person has been punished already for his earlier convictions; therefore the existence of prior record is irrelevant.148
4.97
The issue of prior record show up the tension between the philosophies of due process (in the form of just deserts) and crime control. A crime control approach might approve of incapacitating recidivists by imposing longer custodial sentences on them, but departures of this kind challenge the philosophical underpinnings of just deserts.149 Nonetheless, within certain limitations, prior record may be relevant to the culpability of the offender for the offending behaviour, particularly if the prior offence is sufficiently close in nature, seriousness and time to the the offence for which the offender is being sentenced. Many desert theorists, thus, continue to concede a limited role to prior criminal record.150 This issue will be examined in detail in Chapter 6.
4.98
Since the just deserts theory relies only on the seriousness of the offending behaviour to determine the extent or severity of sentence, the only factors which will be relevant in mitigation will be those which reduce the seriousness of the offending behaviour. Thus, if just deserts were to be adopted as the sole or dominant principle by which sentence could be determined, many of the traditional grounds of mitigation of sentence151 would be lost; e.g. the impact the sentence may have on third parties dependent on the offender. This may pose a problem if the traditional factors which mitigate sentence are still thought to be important in their own right.
4.99
The solution to this problem in most jurisdictions which have adopted a just deserts approach has been to give sentencers a list of exceptional factors which may be considered in mitigating the sentence of the offender.152 The task of compiling such a list is not a difficult one, but it does require some
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=112 |
careful thought, particularly in this jurisdiction where there is not available a ready consensus or set of precedents which set out the factors commonly taken into account by our sentencers.153 These issues are dealt with in detail in the next chapter.
4.100
Finally, there lies the deepest criticism of the just deserts theory, i.e. that it is an uncaring means of dealing with offenders, because it ignores the causes of crime and shows little interest in constructive ways of tackling crime.154 This is an echo of the traditional criticism of retribution, made, usually, by those who confuse just deserts with retributivism. However, it is true that just deserts provides no justification for the imposition of sentence, and its principles give little recognition to policies of crime prevention and control. For this reason just deserts should be seen only as a foundation for distribution of sentences, and not a rationale for the criminal justice system as a whole. For example, correctional institutions may continue to maintain rehabilitative programmes in their treatment of offenders (provided there are sufficient arguments in their favour) within the just deserts sentencing framework.155 Other objects may also be pursued.
4.101
As we have already stated, the just deserts theory does not exclude consideration of the traditional objects, which may be considered so long as they do not violate the requirements of cardinal and ordinal proportionality. Certain hybrid schemes have been developed with the purpose of linking the just deserts approach with traditional justification for punishment.
4.102
Hybrid principles involve the consideration of more than one principle of distribution. To be coherent, however, they require a structure or a system of priorities which resolves conflicts which may arise between conflicting principles. Jareborg describes two means by which this can be achieved:156 (i) giving different principles priority in different areas of application, say for different types of crime, or for different types of penalty; or (ii) ranking different principles in order of priority.
4.103
Recent years have seen a growing interest in the construction of hybrid models for the distribution of sentence, although as yet these experiments have for the most part,157 not influenced sentencing reform. Foremost amongst these theories are those of Professor Paul Robinson, former commissioner with
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=113 |
the US Sentencing Commission.158
4.104
This scheme recognises the dominance of the just deserts theory as the most suitable single principle for distribution, but he observes that pure just deserts principles may impose sanctions which occasionally cost more than the crime they prevent, and fail to impose sanctions where opportunities for efficient crime prevention are great. His hybrid scheme identifies the alignments of conflict which may arise in sentencing as (a) just deserts vs deterrence and incapacitation; (b) deterrence vs just deserts and incapacitation; and (c) incapacitation vs just deserts and deterrence.159 Robinson then puts forward a number of mechanisms that may be adopted to define which purpose should be followed when a conflict of purposes arises in any given situation.160
4.105
Perhaps the most appealing of Robinson's mechanisms is the method of sanction,161 under which, so long as just deserts is followed to decide the extent of sentence (i.e. severity), other objects may be considered to decide the nature of punishment (i.e. the method by which punishment is carried out). If, for example, a brief period of imprisonment is about as severe as a stiff noncustodial sentence, the choice between these penalties might be made on the grounds of incapacitation.
If one month in the state prison is the punitive equivalent to five months of weekends in the local jail, then desert is satisfied even if the more blameworthy offender gets probation, with a condition of seven months of weekends in jail, while the less blameworthy offender goes to prison for one month.162 |
4.106
One vital requirement is noted:
It is critical, of course, that the sanction equivalencies be properly set. |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=114 |
Some empirical research has been done on perceptions of relative seriousness of sanctions163 but the work is still in its infancy. |
4.107
In some situations, however, it may be unnecessary to establish sanction equivalencies. For example a very lengthy or life sentence can clearly satisfy the goals of retribution or incapacitation, but there is simply no rehabilitative alternative.164 What are we to do, for example, with a murderer desperately in need of rehabilitation?165 The limitations of the choice of method hybrid should, thus, be noted it does not propose to provide utilitarian solutions to all sentencing decisions; it merely uses utilitarian knowledge to answer questions which have no answer in just deserts principles.
4.108
The separation of the extent of sentence from its nature has a number of advantages. For one thing, broad judicial discretion can be maintained in determining the nature of sentence within a narrow framework of judicial discretion as to the extent of sentence (such as guideline sentencing grids),166 thus satisfying those who object to the deprivation of judicial discretion at the sentencing stage. Secondly, leaving the decision as to the nature of sentence to the judiciary is justified because principles for selecting the appropriate method of sentence are as yet less obvious than principles for determining its extent. Thirdly, by allowing the nature issue to rely on the known effects of certain types of sentence, sentencing can make use of the knowledge that is available about the utilitarian effects of sentencing, even though such knowledge might not be sufficient to provide a basis for the use of utilitarian principles of distribution. Thus the choice of method hybrid is flexible enough to include consideration of aims such as redress for the community or the individual victims of crime.
4.109
We now make the following provisional recommendations.
We provisionally recommend that the legislature sets out by way of statute a clear statement that the sentence to be imposed on an offender be determined by reference to the just deserts principle of sentencing and that the legislation should include the following provisions:
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=115 |
The severity of the sentence to be imposed on a person found guilty of an offence should be measured in proportion to the seriousness of the offending behaviour.
The seriousness of offending behaviour should be measured by reference to:
|
4.110
We provisionally recommend that the legislation employ a choice of method hybrid for the determination of which of two or more competing sanctions of equal severity should be imposed. The following provisions should be included:
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=117 |
5.1
In Chapter 11 we noted a distinction between two types of factors which may have an aggravating or mitigating effect on the severity of the sentence to be imposed. These we classed as
|
5.2
The former concern the circumstances of the offending behaviour, such as the type of harm caused and the degree of intent of the offender; but the latter concern the personal circumstances of the offender which do not relate to the offending behaviour, such as the impact the sentence may have on the offender or on others dependent on him or her. In this Chapter we examine both types of aggravating or mitigating factors to determine their role in the just deserts sentencing system proposed by this paper.
5.3
It should be stressed that the factors which we are examining here are factors which should be considered by the sentencer when determining the severity of the sentence to be imposed. When a factor is found to be irrelevant to this decision, that is not to say that it is irrelevant to all of the decisions to be made in sentencing it may still be of relevance when determining the type of sentence to be imposed where there is available to the sentencer a range of sentence types of equivalent severity. For example, if the fact that the sentence would deprive the offender's family of parental support is considered not to be relevant to sentence severity, it may nonetheless be a valid factor in persuading the sentencer to choose community service over imprisonment where the terms
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=118 |
of each sentence are thought to be equivalent.
5.4
We should begin by explaining the importance of the distinction between factors which aggravate or mitigate the offence and factors which mitigate sentence.
5.5
To begin with, they arise at different stages of the sentencing decision. Factors which aggravate or mitigate the offence arise for consideration when the sentencer is deciding the seriousness of the offending conduct for which the offender is to be held responsible. Although this may include a consideration of the state of mind or the culpability of the offender during the commission of the offence, the sentencer is, at this stage, primarily concerned with the offending behaviour rather than with the offender personally.
5.6
Factors which mitigate sentence arise later. When the sentencer considers these factors, he or she has decided the seriousness of the offending conduct for which the offender is responsible, but now asks if there is any reason why the offender should not suffer the full punishment which should attach to such responsibility or blameworthiness. Mitigation of sentence is the making of a concession: the sentencer is saying although you are undoubtedly responsible for the offending conduct and should be punished for it, I am letting you off a little because of your personal circumstances.
5.7
If there is confusion between the two types of factors a problem arises. If the confused sentencer takes factors which mitigate sentence into account at the determination of seriousness stage then the offender will be found to be less responsible or blameworthy than he or she actually is. The following example may help to make this clear.
5.8
Let us say that an offender is being sentenced for a rape in which he was the ringleader of a group of offenders and in which he, but not the others, used a great deal of violence. Let us also say that the offender is a single parent and there is no other relative or friend who can look after the child. If the sentencer, when determining the seriousness of the offence, takes into account not only the fact that the offender acted as ringleader and used violence as factors which aggravate the offence but also the fact that the offender leaves behind a child with no one to care for it as a factor which mitigates the offence, then the offence will be considered to be less serious than it actually was; the offender's conduct could even end up being viewed as less serious than that of his co-offenders who played lesser roles in the rape and who did not use violence.
5.9
At the end of the day it may not matter to the sentence whether the personal factors entered into the calculation of the seriousness of the offence or whether they were kept until later as factors which mitigate sentence the final sentence will probably be substantially the same. What does matter, however, is that the sentencing process fails to recognise the full extent of the offender's
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=119 |
blameworthiness and to make him or her accountable for it when factors which mitigate sentence are mistaken for factors which mitigate the offence. There is much to be said, therefore, for a sentencing provision of some sort which would direct the attention of sentencers to the distinction between factors which aggravate or mitigate the offence and factors which mitigate sentence.
5.10
Secondly, the distinction between factors which aggravate or mitigate the offence and factors which mitigate sentence must be clearly maintained when considering their respective roles in a just deserts sentencing system.
5.11
In current sentencing practice, where sentences may be imposed on the basis of rehabilitative, deterrent, or incapacitative principles, aggravation of offence and mitigation of both kinds may sometimes be dispensed with, as Thomas explains:
(A)llowance for mitigation is not considered to be an entitlement of the offender. The sentencer may withhold a reduction which might normally be expected if some recognised penal objective such as general deterrence or the preventive confinement of a dangerous offender, requires the imposition of the whole of the permissible sentence.2 |
5.12
The determination of sentence following rehabilitative, deterrent or incapacitative principles does not require any consideration of the seriousness of the offending behaviour and, thus, does not involve any consideration of factors which aggravate or mitigate the offence since these types of sentence are based on the likelihood of the offender or others re-offending rather than on the gravity of the offence.
5.13
However, in a just deserts system, the principle of proportionality between offence and sentence serves as the foundation of every sentence. Thus, factors which aggravate or mitigate the offence logically have a prior claim on the sentencer's attention since they form part of the determination of proportionality itself.3 Therefore, contrary to Thomas's assessment of current sentencing practice, in a just deserts system allowance for mitigation of the offence should be regarded as an entitlement of the offender. Furthermore, making allowance for factors which aggravate the offence should also be regarded as an essential element in the sentencing decision. If a factor which aggravates or mitigates the offence is not taken into consideration by the sentencer the oversight should form a valid ground for appeal against sentence because of disproportionality either by the offender where the sentence is disproportionately severe because a factor which mitigates the offence has been excluded, or by the prosecution where the sentence is disproportionately lenient because a factor which aggravates the offence has been excluded.4 There would be much benefit in some sort of provision which would make it clear to sentencers that consideration of the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=120 |
factors which aggravate or mitigate the offence is essential in every sentencing decision and that it is no longer the case that allowance for these factors is at the discretion of the sentencer.
5.14
However, different considerations apply to factors which mitigate sentence. Since they are not concerned with the offending behaviour but rather with the offender's personal characteristics or circumstances, then, ostensibly, they are of no relevance in a just deserts system where sentence is determined by reference to the offence rather than the personal circumstances of the offender. As Gross observes:5
... it is plain enough that none of them have (sic) any bearing on how culpable was the criminal conduct, for which punishment is to be imposed ... |
5.15
The net result of this conclusion is that factors such as pleading guilty, showing remorse, attempting to make redress to the victim or even the fact that the sentence will have very adverse consequences on others dependent on the offender should not have any effect on sentence.
5.16
This may be thought to be undesirable.6 However, factors which mitigate sentence can be incorporated into a just deserts system if they can be explained on the grounds of humane considerations or sound penal policy.7 In other words, some of the factors which are personal to the offender can still be taken into account in determining sentence severity, by way of exception to the just deserts principle of proportionality between offence and sentence, if it is thought that they are still desirable because they promote expediency or the smooth running of the sentencing system or because there may be a need to show mercy in the circumstances.
5.17
It should be stressed that factors which mitigate sentence, if they are to be retained in a just deserts system, should be given very careful consideration. Since they are exceptions to proportionality, they carry with them the danger that proportionality might be ousted in favour of utilitarian considerations. For example, if the likelihood of successful re-integration into society is seen to be a good reason for allowing mitigation of sentence then just deserts is replaced at the mitigation stage by rehabilitative principles and the whole point of having a just deserts sentencing system is overturned.
5.18
In considering which factors may be relied on in mitigation of sentence, therefore, we must be certain that there are very good grounds for making an exception to the overall policy of proportionality between the offence and the sentence. Not only must there be sound logical arguments in their favour, but
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=121 |
also, where allowance is made in order to provide some other benefits; such as expediency or the smooth running of the criminal justice system, there should be satisfactory evidence that those benefits will result.
5.19
Also, since factors which mitigate sentence are not inherent elements in the determination of a sentence proportionate to the offence but are exceptions then the question arises as to whether they should be an entitlement of the offender in every case, or whether they remain at the discretion of the sentencer in line with Thomas's assessment above. If they are discretionary then it is all the more important that sentencers should not confuse factors which aggravate or mitigate the offence with them because inherent elements of the offence may be excluded.
5.20
There is a clear need, therefore, for a careful delimitation of the factors which may be taken into account on mitigation of sentence.
Let us now consider the respective roles of each type of factor.
5.21
A trend which may be noted in the criminal law, in Ireland and in other jurisdictions,8 over the last one-hundred years has been the gradual moving away from a specific and rigid definition of crimes in statutes which create criminal offences. The Larceny Act, 1916, for example, specifies in great detail a vast range of offences of theft, such as simple larceny; larceny of cattle and other animals; larceny of wills and written instruments; larceny of things attached or growing on land; larceny of goods in the process of manufacture; abstraction of electricity; larceny of ore from mines; larceny of postal packets; etc. Each of these offences carries with it its own range of penalties.
5.22
Modern statutes tend to be more general;9 and for a number of reasons, such as to improve the efficacy and efficiency of the investigatory and prosecutorial process; to ensure that cases do not fail on technicalities; and to increase the speed of the processing of cases. However, a consequence of this modern trend is a much wider variation in the degree of seriousness of offences within the broad definition of the offence. Modern statutes tend to prescribe a high maximum penalty which is to be imposed for the most serious variation of the offence, and which is far in excess of the least serious variation coming within the definition of the offence.10
5.23
The older statutes, by their restricted definitions of crimes, had less need for factors which aggravate and mitigate seriousness, because, by definition, their
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=122 |
specific variations encompassed the factors which made them more serious or less serious than the other variations, such as abuse of a position of trust by a clerk or servant11 or by a tenant or lodger;12 or causing harm not only to the immediate victim but to the entire community by stealing from the mail.13 Modern statutes, on the other hand, leave the development of aggravating and mitigating circumstances to the courts. We noted earlier,14 however, that the courts have not clearly articulated those principles in a manner which is readily accessible to those involved in the sentencing process or to the public at large. There is, therefore, a need to articulate clearly the relevant aggravating and mitigating factors to be taken into account by the courts when imposing sentence.
5.24
In a sentencing system where the primary principle for the distribution of sentence is just deserts, the principal concern of the sentencing courts is to impose a sentence which is proportionate to the seriousness of the offending behaviour. However the concept of seriousness is not simply a matter of assessing the gravity of the offending behaviour rather it involves both an assessment of the harm caused by the offender in committing the offence and an assessment of the culpability of the offender in causing that harm.15 The aim of a clearly articulated set of aggravating and mitigating factors should thus be to provide sentencers with a guiding framework of the factors by reference to which harm and culpability may be assessed. Such a framework is necessary to ensure a consistency of approach and a consistency of proportion in which these factors are considered and applied in the sentencing of offenders. Ashworth comments:16
Without some framework of agreed categories, relativities and priorities, it is difficult to see how the principle of fairness which requires like cases to be treated alike could have practical application. |
5.25
It should be observed, however, that simply providing a framework of factors which aggravate or mitigate seriousness cannot make sentencing into a precise balancing exercise: it cannot be simply a matter of arithmetic calculation by adding up all the aggravating factors and subtracting all the mitigating factors and arriving at an appropriate sentence.17 By providing guidance as to the factors which aggravate and mitigate seriousness, it is contemplated that a certain degree of consistency of approach in the sentencing of offenders should unfold. The provision of such a framework should direct the courts' attention to the development of more specific principles for the consideration of such factors, such as the weight to be attached to various factors in different situations. Thus sentencers will still have to decide the weight to be attached to each factor, and then apply the relevant developed principles to arrive at a just sentence in all the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=123 |
circumstances of the case. The weighting of factors in different situations will, no doubt, present some awkward questions for sentencers to resolve, as Ashworth observed:18
The great temptation, when asked whether stealing goods worth £100 from a supermarket by shoplifting should be ranked higher or lower than a theft of £10 by a person in a position of trust, is to say: 'it depends'. And so it does. But it does not depend on an infinite number of factors, and in effect the question is answered every day by courts all over the country. My guess, in the absence of sufficiently detailed statistics, is that the very few small thefts by persons in positions of trust, who are invariably first offenders, are regarded as more serious than the ordinary run of supermarket thefts by first, second or even third-time offenders. There is certainly some appellate authority which suggests that the In/Out line between custodial and non-custodial sentences is reached sooner by the 'breach of trust' offender ... It therefore appears that the position of trust generally outweighs the value of property stolen, although there must be points at which the value of the property taken in breach of trust is so small, or the property stolen in an ordinary case is so high, as to place limits on the general proposition. Fixing those points will be awkward, but in an evolving process of guidance that should not give rise to embarrassment. |
5.26
In other jurisdictions, where sentencing reform has sought to provide sentencers with a guiding framework of the factors which aggravate or mitigate the offence, the framework has taken the form of a list of examples of the types of factor relevant to the question of offence seriousness.
5.27
It need hardly be said that such a list cannot be exclusive it is impossible to foresee every factor which may affect the harm of an offence and the culpability of an offender in every circumstance. It is thus necessary to allow the courts to develop unenumerated factors which increase or decrease the seriousness of the offence. It is imperative, however, that any such unenumerated factors be consistent with the overall theme of just deserts and the aims and purposes of sentencing.19 By referring to the examples given in the list of specified factors, sentencers may derive some indication as to whether or not an unspecified factor would be so consistent.
5.28
The advantage of providing such a list, apart from the fact that it provides sentencers with a readymade list of the most common factors which aggravate or mitigate the offence, is that it gives sentencers a clear indication of the type of factors relevant to the question of offence seriousness. This should direct sentencers attention to the distinction between factors which aggravate or mitigate the offence and factors which mitigate sentence, and should also be of assistance in the development of other unenumerated factors.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=124 |
5.29
We tried as far as possible to select factors which aggravate or mitigate seriousness from decided examples of such factors in Irish cases; although this was thwarted somewhat by the dearth of reported considered sentencing decisions of the Irish courts. Our chief sources were the writings of eminent criminologists and penologists;20 the recommendations of sentencing commissions and committees of other jurisdictions who have proposed similar measures;21 and the reform measures of other jurisdictions which have adopted a similar approach as part of their just deserts reforms of sentencing.22 We were also aided in this task by the answers of a number of members of the Council of Europe to questionnaires on the area of aggravation and mitigation.23
5.30
Our examination of these sources brought to light a broad consensus on a number of factors which aggravate or mitigate the seriousness of offending behaviour. We shall now examine these in more detail.
5.31
The following factors are widely (though not universally) regarded as aggravating the seriousness of an offence:24
|
5.32
What follows is a discussion on each of the factors listed above. Since the list draws on many sources, it may be noted that some of the factors mentioned are simply variations on the themes of some others. Where appropriate, therefore, we will deal with a number of factors together.
5.33
Since the determination of seriousness relies on an assessment of the culpability of the offender it is axiomatic that the greater the planning or premeditation, the greater the culpability of the offender because it is more likely that the offence was deliberate and intentional. The offender who plans his offence is not only coolly defying the law but is going to some lengths to ensure that he succeeds and, sometimes, that he is not detected. He clearly and unequivocally places his interests above the constraints imposed by society on him and all others.26 The same concerns apply to offences committed by a member of a group organised for crime, and to offences committed as part of a campaign or sustained course of offending.27 In some cases it may be difficult to obtain sufficient evidence that the activities were part of organised crime, but there is no doubt that organised crime is one of the most calculated, deliberate and defiant types of offending and should be treated as an aggravating factor.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=126 |
5.34
It may be argued that committing an offence for profit or remuneration aggravates the seriousness of offending behaviour because it indicates a higher level of mens rea on the part of the offender. However, this would depend on the circumstances of the case: it probably indicates a level of intent higher than recklessness, but it may equally be seen as an excusing or mitigating factor where the offence would otherwise have been committed for gratification or pleasure. The great danger of including it in a set of enumerated aggravating factors is that it would be made an aggravating factor in all cases without due consideration being given to what it indicates about the culpability of the offender. We do not, therefore, feel that it should appear in our list.
5.35
Offences against weak, defenceless or vulnerable persons are, in principle, worse than crimes against persons who might have a real, in principle, opportunity of defending themselves or escaping the consequences of the offending behaviour because there is disparity between the positions of the offender and the victim. There remains the question, however, of whether an offender should also be more culpable when unaware of the weak or defenceless position of the victim. Nonetheless we are satisfied that knowingly exploiting the weak or defenceless position of others represents an aggravating factor to be taken into account when sentencing.
5.36
The rationale underlying this factor is the concern that persons who occupy a position of confidence or trust are in such positions on condition that they maintain that confidence or trust. If the offender takes advantage of that position to further personal ends then he or she not only commits the offence charged but breaches the trust placed in him or her by society and by the victims of the offence.31 Such breaches are also usually deliberate, thus they indicate a high degree of intent.32 The same may be said of offences committed by law enforcement officers; it is essential for the upholding of law and order that the special position of trust which they hold be maintained.33
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=127 |
5.37
There is little doubt that crimes of violence are the ones which cause society the greatest concern. Violent crimes which cause or risk death, serious injury, or cruelty carry grave consequences for the victim, thus the harm caused or risked is great. Where violence occurs not simply as a constituent of the offence but as an additional element as, say, where violence is used in the course of a theft the culpability of the offender is increased since the use of violence in such cases is regarded as wanton infliction of personal injury to further the offender's criminal activity; some would argue that the culpability of the offender on such occasions outweighs the culpability of an offender who engages simply in a violent offence which is not used in the course or furtherance of another offence:
an impulsive killing in the course of a robbery might be thought to be more serious than a planned and premeditated murder in an impossible domestic situation.35 |
5.38
At the end of the day it remains a question of the weight to be attached to the factors which aggravate in each offence, when one is concerned with the relative seriousness of the use of violence, alone or compared to the use of violence in furtherance of other offences. Nonetheless, it is clear that offenders who use violence to further an offence should be considered more culpable than others who commit the same offence without violence. Not only are they flagrantly defying the law, but they are also prepared to defy it still further to ensure success or non detection.
5.39
Similar concerns apply to threats of violence, since they add to the likelihood that the offender intended to defy the law by committing the offence and to ensure its success.
5.40
The carrying, threatened use or use of a weapon should also be viewed as a factor which aggravates culpability. Carrying a weapon indicates that the offender contemplated the use of violence and had prepared himself or herself for it, unless there is a credible excuse of self-protection against an anticipated
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=128 |
attack.36 Secondly, carrying a weapon makes it more likely that violence will result37 thus the harm risked by the offender is greater and the seriousness of the offence is aggravated. A third reason is that a person faced by an offender with a weapon is at a great disadvantage and this disparity should be viewed as more serious than offences where the parties meet on equal terms.38
5.41
The same concerns which relate to causing or risking physical or emotional injury apply to causing or risking economic loss; though on a lesser scale. Again the harm involved may be great, and the culpability of the offender may be heightened by the intention to cause grave economic harm to the victim.
5.42
Inherent in this factor is the notion that offenders who commit offences merely for thrills or for kicks show complete disregard of accepted community standards and the law. Theirs is the most wanton and flagrant breach of the law imaginable, and their conduct is deliberate, calculated, wholly unjustifiable and inexcusable.41
5.43
There are two reasons why acting as ringleader and inducing others weaker or younger (or, perhaps, even persons who are not weaker or younger) to participate in the commission of an offence should be viewed as an aggravating factor. First of all, leadership infers a degree of planning and premeditation, and therefore greater intention, to break the law of offending and to succeed in its commission. Secondly, by acting as ringleader and instigating others to join in the commission of the offence it is the ringleader who is the major cause of the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=129 |
offending behaviour. The ringleader is thus responsible for greater harm since he or she has encouraged others to offend.
5.44
This is not a widely recognised aggravating factor, and understandably so. Intoxication is commonly treated by the substantive criminal law as evidence of the absence of intent, knowledge or recklessness.44 How, then, may it be viewed as an aggravating factor? The answer may lie in an assessment of the degree of intoxication. An offender who is partially intoxicated, and has some knowledge of his or her actions, but nonetheless offends may be viewed as being in the same situation as an impulsive offender who realises what he or she is doing but loses his or her inhibitions. The fault, however, does not lie so much in the commission of the offence as in allowing himself or herself to become so intoxicated so as to be unable to control his or her actions. One solution is to sentence the offender as a reckless offender for knowingly risking to cause harm by becoming intoxicated, whether the harm was obvious to the offender or not;45 however there remains the dilemma as to whether the offender really was so intoxicated so as to be unable to control his or her actions, or was partially intoxicated and therefore closer to an impulsive offender. Ashworth concludes:
The upshot of this argument is that intoxication is in general neither an aggravating nor a mitigating factor, and the main reason for this is that the ordinary mitigating effect of weakened self-control and less appreciation of the situation is counterbalanced by the aggravating effect of the general social propositions about the use of intoxicants.46 |
At this time we do not feel that the use of alcohol or drugs should appear in our list of aggravating factors.47
5.45
The traditional rationale for the imposition of more severe penalties on
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=130 |
offenders who commit offences against law enforcement officers was the protection of the police by means of deterrence. This justification is wholly at odds with our earlier proposals.49
5.46
However, there is an independent reason why such offences should be viewed as more serious which is in keeping with the policy adumbrated above: the Gardai and other law enforcement officers are charged with the task of enforcing law; assaulting a law enforcement officer is therefore, within the scale of values of the legal system, worse because of the implied rejection of the authority of the law. It is important to note, however, that the offender must know, suspect, or be reckless as to whether the victim is a law enforcement officer-otherwise this argument loses its force.50
5.47
This factor may even be extended beyond law enforcement officers to include ordinary citizens involved in the enforcement of the law: e.g. a private citizen who tries to apprehend an offender in the commission of the offence. The same rationale applies -rejection of the authority of the law.51
5.48
We should stress once again that a list of factors which aggravate the seriousness of the offending conduct cannot be exclusive. There may be other factors which emerge from time to time which could justifiably be treated as aggravating the offence. For this reason, we believe that there should remain a residual discretion in the courts to expand the category of aggravating factors, and this discretion should be given recognition in a statutory provision.
5.49
We would add that some limitation should be placed on the extent of this discretion to ensure that the factors so developed are in keeping with the overall policy of sentencing in a just deserts system. The factors developed must:
|
5.50
Furthermore, it may be desirable that the legislature would from time to time add to or amend the list of aggravating factors, where necessary, to reflect changes in social attitudes to certain crimes. We contemplate that, if a Judicial Studies Board is brought into being, which we recommend,52 there should be some consultation with it to determine whether the proposed changes are consistent with the principles and purposes of sentencing.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=131 |
5.51
The following factors are widely (though, again, not universally) accepted as mitigating the seriousness of offending behaviour:
|
5.52
We shall now examine these factors in more detail. Where appropriate, we shall, again, deal with similar factors under the same heading.
5.53
Duress is already a defence to criminal liability at the trial stage. Duress removes the offender's voluntariness' and overbears his or her will. If the defence of duress succeeds at the trial stage when there will, of course, be no need to consider it at the sentencing stage since there will be no sentencing stage. However, if the defence fails, there may still be evidence that the offence was
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=132 |
committed under considerable pressure not amounting to the defence of duress. This pressure may be considered at the sentencing stage as a factor which reduces the culpability of the offender. This was recognised by the English Court of Appeal in R v Taonis,54 where an offender, convicted of unlawful importation of cannabis, had been forced into acting as courier of the drugs because of threats to beat and torture the woman he was living with and that he would be falsely accused of having stolen a considerable sum of money. In reducing the sentence from four years' imprisonment to two, Scarman LJ commented:
The experience (the defendant) has gone through was described in the Court below as truly terrifying. He did of course as a matter of strict law have the opportunity of going to the police. There was an interval of time during which he certainly was not under direct physical threat or pressure, and ... he could have gone to the police. He would have been very wise to have done so. In the light of the circumstances which I have mentioned, this court takes the view that the sentence was altogether too severe. We feel that the learned trial judge failed to give full or proper weight to the duress. |
5.54
It is clear that duress should be treated as a factor which mitigates the culpability of the offender for an offence.
5.55
Provocation is recognised as a defence to murder in Irish law, reducing the crime to voluntary manslaughter.56 However, for other crimes, the issue of provocation does not arise until the sentencing stage. At the sentencing stage, provocation may be viewed as a factor which reduces the culpability of the offender, depending on the relative strength of the provocation itself and the degree to which the offender's retaliation was sudden and impulsive.57 The weight and priority to be attached to each of these components is a matter which the courts will have to determine,58 but it is at least clear that swift and impulsive retaliation is far less blameworthy than planned and premeditated revenge, and that offences motivated by strong provocation are less blameworthy than unprovoked offences because it is the provocation, rather than an intention to flagrantly disobey the authority of the law, which is the primary motivation for the offending conduct.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=133 |
5.56
Impulsive reactions are generally the least blameworthy kind of intentional act since there has not been a careful decision to defy the law. Impulse is, thus, the corollary of planning and premeditation which acts as an aggravating factor. However, impulse can only be a significant mitigating factor if the offender was unaware of the impulsive reaction about to take place if, say, the offender had a history of violent reactions and knew of the types of situation likely to trigger off these reactions, then he or she may be regarded as more culpable.60
5.57
The central theme of this group of factors is the idea that an offender whose judgment is impaired should be considered to be less culpable than a person of normal judgment. Thus, persons of reduced mental capacity cannot be said to be fully responsible for their offences and some allowance should be made in mitigation in recognition of their reduced intent.
5.58
An offence committed after an offender succumbs to temptation may be regarded as morally less culpable than an offence committed without temptation. Bentham wrote:82
Authors of celebrity ... have said, that the greatness of the temptation is a reason for lessening the punishment; because it lessens the fault; because the more powerful the seduction, the less reason there is for concluding that the offender is depraved. |
5.59
In general, the existence of temptation reduces the seriousness of the offence because it explains why the offence was committed and displays that the offender was less motivated to break the law than to succumb to the temptation. Of course there are limits to this general proposition for example, temptation should not mitigate the culpability of an offender who exploits a position of confidence or trust because temptation is inherent in such positions.63 Nonetheless, there are certain situations in which temptation may be regarded as a factor which mitigates the seriousness of offending behaviour.
5.60
Where an offence is motivated out of strong human sympathy as where, say, a relative of a terminally ill patient switches off the life-support machine the offender should be viewed as less culpable than a person who offends for less altruistic reasons. Again, it will be a question of degree as to when and how
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=134 |
much mitigation should be allowed, but undoubtedly there are some situations in which strong human sympathy should be a mitigating factor.
5.61
The question here is whether or not the young or old offender's judgment was impaired through lack of development or senility. Where the judgment of a young or old offender is impaired then he or she may be viewed as less culpable, just as an adult offender who suffers from a mental impairment would be regarded as less culpable than a younger offender of full mental capacity. We would stress that youth or old age does not per se mitigate seriousness it is still a question of whether or not the culpability of the offender should be reduced because of impaired judgment. In People (DPP) v Simon Maguire and Patrick McDonagh,65 the Court of Criminal Appeal appeared to treat youth as a factor mitigating offence seriousness rather than sentence, but in any event declined to alter the sentence imposed on this ground.
5.62
However, in People (DPP) v Dennigan,67 the CCA took the opposite view, refusing to allow the youth of the applicant as a mitigation of the seriousness of the offence, but permitting it nonetheless to be taken into account in deciding the ultimate sentence.
5.63
In certain circumstances, the fact that an offender played a minor role in the commission of the offence may mean that he or she is less culpable than some of the others who participated in the offence. Fringe members of a group should be treated as less culpable than offenders who participate more fully or lead the others. Also, where a group forms spontaneously to commit an offence, it may sometimes be the crowd atmosphere and heightened excitement which drove the offender to participate in the commission of the offence rather than a desire to flout the law.68
5.64
The Victorian Sentencing Committee chose to add this to their list of mitigating factors as a corollary to the principle that serious penalties ought to attend on those who engage in violent or serious crimes. When no serious injury results, the harm is less; and when serious injury is not intended, the culpability is less than when it is intended.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=135 |
5.65
Traditionally, this factor entered into the sentencing decision as an indicator of the offender's likelihood of reform or re-integration into society. Since these are of no relevance to sentence severity in a just deserts system, making allowance for voluntary attempts to alleviate the effects of the offence cannot be justified on these grounds.
5.66
How does a voluntary attempt to alleviate the effects of the offence mitigate the seriousness of the offending conduct? The answer depends on when the attempt to alleviate the effects takes place. If it is before or during the offence (say, where the offender gives a warning) then it may reduce the culpability of the offender as it shows that he or she did not fully intend all the consequences of the offence. If it occurs after the offence then it is difficult to see how it affects the offence at all; but this depends on where one draws the line between the period of the offence and after the offence sometimes the harmful consequences of an offence may continue for weeks or months, as in rape where the victim may suffer severe psychological and emotional injury in addition to physical injury. If the offender is to be held responsible for all these harmful consequences of the offence then surely any attempt to alleviate them should mitigate the harm of the offence, even though the attempt at alleviating takes place a long time after the offending conduct. This explanation admittedly requires some stretching of the ordinary sense of the offence.
5.67
A simpler solution would be to exclude allowance for voluntary attempts to alleviate the effects of the offence made after the offending conduct from the question of offence seriousness, but instead, to consider it later in mitigation of sentence, since it makes sound penal sense to encourage offenders to make redress or to compensate their victims whenever possible.71
5.68
Therefore, we conclude that voluntary attempts to alleviate the effects of the offence made before or during the offending conduct should go to mitigation of the offence. Those made after the offending conduct should to to mitigation of sentence.
5.69
This factor follows the logic of earlier factors such as duress and provocation, and includes excuses such as ignorance of the law; mistake of fact and necessity, entrapment or abandonment.73 In each case, the factor indicates that the offender was less culpable because through ignorance, mistake, necessity or for some other reason, he or she did not fully intend to flout the law or to
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=136 |
commit the offence.
5.70
Once again, the courts should retain a residual discretion to develop other factors which mitigate the seriousness of the offending conduct, subject to the limitations that such factors must:
|
5.71
Also, we envisage that any legislative additions or amendments to the list would involve some consultation with the proposed Judicial Studies Board to ensure that the changes are in keeping with the overall policy of sentencing.74
5.72
Part of the tradition of Irish sentencing, and, indeed, of sentencing in other jurisdictions, lies in the discretion allowed to the sentencing judge to take a whole range of mitigating factors into account in reducing the level of severity of the sentence to be imposed. These include the age of the offender youth/old age poor health; where he or she has shown genuine remorse for the offending behaviour; where he or she has suffered extreme social deprivation; where the offence followed a period of family disturbance or financial worry; where the consequences of the offence on the offender have already been considerable; and so on.75
5.73
On a strict view of just deserts, these factors should be of no relevance in the sentencing decision since they have no bearing on the harm and culpability of the offender in the commission of the offence76 although some may appear to have a bearing on culpability in so far as they are put forward as the antecedent causes for the commission of the offence, these justifications are tied to rehabilitative sentences rather than to seriousness based sentences.77 Some desert theorists, Von Hirsch included, argue that the exclusion of these past non-criminal choices is justified since just deserts forbids that sentencing should be affected by social judgments upon and about offenders: thus the Minnesotan guidelines expressly preclude reliance on race, sex, employment, educational attainment, marital status, residence or living arrangements as aggravating or mitigating circumstances. Von Hirsch would contend that it is fairer to ignore such issues so as to preserve the equality before the law which just deserts ensures. If an offender loses his or her job because of conviction and sentence
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=137 |
while an unemployed offender suffers no such deprivation, it is argued that the offender who loses work cannot complain that it was the law which treated him or her unfairly. Only by excluding such personal and social factors can true equality before the law be achieved.78
5.74
However, exclusion of personal and social factors may lead to other injustices. It has been observed that:
Disparity among sentences is inequitable when it cannot be justified in principle, which is just the case when it results from disregard of the principle of proportion between crime and punishment. For this reason, biases and theories of criminal liability whose influence subverts considerations of culpability and frustrates the principle of proportionality have no proper place in sentencing deliberations. But there is another principle that must also be observed upon pain of inequitable disparity. Sometimes there are good reasons for reducing the sentence which the principle of proportional punishment would otherwise warrant, and what we might call the principle of mitigation of sentence requires us to give them effect. The principle is founded, once again, on considerations of justifiable punishment and involves certain humane considerations as well as certain practical requirements of sound policy. Disregard of this principle is therefore morally wrong and may also turn out to be imprudent administration of a system of criminal justice. If the principle is disregarded some of the time but not all of the time, there are inequitable disparities among sentences that stand independently as instances of injustice.79 |
5.75
In other words, humanitarian considerations, expediency and sound penal policy may sometimes require that we make exceptions to the just deserts principle of proportionality between offence and sentence by way of mitigation of sentence. Gross explains:
In the first place there are sometimes larger considerations of justice whose influence makes itself felt. In fairness to him, what a man has done that redounds to his credit ought sometimes to be admitted to counterbalance the crime that now redounds to his discredit. The acts of a good citizen and even a virtuous human being often have a proper place and count in his favour in deciding on his sentence. Still, not every kind of creditable activity is properly taken into consideration, and we find it difficult to decide where to draw the line. Apart from justice, there is mercy. If justice is without rigor, justice is undone; and yet the harshness often accompanying rigorous justice may be tempered without causing justice to be undone. But merciful |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=138 |
dispensation is not available on the easiest terms. Mercy is always given without there being a claim of right to it, and so it is exceedingly difficult to distinguish the compassion of common decency that ought to influence a sentence from the tender regard that is a precious human sentiment but has no place in the deliberations of a sentencing judge. Sometimes compassion is not a matter of mercy but a matter of right. When suffering would be cruel, the sentence must be mitigated to prevent that. When compassion founds a claim of right, the issue, again, is a difficult one, since it is not easy to mark the point where cruelty ends and humane suffering begins. Finally, there are reasons of expediency that seem to warrant mitigation. We wish to encourage those apprehended to co-operate in bringing others to justice, and so we reward their co-operation with lighter sentences than they would otherwise receive. But mere expediency cannot alone establish that a concession is right, and we are constantly reminded by bargains made only for administrative convenience that there are difficult questions to be answered in deciding just what kinds of sentencing bargains are proper.80 |
5.76
It is no easy matter to decide what should count as a good reason for allowing mitigation of sentence once we go beyond the relatively certain considerations of culpability and harm of the offence. However, since mitigation of sentence operates as an exception to the general principle of proportionality it is possible to consider what conditions may exclude a factor from justifiably mitigating sentence. Gross, again, remarks:
Because standards are uncertain, good reasons turn out to be problematic and considerations that ought not be admitted at all often influence the sentencing judge toward a more lenient sentence. Two general exclusionary conditions for mitigating considerations provide a foundation for suitable sentencing standards. In the first place it is important to decide whether a proposed mitigating consideration would impair the utility of the sentence. Would what seems a good reason for reducing the sentence, if given weight, allow the guilty man in some measure to get away with his crime? If so, it is not really a good reason since the lighter sentence is then futile as a measure in support of law. But in fact sentences that promote the evils of impunity are now common place in American courts, for it is usual to give lighter sentences to those who plead guilty only because they then relieve the court and the prosecutor of the burden of a trial. It is the very essence of a fair bargain between prosecutor and the accused that the accused gets away in some measure with his crime ... |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=139 |
Besides impairing the utility of punishment, leniency might be inequitable. When that is the case, whatever consideration it is that has dictated leniency cannot be a good reason for reducing the sentence. Inequitable disparity results when there is special treatment for some that cannot be justified by principles that apply to all, and since everyone is entitled to equal standing before the law, such treatment cannot be tolerated ...81 |
5.77
Bearing these exclusionary conditions in mind, we will now examine some of the factors which are widely accepted as mitigating the severity of the sentence to be imposed on an offender. The aim of this examination is to determine which factors could appear in a list as a general guiding framework of the factors and considerations which ought to allow derogation from the principle of proportionality of sentence severity to seriousness of offending conduct. The factors discussed are drawn from the sources referred to in the discussion on aggravation and mitigation of seriousness supra.82
5.78
The following are widely accepted as factors which mitigate sentence:
|
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=140 |
Let us examine each of these in more detail.
5.79
The fact that an offender pleads guilty has no bearing on the circumstances of the offence or the offender's personal characteristics. Making allowance for a discount for a plea of guilty is a purely practical concern based on the need to discourage court delays. This has the advantage of:84
|
5.80
By allowing the offender a discount for pleading guilty, the sentencing court can also compensate or give the offender some recognition for the fact that he or she has foregone the right to trial on a presumption of innocence.85
5.81
In Ireland, a guilty plea is almost always taken into account as a factor reducing sentence.86
5.82
See further The People (DPP) v Moloney,87The People (DPP) v Johnston,88 and The People (DPP) v Maguire and McDonagh,89 where a plea of guilty merited a 6 year reduction in a 20 year sentence of imprisonment for manslaughter.
5.83
On the other hand, allowing a discount for a plea of guilty can be criticised as taking an easy way out of the search for other ways of tackling the problems of delay and backlog in the courts. Also, some fear that it may increase the risk that innocent persons will plead guilty.90 Some consider that an offender who chooses not to plead guilty and is convicted is, in effect, penalised because he has not availed of the opportunity to gain the discount.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=141 |
This perception led three members of the Australian Law Reform Commission to dissent on the view that a plea of guilty should merit a discount91 however the majority was of the view that the benefits of the discount outweigh its disadvantages and thus the discount should be allowed, provided it was stressed that the courts must not take failure to plead guilty as a factor which aggravates the sentence for a convicted offender.92 We, too, would enter the caveat that the fact that an offender has pleaded not guilty to a charge and has thereafter been found guilty should not justify the imposition of a sentence more severe than the seriousness of the offending behaviour would warrant.93 With this in mind, we believe that, on the whole, there are good grounds for making an allowance for a discount in sentence when the offender has pleaded guilty.
5.84
This was recognised as a factor in mitigation of sentence by the CCA in The People (DPP) v Moloney.95 The Court observed, however, that failure to assist in investigations could not in any circumstances amount to an aggravating factor.
5.85
Again, the concern here is that assisting in the investigation by either turning oneself in or by assisting in the investigations of other offences, should help expedite the course of justice. An added advantage is the fact that witnesses and, in particular, victims, may be spared the trauma of a long wait before the matter comes before the courts. Also, as the Australian Law Reform Commission pointed out,96 allowing a discount in sentence for assistance in investigation may also give recognition to the offender for the fact that he or she may have put himself or herself in difficult circumstances and may face the threat of violence and hostility from other offenders especially while in prison.
5.86
A serious danger which should not be overlooked is the danger that assisting information may be recycled, i.e. used at the initial stages to secure a lesser charge and again before sentence to secure a further discount. This
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=142 |
danger would be removed by the implementation of this Paper's proposals regarding plea negotiations.97
5.87
It is difficult to justify allowance for a discount in sentence simply because the offender shows remorse or denounces his or her offending conduct, especially if the offender has done nothing else to show remorse other than to simply express remorse. An inherent difficulty with this factor is that an expression of remorse per se is very difficult to prove or disprove whilst at the same time being very easy to make.
5.88
The traditional justification for allowing a discount for an expression of remorse ie. that it indicates a likelihood of successful re-integration into society does not hold any water in a just deserts system. This, in addition to the difficulties in establishing whether the offender's remorse is genuine, leads us to conclude that remorse should not per se merit a discount in sentence.
5.89
On the other hand, if remorse is expressed by means of a guilty plea, or by disclosure of the offence to the investigatory authorities, accompanied by an admission of complicity, or by making voluntary attempts to redress the wrong, it at once becomes both credible and beneficial. In these circumstances we feel that remorse is something which should be taken into account in determining the amount or size of the discount for the plea, disclosure, or attempt at redress, rather than as a mitigating factor per se.
5.90
There is growing public concern that the criminal justice system should, as far as possible, ensure that the victims of crime are adequately compensated for the loss or damage they have suffered as a result of crime. Earlier in this paper we recommended that a sentencer, when choosing between two or more sanctions of equal severity, should take redress or compensation of the victim into account.100 Under this heading we examine whether there is any satisfactory justification for allowing a discount in sentence when the offender has attempted to compensate the victim.
5.91
To begin with, it is accepted by most that compensation or redress of the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=143 |
victim should be encouraged whenever possible.101 The main justification for allowing a discount in sentence is, therefore, that it would appear to be a good means of encouraging offenders to make redress.
5.92
One of the major difficulties which has to be surmounted, however, stems from the fact that it may be far easier for some offenders to make redress or compensation than others, and, thus, it may be far easier for some offenders to 'buy' a discount in sentence than for others. If a discount is allowed then it will put wealthy offenders in a better position to escape full punishment than others, and the end result will be disparity in the way offenders are sentenced.
5.93
A solution to the problem of disparity, which appears to have gained some recognition in England, is to ignore the amount or size of the compensation when determining the size or amount of the discount. In R v Stapleton and Lawrie,102 for instance, the appellants offered to pay as much compensation as they could while a co-defendant, of substantially the same complicity in the offences, offered to pay a much greater amount, £3,500, without any great difficulty. At first instance the appellants were sentenced to 30 months' imprisonment while the co-defendant was sentenced to 15 months' on the basis that he had offered to pay a large sum of compensation. The Court of Appeal rejected this basis, saying:
In any event, we would have thought it was right that all these accused should be dealt with equally. When one looks at the sentences actually imposed and looks at the compensation point and the very infelicitous way in which it was expressed in sentencing the accused, it is clear that the difference in sentences actually passed cannot stand. |
5.94
The Court of Appeal accordingly reduced the appellants' sentences to 15 months' imprisonment.
5.95
A factor which seems to be of some importance in the English system is the felicitousness of the attempt or offer of compensation or redress.
5.96
There may, thus, be some merit in allowing a greater discount to an offender who, although of little or no income, goes to great lengths within his or her means to effect compensation or redress; but, this would mean that a wealthy offender would have less opportunity to earn such a discount.
5.97
Undoubtedly, therefore, allowing a discount for attempts at compensation or redress would provide many problems for the courts in deciding the weight to attach to that factor in mitigation of sentence. We are satisfied, however, that provided the courts are wary of the danger of disparity in the sentencing of offenders there would be some merit in allowing a discount in sentence for attempts by the offender to redress the harmful consequences of the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=144 |
offence.
The sentence would result in damage to the offender's future employment or career.103
The offender has suffered severe personal injury in consequence of the offence.104
The offender, through age or ill health, would be occasioned unreasonable hardship by a sentence imposed in proportion to the seriousness of the offence.105
Delay or other grievances in bringing the matter to trial.106
5.98
These four factors are similar in nature and may well be dealt with together.
5.99
The primary justification for allowing a discount in sentence where any of these factors exists is equality of impact. The principle of equal impact is based on the argument that while it is just to impose the same sentence on two equally culpable offenders for two equally grave offences, it is unjust to do so if the two offenders have such differing 'sensibilities' in that the sentence would have a significantly different effect on each of them.107Bentham explained the principle thus:
Rule 6. It is further to be observed, that owing to the different manners and degrees in which persons under different circumstances are affected by the same exciting cause, a punishment which is the same in name will not always either really produce, or even so much as appear to others to produce, in two different persons the same degree of pain: therefore That the quantity actually inflicted on each individual offender may correspond to the quantity intended for similar offenders in general, the several circumstances influencing sensibility ought always to be taken into account.108 |
5.100
The principle has received the greatest attention in relation to monetary penalties The District Court Rules, 1948, for example, require sentencers imposing fines in the District Court to take the means of the offender into
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=145 |
account when determining the size of the fine.109 But he principle may also have more widespread application thus a sentencer may reduce a sentence of imprisonment for an offender whose life expectancy is short.110 Similarly, in The People (DPP) v O'Leary111 a 30-year old soldier was given a 3-year suspended sentence for having unlawful carnal knowledge of an 11-year-old girl. In sentencing the soldier the court referred to the fact that the accussed had an excellent employment record but would lose his job if he received a prior sentence, and in The People (DPP) v O'Sullivan112 the accused was given a suspended sentence on the basis that he suffered from a very severe muscular wasting disease which caused him great pain and discomfort most of the time.
5.101
However, there are many reasons why the principle of equal impact should not be given a role in every case. For one thing, it may be objected to on the grounds that it enjoins the impossible113 since the sentencer can take this into account only in the crudest of ways: for instance, by reducing a poor man's fine or an old man's prison term. He is in the position of having to adjust something he cannot measure.114 Secondly, the effect of the principle upon sentencing practice may be misunderstood by the public and other offenders.115 Thirdly, is the fundamental objection to the principle of equal impact-that offenders ought to have been aware of the consequences of conviction and sentence when they committed their offences. In other words, the offender ought to think about the extra consequences when committing the offence. Finally, over-reliance on the principle of equal impact may lead to injustice. Von Hirsch argues that in an attempt to produce equality of impact a court might place a middle-class offender on probation and send an offender from the ghetto to prison, even though the cases are otherwise comparable:
More drastic measures thus come to be imposed chiefly on those of lower status who are deemed to have 'less to lose' but only because they have lost so much already through their deprived social situation.116 |
5.102
Mercy may, nevertheless, require that some recognition should be given to the principle of equal impact where to do otherwise would lead to grave injustice. We shall now examine the four circumstances outlined supra to see if they present good grounds for invoking the principle of equal impact.
5.103
Where an offender's employment or career appears to be in jeopardy because of a sentence, making allowance for a discount in sentence to
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=146 |
compensate for the additional deprivation suffered in the loss of job would seem to make good sense.117 However, making such allowance is apt to create grave injustice where an offender who has less to lose (i.e. is unemployed) suffers greater deprivation because he does not have a job. In fact the English Court of Appeal would maintain that those who hold high positions are expected to maintain higher standards, so that their punishment should certainly be no less.118 Allowance for a discount in sentence when the offender's job is in jeopardy leads to the introduction of social inequality into sentencing. We would have grave reservations about making such an allowance.
5.104
Where the offender suffers severe personal injury in consequence of the offence, or, say, where a bank-robber is shot and seriously injured during the course of the offence, it is questionable whether his sentence should be reduced to take the additional suffering consequent upon the offence into account. Ordinarily, where the offender suffers extra consequences, there should not be any mitigation of sentence since the offender should have thought about them beforehand. However, where the consequences are severe, as, say, where the offender's hand is severed in the affray in which he or she participated,119 there may be good grounds for a reduction in sentence. Again, we would have grave reservations about allowing such a discount in any but the most exceptional circumstances.
5.105
Where an offender, through age or ill-health, would be occasioned unreasonable hardship by a sentence imposed in proportion to the offence, it may be right to allow some reduction in sentence. For example, a term of imprisonment may have a much worse effect on an elderly offender suffering from Parkinson's disease than on a younger offender in good health. In R v Varden120 the English Court of Appeal upheld a reduction in sentence on a seventy-one year old offender of low intelligence because his advanced age would probably make a term of imprisonment more unpleasant for him.121 Similarly, the youth of an offender may also be treated as a reason for mitigation. As Walker has pointed out, to spend part of one's youth in prison is worse than spending part of one's middle age there.122
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=147 |
5.106
Similar concerns apply when the offender suffers from a physical disability.123
5.107
It must be stressed once again that allowance for such factors should be the exception rather than the rule. Ordinarily the offender's individual reaction to the sentence is not something which should affect its severity.
5.108
Finally, it remains to be asked whether delay or other grievances in bringing the matter to trial should count as factors which mitigate sentence. The question here is whether such delay or grievance can be viewed as, in itself, punishment. If one considers that sentencers commonly order custodial sentences to run from the date on which the offender was first kept on remand in custody pending trial and sentence,124 then such an allowance might appear to be justifiable on similar grounds however, if the delay or grievance led to an extra period of detention on remand in custody and that period is taken to form part of the sentence, then there is no reason why any further reduction should be allowed by way of mitigation. Furthermore, if the delay resulted in the offender being at liberty for an extra period of time then he will have benefited rather than suffered, so there is no reason why a reduction in sentence should be allowed in these circumstances either. On the whole, therefore, we see no reason why delay or grievances in bringing the matter to trial should merit a discount in sentence except in the most extraordinary of circumstances, say, where an offender is remanded in custody for a considerable length of time pending sentence but receives only a fine as sentence.
5.109
We conclude that the invocation of the principle of equal impact out of merciful considerations should only be allowed in the most exceptional circumstances, and where possible should be avoided unless the sentence proportionate to the seriousness of the offence would result in manifest hardship or injustice. We contemplate that in many cases hardship and injustice may be avoided by imposing a type of sentence which would be less likely to inflame the offender's sensibilities provided the sentence chosen is still proportionate to the seriousness of the offending behaviour. For example, where an offence is in the lower range of equivalent sentence types, hardship on an offender who is in bad-health may be avoided by imposing a fine rather than a short custodial sentence.
5.110
It is, thus, only where hardship or injustice cannot be avoided by choosing an agreeable sentencing option that the principle of equal impact should be given scope.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=148 |
5.111
This factor is not so much an example of the principle of equal impact as an extension of the principle. Here it is not the offender's sensibilities but those of his or her family which are being relied upon.
5.112
Thus, in Coughlan126 a woman who pleaded guilty to the manslaughter of her husband who had brutally assaulted her while she was in labour received a 5-year suspended sentence of penal servitude. Butler J highlighted the constitutional aspect of the case:
in considering what penalty to impose, I must remember that she is the surviving parent, and the Constitution confer rights on the family and rights on the children. |
In one respect, therefore, it can be said that the constitution required steps to be taken, including the mitigation of sentence, in situations where the constitutional rights of the offenders family would be jeopardised by a sentence. This argument is not seen explored fully by the courts to date.127
5.113
One objection to this factor is that the offender ought to have thought about the consequences before committing the offence.128 The English Court of Appeal has generally taken this approach,129 and the objection is compelling in the sentencing of all but impulsive offenders. On at least one occasion, however, the Irish courts have had regard to family support and being a good family provider as elements in the sentencing decision.130 We would have serious reservations about allowing such a discount in sentence in all but the most exceptional cases, as where the sentence would deprive the offender's children of all parental care.131 Furthermore, the introduction of the role of the offender as a good family provider might be thought to discriminate against poorer offenders. Again, hardship may be avoided in cases at the lower end of offence seriousness by the imposition of non-custodial sentencing alternatives.
5.114
A principle which appears to have gained some recognition among English sentencers, although it is unclear whether it is followed here, is that of allowing
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=149 |
an offender a discount in sentence in recognition of some outstanding good deed done by him or her in the past. Where the court states that it is reducing the sentence which it would otherwise have passed, so as to take account of, say, the fact that the offender has saved a child from drowning, it may be seen as somehow settling the offender's 'moral' account in other words, the offender may not have exhausted all possible credit for the past good deed.132
5.115
Any element of moral accounting would be anathema to the just deserts principle of proportionality between offence and sentence and opens up considerable scope for bias to enter into sentencing. The principle cannot easily be justified in terms of the offender's moral standing; Walker quips that he has not come across a case in which a judge increased a man's sentence because he had evaded conscription, let a swimmer drown, or refused his sister a kidney.133 There is also the question of where to draw the line: when does a good deed fall below the level at which a discount may be gained in sentence?
5.116
On the other hand society might lose respect for a sentencing system which failed to take account of spectacular social acts.134 There is no ready means of determining whether this is so. We have strong reservations about making allowances for past good deeds when it comes to sentencing after all, it may be said that the function of sentencing is not to give recognition for past good deeds but rather to impose punishment for present bad ones. We would welcome views on the matter.
5.117
We conclude that there is some need for a statutory provision which would emphasise the importance of the distinction between factors which aggravate or mitigate the offence (which would be considered in all cases) and factors which mitigate sentence (which should also be considered in all cases, but should only be allowed when necessary). There is also a need for some kind of framework which would guide sentencers as to the matters relevant to the aggravation and mitigation of offence seriousness and to the mitigation of sentence so that the courts may develop such principles in a consistent and coherent manner, and which would promote consistency of approach by sentencers in the sentencing of offenders.
5.118
We envisage that such a framework would be best effected by means of a list of examples of the most common factors which affect offence and sentence. The list should be non-exclusive and should allow sentencers to develop and rely on other factors, so long as such other factors are consistent with the policies and principles of sentencing proposed in this Paper. We would invite views as to
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=150 |
whether there is a danger that the provision of such a list would oblige the courts to have regard to the language of the list and would result in too literal an approach.135
5.119
We provisionally recommend the introduction of a statutory provision governing sentencing which would highlight the following concerns:
In assessing the harm, culpability and circumstances which tend to aggravate the offence, the sentencer shall give special consideration to:
|
5.120
In assessing the harm, culpability and circumstances which tend to mitigate the offence, the sentencer shall give special consideration to:
|
5.121
Having arrived at a sentence which is proportionate in severity to the seriousness of the offence, the sentencer should give reasonable consideration to whether there are any special reasons, by way of exception to the general principle of proportionality between offence and sentence, why a sentence of lesser severity should be imposed, such as where:
|
5.122
We would welcome views on the matter of whether the sentencer should be empowered to allow some reduction in sentence for the fact that the offender has done some spectacular good deed in the past.
5.123
We provisionally recommend that the statutory lists of aggravating and mitigating factors be reviewed by the legislature from time to time in order to take new developments into account and that any alterations or amendments be made in consultation with the proposed Judicial Studies board in order to ensure that they do not undermine or conflict with sentencing policy.
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=153 |
6.1
We have singled out the issue of prior criminal record for special attention because of the prominent position it occupies in the sentencing decision.1 It has historically been a feature of judicial sentencing practice, and certainly there is an instinctive tendency to attribute some significance to past record in sentencing. However, while its appeal as a predictive factor is considerable,2 it is not immediately obvious how it can be of any relevance in the assessment of the deserts of an offender in proportion to the seriousness of the instant offence. Fletcher3 and Singer4 have both argued that prior criminal record is of no relevance in the just deserts sentencing decision since its inclusion must in fact be covertly preventive,5 and preventive considerations are not germane to an offender's deserts.
6.2
Nevertheless, certain elements of prior criminal record may be considered germane to the just deserts principle. The Irish Supreme Court appears to envisage reliance on it in a manner wholly in keeping with just deserts.6 The existence of a prior criminal record may be seen as a factor which can be regarded as aggravating the seriousness of the offence by increasing the culpability of the offender. If this is the case, then the seriousness of the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=154 |
offence is increased, and so too must be the sentence in proportion to it. Von Hirsch explains:7
The reason for treating the first offense as less serious is...that repetition alters the degree of culpability that may be ascribed to the offender. In assessing a first offender's culpability, it ought to be borne in mind that he was, at the time he committed the crime, only one of a large audience to whom the law impersonally addressed its prohibitions. His first conviction, however, should call dramatically and personally to his attention that the behaviour is condemned. A repetition of the offense following that conviction may be regarded as more culpable, since he persisted in the behaviour after having been forcefully censured for it through his prior punishment. |
6.3
If prior criminal record is to increase the culpability of the offender because he or she has persisted in ignoring the prohibitions of the law, then it should be observed that only a limited number of factors of prior record emerge as being of relevance.
6.4
To begin with, the prior offence(s) must be similar in nature to the offence in question before they can have any bearing on the culpability of the offender: for example, it cannot be forcefully argued that a prior conviction for a motoring offence dramatically and personally calls to the attention of the offender that crimes of violence are condemned by the criminal law.8 This much was recognised by Finlay CJ in The People (DPP) v Tiernan where the offender had four previous convictions: for assault occasioning actual bodily harm; for aggravated burglary associated with a wounding; for gross indecency; and for burglary. Of these, the ones which the Supreme Court considered as aggravating the culpability of the offender for a violent rape were those which involved violence and the crime involving indecency.9
6.5
Secondly, the staleness of the previous convictions should be taken into consideration. As the time between the past and current offences increases, the culpability of the offender decreases. The more distant the conviction the less plausible it is to claim that it dramatically and personally calls to the offender's attention the fact that the current offence is condemned by the criminal law. Similarly, the age of the offender at the time of commission of the previous offences should also be of relevance since an offence committed when a minor casts less light on the present character of the offender.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=155 |
6.6
Thirdly, the seriousness of the prior offence may have some bearing on the culpability of the offencder for the current offence, as von Hirsch explains:10
... the quality of the record should count. Someone convicted of his first serious crime would be entitled to plead that such gravely reprehensible conduct has been uncharacteristic of him, and hence he deserves to have the penalty scaled down even where he has a record of lesser infractions. |
In other words, the prior conviction should drive home to the offender that crimes of a serious nature are condemned by the criminal law thus he or she should have known better than to engage in further serious crime hence he or she may be viewed as more culpable.
6.7
Number may also be of some relevance. Intuitively, one could claim that the greater the number of prior convictions the more the offender should have known not to engage in criminal conduct. The offender with the greater number of relevant prior convictions may thus be viewed as more culpable.
6.8
In this manner, prior offences may be seen as being germane to a just deserts based approach. Von Hirsch points out that, conceptually, this system may have one shortcoming: The offender, although it is a first offence, may already have been warned by others as to the prohibitions of the law, and consequently may be as culpable as another offender who has a prior record.11 For example, a police officer who commits a crime should be considered more culpable than an ordinary member of society committing the same crime because of his or her extra knowledge of the prohibitions of the law and his or her duty to uphold it, even though he or she may not have a prior criminal record. However, if there is a problem concerning persons who, although they do not have prior criminal records, are equally deserving of additional censure (e.g. the police officer in our example above) then all that is necessary to ensure that they are equally censured is that the sentencing court takes their special circumstances into account as factors which aggravate culpability.
6.9
The most obvious disadvantage of this approach to prior criminal record is the danger of over-reliance on cumulative sentencing an offender with a lengthy criminal record could end up with a substantial sentence for a minor offence. The logical solution would be to place a ceiling on the degree to which criminal history can aggravate the culpability of the offender, but, when one considers that there is no ready means by which culpability can be measured, it is difficult to conceive how such a ceiling could be defined. Even if it can be defined, there is still the question of how many past offences should be counted or how serious should a past offence be before the ceiling is reached.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=156 |
6.10
An alternative means of dealing with prior criminal record within a just deserts system is the progressive loss of mitigation approach. This approach rests on a theory of desert that is primarily oriented towards the present crime, but qualified to a limited extent by considerations related to prior conduct.12 The foundation for this theory is the fact that disapprobation is addressed to the offender, even though the basis for condemnation is the conduct von Hirsch allegorises:
When a person commits a misdeed in everyday life ... he may plead that the misconduct was uncharacteristic of his previous behaviour. He may use such language as I'm sorry, I don't know what got into me it's not been like me to do that kind of thing. ... The actor is pleading in self-extenuation that though this act was wrong, he should not suffer the full measure of obloquy for it because it was out of keeping with the standards of behaviour he has observed in the past. ... The plea, by its manifest logic, carries its greatest force when the actor has not committed the misconduct before, and it loses force progressively with each repetition.13 |
6.11
Under this approach, the just deserts theory has to make a concession to a requirement which does not fit neatly into its logic: i.e. persons who do not have a prior criminal record must be given substantial mitigation of sentence. The first offender, according to this theory, is disapproved of less because we wish to accord him some respect for the fact that his inhibitions against wrongdoing have functioned, and to show sympathy for the lapse. He has his sentence mitigated because of the absence of a prior criminal record. The worse the record gets, the less there may be taken off the sentence in mitigation.
6.12
An English judge might respond that this is nothing new there a progressive loss of mitigation system has been recognised for decades although sometimes more in the breach than in the observance.14 In the 1973 case of Bowman, Murphy and Bromwell15 the Court of Appeal was faced with three men who had handled a substantial amount of stolen property. One had been sentenced to five years imprisonment, and another to seven years because of his 'longer and worse' record. The Court said that the wrong approach had been adopted:
Men are not sentenced on their records. They are sentenced for their offences. If they have got bad records then nothing can be taken off by way of mitigation, while if they have not got bad records a great deal can be taken off. |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=157 |
6.13
Again, the prior offence should be similar in nature or seriousness; some consideration should be given to the time elapsed or the staleness of the past convictions and the number. However, number is relevant under the progressive loss of mitigation theory only in that mitigation will be exhausted after a specified number of convictions.
6.14
The two systems outlined above of dealing with the question of prior criminal record within a just deserts system the aggravation of culpability approach, and the progressive loss of mitigation approach both ensure that the existence of prior criminal record does not go un-noticed by the sentencing court, and result in the repeat offender suffering an added measure of censure for his repetition. The end result of both is the same. Which method, therefore, is to be preferred should just deserts be adopted in Ireland?
6.15
The aggravation of seriousness model appears to represent the present approach to sentencing of the Irish Supreme Court, and thus may be thought to be preferable. If there is anything to be said against it, however, it is that there is no ceiling or upper limit to the amount by which seriousness (and, consequently, sentence) may be aggravated thus offenders with prior records could be punished excessively more than offenders without prior records. On the other hand, it sits squarely with just deserts logic, since it treats the prior criminality in terms of culpability.
6.16
The progressive loss of mitigation theory is certainly engaging, but some doubt must remain, especially if our notion of desert is informed more by consideration of consequences and culpability than by the motivation of the offender. The theory does not sit so squarely with desert logic, since it requires first offenders to be given mitigation of sentence simply because they are first offenders. This cannot be explained in terms of culpability or harm. We do not know if the progressive loss of mitigation approach is, or ever was, countenanced by the Irish Courts.
6.17
Also, the unreality of the theory in present judicial practice here and elsewhere may, arguably, be replicated in reforms it is difficult to believe that criminal history is not aggravating and cumulative simply because the accumulation of mitigation is structured and has an upper limit.16
6.18
A possible disadvantage of this approach is that, unlike the aggravation of seriousness approach where there is no limit to the amount by which sentence may be aggravated, under this approach there is no limit on the amount by which sentence may be mitigated for a first offender. However, this might not be such a bad thing in a sentencing system which aims to reduce the level of prison population. If a lower limit is to be placed on the amount of mitigation which is to be allowed, then the obvious question is how many repetitions can occur before the mitigation is lost?17Von Hirsch concedes that there is no ready
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=158 |
answer, and most supporters of the theory seem content to suggest a certain limited number of repetitions.18
6.19
In the final analysis, we feel that we should lean as far as possible towards preserving the status quo, and that the matter of prior record should be dealt with in a manner that sits most squarely with a just deserts theory. This entails an aggravation of culpability model. We feel that the danger of an excessive amount of aggravation in some circumstances might be limited by introducing a requirement that sentence may not exceed a stated maximum, (expressed, perhaps, as a percentage of the un-aggravated sentence), although, admittedly, this may involve some stretch of the mind. Other jurisdictions, such as Sweden, Finland, and England and Wales, have employed prior criminal record in a manner which aggravates the culpability of the offender as part of their just deserts approach.19
6.20
We provisionally recommend, therefore, a just deserts approach which includes the consideration of relevant prior criminal record as a factor which aggravates the culpability of the offender, although we would welcome views as to the merits of adopting a progressive loss of mitigation approach in preference to this.
6.21
We therefore provisionally recommend that there be implemented a statutory provision which confines the role of prior criminal record in the determination of the severity of sentence to situations in which it aggravates the culpability of the offender in committing the offence. The statement should highlight the following concerns:
The sentencer, in determining the severity of the sentence to be imposed on an offender, may have regard to any offences of which the offender has been found guilty in the past which may be considered to increase the culpability of the offender. In considering whether such prior offences aggravate the culpability of the offender for the offence for which he is being sentenced the sentencer should have regard to:
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=160 |
7.1
A number of other jurisdictions have, in response to problems similar to those encountered in the Irish sentencing process, established sentencing commissions and sentencing reform projects to conduct a comprehensive review of sentencing policy with a view to solving some of those problems.
7.2
Two trends are evident in these reforms:
|
7.3
In this chapter we shall examine the reforms which these other jurisdictions have implemented in order to make their sentencing policies more coherent and consistent. We shall also take a look at the sentencing systems in some of the member states of the Council of Europe to see how their problems correspond to ours and if they have adopted any useful techniques to solve them.
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=161 |
7.4
In 1976, Finland added a new Chapter 6 to its Penal Code, dealing with choice of sentence. The new chapter marked a change in Finnish sentencing ideology away from the rehabilitative ideal towards neoclassical criminal policy, i.e. the structuring of sentencing discretion and the imposition of proportionate sanctions.2 Prior to that, the Finnish code had also thereto overemphasised the impact of prior criminality in comparison with other sentencing criteria, and the change in ideology gave strong support to demands to unify the prevailing sentencing practice in order to reduce disparity in sentencing. Article 1 of the new Chapter 6 makes the seriousness of the offending behaviour the most important factor in determining the severity of sentence. It reads:
The punishment shall be measured so that it is in just proportion to the damage and danger caused by the offence and to the guilt3 of the offender manifested in the offence. |
7.5
This is in effect an expression of the just deserts limb of cardinal proportionality the sentence is to be proportionate to the gravity of the crime.
7.6
A key factor in the Finnish reform is the intentional omission of the risk of future misconduct the most important element of rehabilitation, deterrence and incapacitation. Desert is, consequently, the only principle by which the extent of sentence can be determined.
7.7
Article 1, it will be noted, contains an important description of how seriousness of the offending behaviour is to be measured -by reference to the harmfulness of the conduct and the culpability of the offender. Article 2 of Chapter 6 contains a list of more specific criteria which may be considered as increasing the seriousness of the offending behaviour. The list is not exhaustive, and the elaboration and more detailed development of these criteria is left partly to legal doctrine and partly to the courts.4 Factors which increase offence seriousness are:
|
7.8
Article 3 of Chapter 6 lists factors which generally reduce the harm or culpability of the offending behaviour:
|
7.9
Article 4 allows the sentencing court to take into account other (mitigating) consequences caused to the offender through the crime or the sentence when these together with the punishment would lead to an unreasonable result.
7.10
All of these factors affect the sentence within the range prescribed by statutory maxima and minima. However, in addition, there are specific provisions allowing the court to go below the prescribed minimum where the offender is aged 1517 years; or had diminished responsibility; aided or abetted; attempted; exceeded the normal boundaries of self-defence; or, in some cases, committed the crime out of necessity.5
7.11
A puzzling provision of the Finnish Chapter 6, however, is Article 2(4) which provides that prior record may be taken into account if it suggests that the offender is apparently heedless of the prohibitions of law. Finnish penologists are reported to regard this as a weak point in the law, because no indication is given as to the weight that should be given to prior record, or how heedlessness should be judged.6
7.12
A second lacuna is the lack of guidance on the use of imprisonment. Should a large variety of crimes be punished by imprisonment, albeit with graded durations reflecting the comparative seriousness of crimes? The statute does not say.7
7.13
A decade of experience with the new law has indicated a trend towards giving increased attention to the degree of gravity of the criminal conduct. The provisions have developed a substantial consensus of support and virtually no sentiment favouring repeal or major alteration has been discernible in Finland to date.8 A more detailed account of their implementation is to be found at
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=163 |
Chapter 9 infra. (Implementing Sentencing Policy.9
7.14
In short, therefore, the Finnish reforms are characterised by:
|
7.15
In 1986, the Swedish Committee on Imprisonment (Fδngelsestraffkommittιn) issued its report Sanctions for Crimes10 which recommended a reduction of statutory maximum and minimum sentences for many offences, changes in the rules on parole, and an expansion of the famous day fine system.11 The Committee also drew up two new draft chapters of the penal code (Chapters 29 and 30) which were enacted by the Swedish legislature with little modification in June 1988,12 coming into effect in March 1989.13
7.16
The Swedish Penal Code had, up to this, provided merely that sentences should (1) Promote general obedience to the law and (2) foster the defendant's rehabilitation.14 It failed, however, to suggest what features of the offender or the offence ought to be given priority in sentencing, or to give guidance as to the proportionality between the gravity of crimes and the severity of punishments.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=164 |
Guidance was thought to be needed to supply a coherent policy for sentencing, to help choose which penal aims should predominate, and thereby to help decide what features of the offender or his offence should be given the most weight.
7.17
The Swedish Imprisonment Committee proposed a legislative statement of a single principle of distribution to guide sentencers in their choice of sentence. The legislation rests on the principle of proportionality in effect the cardinal proportionality limb of the just deserts theory ie punishments should be commensurate with the seriousness of the defendants' criminal conduct. The severity of the penalty relies chiefly on what it termed the penal value (ie seriousness) of the offence. Penal value is determined by (a) the degree of harmfulness of the conduct and (b) the offender's culpability in committing it. The concept of penal value, therefore, defines the deservedness of the offender in relation to his conduct and culpability. The new legislation provides:
Chapter 29 On Deciding of Penalties and Remission of Sanction Section 1 Penalties shall be decided with regard to the desirability of uniform and consistent adjudication and set within the scale of punishment applicable to the culpability of the offence or offences taken as a whole. In assessing culpability, special consideration shall be given to the damage, injury or danger occasioned by the criminal act, to what the accused realized or should have realized, and to the intentions or motives he may have had in committing such act.15 |
7.18
It will be noted that the Swedish provisions are very much in the same style as the Finnish reforms described above. This pattern continues in sections 2 and 3 which contain lists of aggravating factors (such as taking advantage of a victim's vulnerable position or other special difficulties in protecting himself) and mitigating factors (such as provocation, insanity, or compassion) which enhance or diminish the penal value or deserts of the offender's conduct.
7.19
S2 provides a list of factors which may be regarded as aggravating the seriousness of the offending behaviour:
|
7.20
S3 contains a list of factors which mitigate offence severity:
|
7.21
S4 and S5 of chapter 29 provide two other factors which may be considered in determining the extent of sentence. S4 addresses how prior record affects the choice between fines and imprisonment and how it affects the amount of fines or imprisonment. To this extent, the Swedish provisions improve upon the Finnish because they clearly define the degree to which prior criminal record is a factor in determining sentence. Under S4, prior record may be taken into account in determining the severity of sentence, but only if it has not already been taken into account in determining the type of sanction or in the revocation of parole:
In meting out punishment, the court, if insufficient regard can be paid to the circumstances in question through choice of sanction or forfeiture of conditional release, shall give reasonable consideration, besides the culpability of the offence in itself, to whether the accused has previously been guilty of an offence or offences. Special consideration shall be |
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=166 |
given to the extent of such previous offence or offences, to the time which has elapsed between the offences, and to whether the previous offence or offences and the new offence are similar in nature or whether in both cases they are of an especially serious character.16 |
7.22
S4 thus allows some room for the possibility that prior criminality may be seen as somehow increasing the culpability of the offender but only if the prior criminal act is closely related to the one in question. Thus, a commendable feature of the section which should be observed is its clarification of the various elements of prior criminal conduct which are to be considered in determining the weight to be attached to prior criminality; namely the type, the extent, the seriousness, and the time which has elapsed since the commission of a prior offence. This excludes from consideration the prior commission of, say, a string of parking offences in the sentencing of a burglar even more so if they occurred some considerable time in the past.
7.23
S5 gives a list of special factors which may be considered when making the mitigation decision:
In meting out punishment, the court shall give reasonable consideration, besides the culpability of the offence in itself, to:
|
7.24
Chapter 30 deals with the choice of the nature of sanction. The provisions of Chapter 30 are closely similar to the choice of method hybrid discussed supra.17 Whilst the determination of extent in Chapter 29 relies solely on the penal value or deservedness of the offender, the choice of nature of sanction relies on traditional aims such as rehabilitation (S9) and incapacitation (S7).
The important sections of the chapter (for our purposes) read as follows:
On Choice of Sanction Section 1 In choosing a sanction, imprisonment shall be considered a more severe sanction than conditional sentence or probation. Section 4 In choosing a sanction, the court shall give special notice to any circumstance or circumstances suggesting the imposition of a sentence milder than imprisonment. And in so doing, the court shall consider such circumstances as are envisaged in Chapter 29, Section 5, of this Code. In contemplating imprisonment, the Court may take into account, besides the culpability and nature of the offence or offences, the fact that the accused has previously been convicted. |
7.25
Incapacitative considerations are included in S7:
In choosing a sanction, the court, in contemplating conditional sentence, shall consider whether there is no particular reason to believe that the accused will continue to commit criminal acts in future. |
7.26
Rehabilitative considerations are included in S9:
In choosing a sanction, the court, in contemplating probation, shall consider whether such sanction might encourage the accused to refrain |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=168 |
from committing further criminal acts. As grounds for probation, the court may consider:
|
7.27
The thrust of Chapter 30 amounts to the position that once the severity of sentence has been decided in accordance with Chapter 29, and there exist two or more types of sanction which are equal in severity, rehabilitative or incapacitative considerations may be relied upon to determine which type of sanction should be imposed.
7.28
The Swedish reforms are characterised by:
|
7.29
The Canadian Sentencing Commission produced its report Sentencing Reform: A Canadian Approach in 1987. It proposed a fundamental overhaul of the sentencing system with the purpose of making sentencing more equitable, predictable and understandable.
7.30
The Commission found that one of the problems with their sentencing structure was:
The almost complete absence of policy from Parliament on the principles that should govern the determination of sentences.18 |
7.31
The Commission concluded that a sentencing rationale which declared purposes and principles of sentencing would provide guidance to the judiciary and enlightenment to the general public.
7.32
In order to come to a realistic conclusion as to the purposes of sentencing, the Commission first examined the scope of the sentencing process.19 Its immediate conclusion was that the sentencing process is limited in its scope. Only a small amount of crimes committed are reported to the police, and of these it was calculated that only 8.5% actually reached the stage where the sentence was passed by a Canadian Court. This was because many of the crimes reported went unsolved, and because many of the solved cases were filtered out of the sentencing process through the intervention of social workers, police officers, and prosecutors who exercised their discretion along the way. The complete picture showed that sentencing deals with only a small amount of offenders:
Its actual reach, as compared to the total amount of crime, is little more than a scratch on the surface and this situation is unlikely to change.20 |
7.33
Thus it would be unrealistic to argue that the purpose of the sentencing
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=170 |
system should be the same as that of the entire criminal justice system, because to do so would be to make the sentencing process accountable for the entire criminal law, over which it has very limited control.21 This is of profound consequence to those who argue that the purpose of sentencing should be the protection of the public either by means of rehabilitative programmes to prevent offenders from recidivating; by means of deterrent strategies to prevent others from offending; or by means of incapacitation to prevent certain offenders from re-offending. Since sentencing deals with only a handful of offenders, the function of protecting the public might better be viewed as the overall purpose of the entire criminal justice system, and the primary responsibility of the police, other prosecutorial and regulatory bodies, and Government agencies. The Commission neatly summed up its conclusions as follows:
Intuitively, at least, one would rather resort to a security guard than to a sentencing judge to protect one's home.22 |
7.34
On the other hand, although sentencing fulfils an indespensible public function in assisting in the administration of the criminal justice system, the primary objective of the courts is to ensure that justice is observed in the administration of criminal sanction, whereas security objectives are more akin to police work and corrections. The overriding concern of sentencing, therefore, is to ensure that members of the community are made accountable for behaviour which is victimising and flouts the basic values of society; hence the outline of the overall aim of sentencing should reflect the proposition that people should be held accountable for conduct which betrays the core values of their community.
7.35
The purpose of sentencing was formulated as follows:
The Commission recommends that the fundamental purpose of sentencing be formulated thus: It is recognized and declared that in a free and democratic society peace and security can only be enjoyed through the due application of the principles of fundamental justice. In furtherance of the overall purpose of the criminal law of maintaining a just, peaceful and safe society, the fundamental purpose of sentencing is to preserve the authority of and promote respect for the law through the imposition of just sanctions.23 |
7.36
As regards principles to govern the distribution of sentence, the Commission felt the need for a synthesis between just deserts and utilitarian principles, but noted that insensitivity to possible conflicts between objectives ascribed to the criminal justice system and objectives of the sentencing process was a feature of the status quo. Such conflicts led to inconsistency.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=171 |
7.37
The Commission thus chose the just deserts limb of cardinal proportionality as the paramount consideration governing the determination of sentence. Other principles, (i.e., incapacitation, deterrence and rehabilitation) could also be considered within the framework of proportionality, but were rejected as principles for the determination of sentence for two reasons First, they could not be proved to work, and second, sentencing alone could not solve the crime problem. So increased use of utilitarian sentences could not be promoted to the detriment of individual rights.24
7.38
The Commission proposed a two pronged reform strategy as far as principles of distribution of sentence are concerned. First a legislative statement of sentencing principles was to be made; then a rigid guideline system would be imposed with ranking of offence and penalty severity. The legislative statement of principles mentions only cardinal proportionality ie sentence is proportionate to the gravity of the offence and the degree of responsibility of the offender but it is clear from the guideline rankings that ordinal proportionality has an equally important role.25
7.39
The Commission's recommendations read:
The sentence to be imposed on an offender in a particular case is at the discretion of the court which, in recognition of the inherent limitations on the effectiveness of sanctions and the practical constraints militating against the indiscriminate selection of sanction, shall exercise its discretion assiduously in accordance with the following principles:
|
7.40
The proposals represent a clear attempt to create a system of sentencing
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=173 |
based on proportionality, where the most important factor is the gravity of the offence rather than the offender's past convictions past convictions are only a factor amongst many to be taken into account in determining the sentence level within the presumptive range or in deciding whether to depart from the presumptive sentence.
7.41
In order to assist sentencers in assessing the gravity of the offence and the degree of responsibility of the offender for the offence (ie. the seriousness of the offending conduct) the Commission proposed a non-exhaustive list of factors which aggravate or mitigate the seriousness of the offence as it appears in the presumptive guidelines.26 They were as follows:27
Aggravating Factors
|
7.42
The Canadian Sentencing Commission's recommendations are characterised by:
|
7.43
The Victorian Sentencing Committee published its three volume report Sentencing in April 1988. The Committee, after extensive analysis of the traditional aims of sentencing, noted that:
In most statutory provisions Parliament merely sets the maximum penalty that may be imposed, and that is generally the only guidance it gives to the court on sentencing.28 |
7.44
It concluded that sentencing is a purposive and complex process which requires to be justified by a number of policy aims:
No one aim alone can justify either the process as a whole or the imposition of a particular sentence.29 |
7.45
The Committee maintained the distinction, often made by scholars, between principles which justify the entire sentencing system and principles which justify the imposition of a particular sentence on an offender, noting that justification for the imposition of a particular sentence needed to be more specific.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=175 |
7.46
The Committee did not, however, make a distinction between the objects of sentencing and the distribution of sentences, and it is clear from the Committee's recommendations that it intended the question of distribution of sentence to be answered by reference to the justifying principles chosen by the Committee.
7.47
The first matters considered by the Committee were the principles which justify the entire sentencing system, and which are to be relied upon by parliament when fixing penalties for crimes. The Committee concluded that deterrence, rehabilitation and retribution were feasible aims of the sentencing system, whilst incapacitation, because of its inefficacy, was not. The concepts of denunciation and wilful default (ie failure to comply with the terms of a lesser punishment as in imprisonment for fine default) were found to be mere effects of the sentencing system, rather than aims to be pursued by it. Economic considerations such as prison capacity and the cost of sanctions were found to affect the sentencing system, and thus had to be borne in mind.
7.48
The Committee concluded:
The Committee recommends that the purpose of a sentencing system is to prevent crime and promote respect for the law by:
|
7.49
The Committee then turned its attention to the principles which should justify the imposition of sentences in individual cases, and which may be relied upon by sentencers when fixing the sentence for an individual offender.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=176 |
7.50
Primary importance was to be accorded to just deserts. Although it appears that the Committee was only relying on the cardinal proportionality limb of just deserts theory, whilst abandoning the requirement of ordinal proportionality, the Committee also proposed a comprehensive system of guidance which addressed the requirement of ordinal proportionality.31 The only purposes for which a sentence could be imposed were to be denunciation, deterrence and rehabilitation, whilst at all times the sentencing decision was to be tempered by reference to consideration of parsimony, or, in exceptional circumstances, mercy. Under no circumstances, however, could a sentence be increased beyond the limit set by the concept of desert. The Committee recommended:32
In sentencing an offender a court must have regard to
|
7.51
The Committee also proposed a statutory statement of factors which would be regarded as aggravating or mitigating the culpability of the offender, and, accordingly, sentence. The lists were to be non-exhaustive.
7.52
The following would increase the culpability of the offender:
|
7.53
The Committee also recommended the express listing of two factors which were not to be taken as aggravating the culpability of the offender:
|
7.54
The following would decrease the culpability of the offender:
|
7.55
There followed a brief list of two factors which, although not related to culpability, might be considered as mitigating the severity of sentence:
|
7.56
The Committee also found that it would be of some assistance to the courts if the legislature set out a hierarchy of sanctions to guide the courts in their use. It recognised, however, that there might be a certain degree of overlap between a lesser level of one penalty and a more serious level of the penalty below it in the hierarchy,33 and also that different people might have different views on the comparative severity of different penalties, and therefore the most that could be hoped for was that some degree of consensus might be achieved.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=180 |
The consensus reached or the hierarchy of sanctions was as follows, in descending order of severity:
|
7.57
Further details on the Victorian scheme of guidance to assist in the implementation of the new sentencing policy may be found in paras 10.20 et seq, infra (Victoria).
7.58
For the present we may characterise the Victorian proposals as follows:
|
7.59
Like the Victorian Sentencing Committee, the Australian Law Reform Commission published its report Sentencing34 in 1988.
7.60
The Commission examined the purposes of the sentencing system along lines similar to those followed by the Canadian Sentencing Commission.35 It concluded that sentencing is only one component of the criminal justice system. The goal of the criminal justice system is to make criminal laws real and meaningful by providing the means to ensure that a breach will attract significant consequences. In terms of crime control and protecting the public, it is the criminal justice system, taken as a whole, and all its components, which controls crime, not only one component, in particular, the sentencing or punishing
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=182 |
component.36 The Commission found that the basic justification for the imposition of a sentence was simply that the offender has committed a crime. The sentencing process had to follow the overriding requirement that in imposing a criminal sanction the system operated in a just manner by imposing just punishments.
7.61
This amounted, in part, to an expression that the purpose of sentencing is to ensure that a person who has committed a crime should be punished but only in a manner which was just -in other words, by implementing the 'just deserts' principle of distribution.
7.62
The Commission expressed five important principles underlying its approach:
7.63
First, punishments imposed by the criminal justice system for offences must be just, that is, they must be of an appropriate severity, having regard to the circumstances of the offence and the offender.
7.64
Secondly, consistently with a just punishment, rehabilitative goals and restitution for victims may also be pursued. In the final analysis, however, punishments are not imposed on offenders for the purpose of rehabilitation, or for restitution. They are imposed to punish the offender for having broken the law. But where rehabilitation can be advanced, or restitution ensured, within the context of a just punishment for the crime, this should be encouraged.
7.65
Thirdly, inhumane, cruel or vengeful punishments such as capital punishment, corporal punishment, and torture should in no circumstances be permitted.
7.66
Fourthly, goals such as the incapacitation of the offender or general deterrence should not be among the objectives of the imposition of punishment. They both run counter to the general principle of justice underlying the report and both punish the criminals, not for their criminal activity, but for what they or others may do in the future.
7.67
And, finally, punishment must be consistently applied. This implies not only that offenders should be punished for the crimes they commit but also that similar offenders who commit similar crimes in similar circumstances should be punished in similar ways. It further implies that offenders who commit more serious offences should be punished more severely than those who commit less serious offences.
7.68
The Commission professed a primary reliance on the principle of just deserts. The ALRC's concept of the just deserts theory clearly included both cardinal proportionality and ordinal proportionality:
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=183 |
The concept of 'just deserts' ... implies that similar offenders who commit similar offences in similar circumstances should be punished in a simliar way. Furthermore, it implies that offenders who commit more serious offences should be punished more severely than those who commit less serious offences.37 |
7.69
Surprisingly, despite these bold statements of policy governing the Commission's own approach to sentencing reform, the recommendations did not include a statutory statement of these principles of any kind. Instead, the Commission proposed a number of reforms to the procedures surrounding the exercise of sentencing discretion so that consistency of treatment between offenders and offences would be enhanced. These included more extensive requirements for the giving of reasons by sentencing judges; a statutory list of factors regarded as relevant to the sentencing decision but it should not place an obligation on the courts to consider all or any of those matters; a statutory list of factors irrelevant to the sentencing decision; a clarification of the standard of proof required at sentencing hearings; and a more active role for the prosecution at the sentencing stage. Thus, whilst the policy which the Commission favoured is clear, the Commission proposed nothing which would oblige the courts to follow it, apart from a statutory list of relevant factors based on the policy and even those were not to be considered binding.
7.70
The Commission found that the present law did not provide a statement of which facts are relevant to the exercise of sentencing discretion. A rational and consistent system of law requires the existence of a common standard by which to evaluate individual decision making. Consequently, the Commission recommended provision in legislation for a list of factors relevant to sentencing. Since it is impossible to predict every factor which might be relevant to sentencing, the list of categories should not be closed but should at least include the following:
|
7.71
It will be observed that the list does not differentiate on the basis of whether a fact is aggravating or mitigating, or on the basis of whether it aggravates or mitigates the seriousness of the offending behaviour, or whether it is merely a factor which mitigates the severity of sentence. This was apparently done on purpose, but the reasons are not clear although presumably because some may be both aggravating or mitigating depending on the circumstances, e.g. the degree of participation in the offence.
7.72
Two members of the Commission dissented on the issue of a statutory list of relevant factors, saying that if its directory character was emphasised, it would provide little assistance, and if substance was given to it, the courts would be obliged to give effect to the language of the legislation which would amount to an exercise in statutory interpretation.38What is needed is the development of principle, not an exercise in statutory interpretation ... the development of consistent sentencing principles may be better achieved through the processes of the common law.39
7.73
The Commission acknowledged the controversial nature of two factors included in the list. First, the impact of a particular sanction on third parties was controversial because it appeared to authorise punishment otherwise than by reference to the offender's characteristics or conduct. However, it was included because of the potentially destructive consequences which might ensue if the impact of punishment on third parties, especially the family of the offender, was ignored. Secondly, the inclusion of the prior and relevant history of the previous convictions and dispositions of the offender was seen as controversial on the basis that the punishment for an earlier crime having been incurred, that crime was no longer relevant to the offence at hand. However, what the Commission proposed, although it is not clear from the list, was that prior criminal record could be of relevance, without contravening the principle of proportionality to the current offence, if it was appropriate to extend to first offenders some leniency in punishment, because it would consequently not be appropriate to treat offenders who continued to offend with that kind of leniency whilst remembering that prior offences of a different kind to that being considered might not always be relevant to sentence. This amounted to an espousal of the progressive loss of mitigation theory outlined supra.40
7.74
A novel proposal was for a list of facts not relevant to sentencing:
|
7.75
The Australian Law Reform Commission's recommendations are characterised by
|
7.76
The first sentencing commission in the United States was established in the state of Minnesota in 1978. In its reforms, the Commission adopted just deserts as the overriding consideration in determining sentences of imprisonment; nothing was done to alter the law in relation to other sanctions.42
7.77
The Commission boldly chose a prescriptive system for the ranking of offences into ten categories of severity. Offenders were divided into seven categories their deservedness being calculated by reference to their prior criminal record. This reliance on criminal history is problematic, however, as the presence of a high criminal history score reduces the significance of the current offence and the punishment may no longer be proportionate to the gravity of the offence.
7.78
The Commission also produced a list of aggravating and mitigating factors which are only relevant to the sentencing decision if they conform to the desert rationale. This is clearly illustrated in that part of the guidelines which deals with factors which may or may not be used by a judge in departing from the presumed sentence under the statutory sentencing grid.43
7.79
The list of factors which cannot be used for varying the sentence is:
|
7.80
The list of factors which can be so used is:
Mitigating
|
Aggravating
|
7.81
There are also some specific mitigating and aggravating factors listed in relation to particular crimes or groups of crimes. These are:
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=189 |
7.82
In 1987 the United States Sentencing Commission issued its Report Sentencing Guidelines and Policy Statements. The Comprehensive Control of Crime Act, 1984 delegated to the Commission the authority to review and rationalise the federal sentencing process and demanded guidelines which would further the basic purposes of criminal punishment, i.e., deterring crime, incapacitating the offender, providing just punishment and rehabilitating the offender.
7.83
The Commission, in its first report on its guidelines' remarked that it would be profoundly difficult to choose between the various possible objects of sentencing.44 More sustainably, it suggested that a clear-cut Commission decision in favour of one of these approaches would diminish the chance that the guidelines would find the widespread acceptance they need for effective implementation.45Allen counters that this begs the question whether there can be effective implementation of guidelines which have no coherent underlying rationale.46
7.84
The solution actually adopted by the Commission was to take an empirical approach, using data estimating the existing sentencing system as a starting point. A primary aim was to determine which distinctions were important in judicial sentencing practice at that time and to replicate them in the guidelines. Thus a descriptive scheme was adopted (though with some evolutionary elements).47 The Commission made the following case for its decision:
Those who adhere to a just deserts philosophy may concede that the lack of moral consensus might make it difficult to say exactly what punishment is deserved for a particular crime, specified in minute detail. Likewise those who subscribe to a philosophy of crime control may acknowledge that the lack of sufficient, readily available data might make it difficult to say what punishment will best prevent that crime. Both groups might therefore recognise the wisdom of looking to those distinctions that judges and legislators have in fact made over the course of time.48 |
7.85
This assessment is rather optimistic, and the Commission's other defence of its action is rather speculative: that as a practical matter, both philosophies may prove consistent with the same result in most sentencing decisions.49 This, it is submitted, places the cart before the horse, as it were: the objects of sentencing should dictate the penalty imposed rather than being found, on examination after the event, fortuitously to be in agreement with the sentence
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=190 |
handed down.
7.86
Breyer, who was a member of the Commission majority, subsequently justified their position as being a compromise forced upon the Commission by the institutional nature of the group guidelines writing process.50 In respect of a just deserts approach, a difficulty would arise in that different Commissioners would have different views about the correct rank order of the seriousness of different crimes. The trade-off of views would tend, in his opinion, to create increased punishments in each area.51 Nor did the Commissioners believe that public polling was sufficiently advanced or detailed to warrant its use as an accurate source in ranking criminal behaviours and to combat the inherent subjectivity of Commission decisions in this field.52 At the same time, it was felt that the empirical work with respect to deterrence could not provide the Commission with the specific information necessary to draft detailed sentences with respect to most forms of criminal behaviour.53Commissioners Nagel and Block gave this further justification for their approach:
'Even had the Commission simply mimic[ked] the mathematical averages of past sentences, however, a substantial step toward achieving both fairer and more effective sentences would have been made. Clearly, averaging out the extremes and irregularities of past sentences promotes more equal treatment for offenders. Perhaps more importantly, it furthers the crime-control goal of deterrence. Rational individuals consider the likelihood as well as the severity of punishment. Merely setting the guideline sentences at the average current sentence levels would increase the certainty of imprisonment while decreasing the length of the term more offenders would go to prison, although some would go for a shorter time. Few experts would deny that this change in the manner of distributing punishment would increase the level of deterrence, thus enhancing one of the most important purposes of the institution of punishment.'54 |
7.87
Thus, the Commission adopted its empirical compromise, which Breyer defends thus: The result of this compromise is that the Commission's results will reflect irrationality in past practice, but only to a degree. Since the Commission employed typical past practices, the Guidelines tend to avoid unjustifiably wide variations in sentencing.55
7.88
The criticism by Commissioner Robinson of this rationale in his dissent
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=191 |
is justified that individual judges up to the present have been relying on numerous different philosophies, and that the amalgamation of their practice can only deprive their sentencing of such little rationality as it possessed. But both he and the Commission majority were forced into untenable conclusions by the terms of the Comprehensive Crime Control Act, 1984, which demanded guidelines that will further the basic purposes of criminal punishment, i.e. deterring crime, incapacitating the offender, providing just punishment, and rehabilitating the offender.56 The failure of the original federal legislation to take account of the need to prioritise one single principle for the distribution of sentence must be held largely responsible for the subsequent logic of the Commission's Guidelines and the Robinson dissent. The end result has been that the guidelines manifest a strong tendency toward the incapacitation rationale.
7.89
The Federal Proposals can be characterised by:
|
7.90
JUSTICE, the British Section of the International Commission of Jurists, established a committee in November of 1987 to assess the objectives and effectiveness of sentencing and the extent to which sentencing policy in England and Wales should be predetermined to achieve consistency. The Committee, chaired by Lady Ralphs, produced its report, Sentencing, A Way Ahead, in 1989.57
7.91
The Committee noted an urgent need for a clear and defined objective in sentencing policy, since Parliament had shown a marked reluctance to provide one.
7.92
After examining the systems of proposed reform in other jurisdictions, the principle of proportionality (just deserts) was proposed as the new rationale:
As an underlying principle of the criminal justice system we consider that punishments must be just in that they are of appropriate severity to reflect both the gravity of the offence and the culpability of the offender. Thus we recommend that the rationale underlying sentencing should be |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=192 |
that of proportionality to the culpability of the offender. Accordingly, offenders committing similar offences in similar circumstances should be punished in similar ways. |
7.93
Goals such as rehabilitation and restitution could be pursued, but less tangible goals such as general deterrence could not be relied upon to increase a sentence beyond what is proportionate to the offence.
7.94
An offender's criminal history could not be taken into account as an aggravating circumstance increasing the sentence, but it could cancel or reduce the degree of mitigation to which the offender would otherwise have been entitled.58 Where a choice had to be made between a community sanction or a custodial one, prior record could also be taken into account, especially since a failure to respond to community sanction in the past could indicate that custody is appropriate for the instant conviction.
7.95
The Committee also recommended that the premise that imprisonment is a punishment of last resort should be firmly established and acted upon. Only those whose offences are so grave that any sentence would be unacceptable should be sent to prison.59
7.96
The Criminal Justice Act, 1991 represents the manifestation of the British Government's proposals contained in its earlier White and Green Papers.60 Already, the Act is heralded as a great disappointment when seen in the light of the White Paper's proposals.61
7.97
The White Paper, Crime, Justice and Protecting the Public proposed a new legislative framework for sentencing, since, so far, Parliament had given little guidance to the Courts on sentencing beyond setting the maximum penalties for offence, even though sentencing principles and sentencing practice are matters of legitimate concern to Parliament.62
7.98
The aim of the Government's proposals was better justice through a more consistent approach to sentencing. The ultimate objective of the Government was to reduce crime, particularly crimes of young people, before they embarked on a career of criminality. To this end, the Government had promoted and encouraged many crime prevention initiatives, including the promotion of neighbourhood watch schemes and crime awareness strategies.63 Importantly, the Government noted that while sentencing has an important part
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=193 |
to play in the prevention of crime, its role must not be over-stated. Many crimes are not reported, and even those that are reported are not always solved, so many of those who commit crime cannot be brought to justice in the sentencing arena. The Government's proposals therefore emphasised the objectives which sentencing is most likely to achieve in whole or in part:
The first objective for all sentences is denunciation of and retribution for the crime. Depending on the offence and the offender, the sentence may also aim to achieve public protection, reparation, and reform of the offender, preferably in the community. This approach points to sentencing policies which are more firmly based on the seriousness of the offence, and just deserts for the offender.64 |
7.99
Just Deserts was the Government's choice. Objectives such as rehabilitation, deterrence and incapacitation could not be successfully met by sentencing, and, in any event, it had been a long accepted objective of sentencing that punishment should be proportionate to the seriousness of the crime.
7.100
In tandem, the Government proposed that imprisonment be relied upon less, since many offences, especially property offences, could be dealt with adequately by way of compensation orders, fines, or community penalties. In contrast, crimes of violence, which are viewed as being more severe, could be treated more severely.
7.101
Under the proposed framework, an offender's criminal record could not be used to aggravate the sentence; but a good record could be relied upon to mitigate the sentence.
7.102
In contrast to the White Paper, the Act vehemently avoids statements of general principle. In the run up to the Act there was much controversy and debate,65 and the end result shows many signs of a compromise stance having been adopted. In essence, the Act restricts the Courts to certain justifications for imposing particular sentences.
7.103
The Act is prolix. Part 1 concerns the power of the courts to deal with offenders, and introduces a new framework for sentencing. Section 1 restricts courts to two possible justifications for imposing a custodial sentence:
|
7.104
However, if the offence is indictable only, and the offender was previously sentenced to imprisonment, or the sentence is a mandatory one, these restrictions do not apply. Section 1 also makes provision for the giving of reasons whenever
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=194 |
the court is passing a custodial sentence.
7.105
Section 2 provides that the term of custody imposed by a court must be:
|
7.106
These requirements do not apply, however, to crimes triable on indictment only. Reasons are only required to be given if the duration of sentence is based on the protection of the public under section 2(b).
7.107
Section 3 covers the consideration of pre-sentence reports, information about the circumstances of the case, information about the offender's attitude to the offence and his or her physical and mental condition, and the importance of prior criminal record. Section 3(2) provides that, in general, previous convictions and responses to previous sentences do not render an offence more serious: however section 3(3) states that the circumstances of previous offences may be of relevance to the seriousness of the offence. No indication is given of how the circumstances of previous offences may be related to the seriousness of the offence, or to what degree.
7.108
Section 4 abolishes the power of the court to pass a partly suspended sentence or an extended sentence. Section 5 sets out the grounds for passing a community sentence, i.e. a sentence including any one of following:
|
7.109
The courts may only pass one of these types of sentence when satisfied that it is the most suitable for the offender, and the restriction on the liberty imposed by the order or orders must be commensurate with the seriousness of the offence.
7.110
Also of interest is section 16 which provides for fines imposed by the magistrates' courts to be determined by reference to a unit fine scheme in which
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=195 |
the number of units corresponds to the seriousness of the offence.66
7.111
All in all, the Act represents a compromise attempt to introduce the policy of just deserts into the sentencing decision by requiring the courts to impose a sentence proportionate to the seriousness of the offence, while at the same time retaining the policy of incapacitation when imposing a custodial sentence. Even those who agree with the policy introduced by the Act criticise it for making sentencing too complex without pronouncing any consistent or dominating policy.67 The Act's greatest defect68 is that it misses the opportunity to declare the aims, principles and policies which ought to govern sentencing generally. It is destined to generate a considerable amount of public and professional discussion in the coming months.
7.112
The Act is characterised by:
|
7.113
The Council of Europe has in recent years been responsible for extensive comparative work on sentencing throughout the continent. Chief sources are the papers of the Eighth Criminological Colloquium (of 1987)69 and the documents of the Select Committee of Experts on Sentencing which have been published in the intervening period.70
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=196 |
7.114
A good introduction is given by Marc Robert to the sentencing problems which the civil legal systems of Europe share with those of the common law world.71
7.115
He remarks that there exist troublesome disparities and uniformities in European sentencing practice disparity in the nature of the penalty imposed, and in the quantum of the sentences, and excessive uniformity in the solutions adopted eg. as between offenders with criminal intentionality who must be segregated from society and ... those without this intentionality in relation to whom a solution should be adopted which does not withdraw them from society, even if the same criminal act is involved.72
7.116
A further problem arises with the co-existence in European criminal systems of two different and almost contradictory values.73 One is that of formal equality: if the offence has been defined and classified and attributed to the defendant in accordance with the rules of procedure, and if the sentence has been imposed within the framework laid down by the provision relating to the offence concerned, a person convicted after a trial must be considered as having enjoyed all reasonable guarantees against arbitrary proceedings and to have been treated fairly.74
7.117
The other is that of individualisation, and of substantive equality, whereby the courts are now required to apply different sanctions to individuals who differ in their degree of responsibility, and their personalities ... giving preference to equal chances for [social] reinsertion over the traditional concern for equality of punishment.75
7.118
The combination of these two values requires, in Robert's view, a number of features to be introduced to penal systems. In particular, general criteria of individualisation must be given.76 Such provisions, where they exist, tend to be very similar, ultimately referring the court to the application of the objectives pursued by the penalty. For example, Article 45 of the preliminary draft of the Belgian Criminal Code provides that within the limits of the law, the court shall select the penalty bearing in mind the objective seriousness of the act and subjective guilt of the perpetrator, and giving special consideration to the effectiveness of this choice for the defence of society, and the values it recognises, and the possibility it provides for the social reinsertion of the offender
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=197 |
and respect for his personality.77
7.119
However, the functions of penalties are rarely more precisely defined by the legal systems of Western Europe:78
The history of French legislation in the field of penology in the last ten years is a good example of the uncertainty which can prevail in this area owing to the confrontation of two antagonistic currents: the first insists on the need to treat offenders by using security measures (mesures de surete) rather than penalties (see Acts of 15 July 1975 and 30 June 1983); the other seeks to reinstate deterrence by retribution and neutralisation by a selective increase of prison sentences (see Acts of 22 November 1978, 2 February 1981 and 9 September 1986), not so much in the interests of equality but in an attempt to put an end to a supposed laxity of the courts, exemplified by the difference between the statutory penalties and the penalties actually imposed.79 |
7.120
The German Penal Code contains what Weigend calls a compromise formula that states rather than resolves the perennial conflict between retributivists and rehabilitators:80
The culpability of the offender is the basis of sentencing. The effects which the punishment is expected to have on the offender's future life in society shall be taken into account.81 |
7.121
In fact, rehabilitation has never been more than a complementary purpose of punishment in practice, though regarded as co-equal with retribution in theory. German courts are precluded from prolonging a sentence beyond the limits set by the desert principle in order to facilitate the rehabilitation of the offender.82 (This, however, can be circumvented by recourse to non-punitive measures like preventive detention, which are discussed below).
7.122
Two German commentators, Horn and Schoech, have made a novel proposal for the interpretation of the statutory formula in a non-self-contradictory fashion. They suggest that culpability and rehabilitation be the guiding themes of different phases of the sentencing process. The length of sentence would be determined, as an initial step, according to the desert of the offender. The nature of the sentence (imprisonment, probation, fine) would then be dictated by rehabilitative theory.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=198 |
7.123
Sentences of up to a year would be interchangeable (and the majority of sentences lie in that range). The choice among modes of punishment, as opposed to its quantum, should be guided, according to this proposal, by criminological knowledge rather than by an assessment of culpability.83
7.124
Stated thus simply, the Horn/Schoech scheme is not dissimilar to the hybrid choice of method approach discussed above.84 The criticisms voiced by German commentators are therefore of interest, as summarised by Weigend:
Critics argue that mechanical allocation of sentencing considerations to different phases of sentencing is too simple to be fair. Nor does the statute permit the total exclusion of rehabilitative considerations from the determination of the length of the sentence. Finally, the proposal offers no solution to the problem of sentencing in serious cases, where the conflict between culpability (which requires a long prison term) and rehabilitation (which is often best served by noncustodial treatment) is most acute.85 |
7.125
It is submitted that the first two criticisms could be answered by greater sophistication in operating the choice of approach method, but the third remains problematical.
7.126
Robert noted, however, a growing realisation that there exists no consensus on the function of criminal penalties (nor of the criminal law), and that a sentence cannot of itself resolve social problems, and must be content simply to preserve the authority of the law and promote its observance in a spirit of justice and equity.86
7.127
But whether continental judicial systems are prepared to follow more precise instructions on the nature and length of sentences (as must be necessary if simple uniformity and proportionality become chief aims of sentencing) is open to question.87Robert does remark that up till now, the means available to European courts to promote individualisation in sentencing varied enormously, dependent largely on the proportion of the procedure devoted to a sentencing hearing. In England and Sweden, this is of considerable importance, in Italy and France it plays only a marginal role.88 This may be explained by the extent to which the preliminary investigation in an inquisitorial system can provide the necessary information for fixing sentences. Nonetheless, the comparative rarity of recourse to personality studies casts doubt on the individualisation of
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=199 |
sentences in such circumstances, implying that more importance is attached to the act than to the personality.89
7.128
The amenability of judges to the influence of judicial precedent is of considerable importance for the success of any sentencing initiatives. While in countries applying the Romano-Germanic system, judicial precedent is not normally a source of domestic law, there is evidence that in Italy, Belgium and France, objective criteria for the commonest types of offence are being fixed by the courts for certain offences cheque fraud, misappropriation, traffic infractions, shoplifting and that penalties are fixed in some chambers by genuine judicial precedents based on local constants.90 In France and Germany, instructions and scales are distributed to courts or to prosecuting authorities (who are subject to superior instructions) based on past judicial practice. But, as Robert points out, this relates only to the mass of very frequent repetitive offences committed in similar circumstances which are ill-adapted to individualisation.91 In general, judicial sentencing in France and Italy is governed by tradition, non-rational factors and the courts' concept of criminal policy and not by criteria laid down by statute or case-law, with judges exercising too wide a discretionary power without instructions or supervision.92
7.129
The Scandinavian countries are much closer to the Anglo-Saxon Model in Denmark, Norway and Sweden, judicial decisions are of real influence in subsequent analogous cases. In Denmark, this reaches its greatest extent, where the presidents of the two High Courts may consolidate practice with guidelines for offences such as traffic offences.93
7.130
Robert also gives an account of the erosion of judicial control of sentencing at both the pre-hearing and post-hearing stages in most European countries, through the broad discretion given to prosecution authorities and through selective or varied enforcement of penalties (especially imprisonment).94
A number of European countries make special provision for dangerous offenders. Sometimes, such provisions exist on the statute books but may be said to be dormant, as in the case of Norway.95 In Germany, there is no provision for the punishment of dangerous offenders.96 There are, however, what are termed measures of rehabilitation and prevention.97 As these are not considered to be punishment, they are not subject to the usual rules on
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=200 |
sentencing. Two medical measures are placement in a psychiatric hospital and committal to an alcohol/drug dependency unit. The third measure is preventive detention.98 At present, some 40 preventive detention orders are given annually: three quarters relate to rape, robbery and homicide, the rest to burglars and professional fraudsters. An order of preventive detention is imposed with a prison sentence and is served after the term of imprisonment. The prerequisites for such an order are a number of previous convictions and prison terms, and a finding that these, combined with the instant offence, are the expression of an inclination to commit very serious offences. The maximum detention is 10 years (unless the offender has been so detained before). Release is necessary as soon as the detainee can responsibly be allowed out of the institution to see whether he will desist from further offence.99 These decisions are the responsibility of a specialised court.100
7.131
The Council of Europe has yet to produce a final report on sentencing. The Select Committee of Sentencing Experts, chaired by Professor Ashworth, has, however, published Draft Recommendations on Consistency in Sentencing, with a commentary by Professor Ashworth. Many of the proposals are in accordance with the recommendations of this paper. Those recommendations and commentary are published in full below as Appendix A.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=201 |
8.1
That there is a general lack of concern about sentencing problems in continental Europe, and a tendency to rely on formalist solutions where such problems are raised, is illustrated by the responses of various States participating in the European Committee on Crime Problems to a questionnaire circulated by Professor Ashworth.1 It is worthwhile summarising some of the results of this questionnaire.
8.2
The first four questions sought information on any techniques, restrictions, etc, adopted in order to reduce disparity in prosecution or sentencing practice.
8.3
In countries applying the principle of mandatory prosecution, it was stated that no discretion existed at this stage, so no techniques to reduce disparities had been introduced.2
8.4
Where discretion does exist to prosecute, the adoption of different approaches is sought to be prevented by the issue of circulars or guidelines following consultation between chief prosecutors.3 In some cases, summary fines or financial settlements in lieu of prosecution were also cited,4 but it is difficult to appreciate how the existence of this option can guide recourse to this or other courses of action available to the prosecution. A proposal in Norway, during the preparation of the Penal Prosecution Act, 1987, that the defendant have a right
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=202 |
of appeal to a superior prosecuting authority eg. on the ground that there was a disparity in the prosecution's treatment of his case, was ultimately rejected.5 This is an interesting idea. It appears that a similar, informal practice exists in Ireland: defendants can (and do) contact the DPP's office to complain about prosecutions taken by the Gardaν, etc.6
8.5
More countries had taken account of the possibility of disparities at the sentencing stage. Luxembourg has ordained the preparation of a standard prosecution application by the public prosecutor so as to introduce standardised case-laws for comparable cases.7 This seems a useful practice, but one whose utility is probably limited to the more common minor crimes for which there can be few special circumstances that should aggravate or mitigate punishment.
8.6
Another Luxembourg innovation has been the diversion of criminal cases, at first instance as well as on appeal, to a special court chamber whose members are appointed for a certain term, with the object of attaining greater uniformity of decision-making.8
8.7
In other countries, disparity or severity of sentence may be a ground of appeal (e.g. in Cyprus, Denmark, Luxembourg and many others) or of Royal Pardon (e.g. in Belgium); courts may have more than one judge in order to ensure consistency (e.g. in Greece); fixed sum fines have been introduced in specific fields, especially for traffic offences (e.g. in Switzerland and various other states). Legislative control of judicial discretion in sentencing is almost non-existent in some countries (Norway, Switzerland); in most, upper (and sometimes lower) limits are set for each offence type. (See especially Belgium, Italy, Portugal).
8.8
In general, therefore, the measures taken at this stage to reduce sentencing disparities are not very interventionist. In only two countries (Luxembourg and Greece) is there any provision for the righting of sentencing disparities by the authorities responsible for the execution of sentences.9 In most countries, early release either cannot or is not resorted to in order to achieve such a goal.10
8.9
The autonomy of judges rules out in most jurisdictions judicial provision of general advice, guidance or instruction either on appeal or otherwise. In many countries, the restriction of the competence of higher courts to the supervision
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=203 |
of purely legal points strengthens this trend.11 Only Norway and Denmark are substantial exceptions. In Norway, a higher court may provide general guidance for judges in lower courts; in Denmark, the Presidents of High Courts issue guidelines on certain matters. These however, are only in respect of minor offences; nonetheless, in general, judgments of higher courts are followed. In Norway, the Supreme Court is the only court of appeal in criminal cases, with competence to review all aspects of the case. The purpose of this system of direct appeal is to ensure an efficient attention to uniformity in law and sentencing. The Supreme Court is thus given the authority to avoid concrete disparity and to draw general guidelines for the lower courts.12 Interestingly, almost half (46%) of all cases of the Norwegian Supreme Court concern inter alia sentencing appeals, so that a considerable jurisprudence must by now have been built up.
8.10
It is worth noting that plea-bargaining is not accepted in theory, and almost unknown in practice, in Scandinavia, as well as in many other continental European countries.13 A formal plea of guilt is not conclusive the court still has a duty to find out the truth, so that a confession is not given conclusive evidentiary weight.14
8.11
Nonetheless, there are practices in place which concede considerable power to prosecutors. In the Netherlands, judges tend (but are not bound) to follow the guidelines of the Public Prosecutions Department which are applied in demanding a sentence in court.15 These have been issued in respect of inter alia contravention of weapons laws, drunken driving and drug offences (contravention of the Opium Act). In respect of the latter, for example, the Public Prosecutions Department has indicated in its guidelines which minimum statutory penalties are to be demanded for certain categories of offenders such as traffickers, couriers, addicts and dealers.16In practice the guidelines and the sentence demanded by the public prosecutor play an important role in sentencing by the court. They reduce undesirable inequality in sentencing, provide the court with some guidance in sentencing and compel judges to provide reasons for sentences which deviate from the normal.17 One point of criticism that might be raised, however, is that this scheme gives too much influence and initiative to prosecutors; there is no sign that defence counsel's contributions carry equal weight. In the absence of fuller evidence, it is impossible to pronounce on this question.18
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=204 |
8.12
In Germany, the prosecutor is accorded unusual deference within the criminal justice system, based on the view that he is a neutral officer, who upholds the law rather than necessarily seeking a conviction, so that he can safely be trusted to share sentencing authority with the judge.19
8.13
In two common situations, the prosecutor can contribute significantly to the determination of the sentence imposed on the defendant. In minor cases, the judge can give a provisional written judgment containing a criminal conviction and a specific sentence, based on the prosecutor's file this becomes final if the accused does not appeal within a week. If he or she does, an ordinary trial is held. The novel feature of this system (to Irish eyes) is that it is the prosecutor who decides if this process (Strafbefehlsverfahren, or penal order proceeding) is to be employed, and who drafts the provisional judgment including the sentence. The judge cannot alter this he or she must either accept it in its entirety, or reject and order a trial.20 In fact, judicial consent is withheld in less than 1 per cent of cases, not least because there exist informal channels of negotiation between judges and prosecutors.21
8.14
Almost half of all criminal cases are processed by Strafbefehl,22 and 85% of these penal orders become final either because the defendant acquiesces or because he withdraws an appeal filed.23 The result is that prosecutors can virtually dictate legal outcomes in vast numbers of cases without there ever being a trial a situation resembling plea-bargaining, except that the accused's position is significantly weaker, as there is no bargaining process as such.
8.15
In a second situation, more akin to their powers in other European countries, prosecutors can recommend a sentence after trial. There is approximately 50% judicial adherence to such recommendations. They are most significant in that judges will rarely impose a harsher sentence than that recommended in practice, the recommendation is viewed as the most severe appropriate sentence, and so sets an outer limit to the punishment a defendant can normally expect to receive.24 It may be remarked, however, that the prosecutor's role in recommending the harshest appropriate sentence sits ill with his or her supposedly neutral role as a court officer when operating the Strafbefehl system and effectively setting sentences himself or herself.
8.16
An important factor when judges come to place a particular crime on the scale of seriousness is the presence of features which the law describes as aggravating or mitigating. Naturally, in a jurisdiction with a clearly defined and non-contradictory sentencing policy, these could in any event be deduced. Some European states expressly list such factors (usually non-exhaustively) in positive
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=205 |
law; in others, they may be formulated by the judiciary. Sometimes, aggravating and mitigating factors are defined on an offence-by-offence basis, and so vary according to the offence charged.25
8.17
In Germany, the Criminal Law Code does not define aggravating or mitigating factors as such. Most of the factors cited in the general part of the Code can be aggravating in some cases and mitigating in others.26
8.18
In the special part of the Code, the exemplary description of really serious cases is, in a way, similar to the definition of aggravating circumstances e.g. theft:
burglary, a specially secured object, weapons as an object of the theft, professional stealing, stealing from a museum, church or helpless person.27 |
8.19
In this respect, therefore, Germany mirrors the French practice of defining these factors on an offence-by-offence basis.28 Nonetheless, the courts have also developed a number of factors in practice, although the appeal courts are cautious about giving general advice on this topic.
8.20
The difficulty in giving advice on this issue must be considerable in a system, such as Germany's, which has been dedicated to pursuing conflicting sentencing objectives.29 Finland is exemplary in this respect: its Sentencing Act contains both general sentencing principles (chief of which is proportionality of punishment to offence seriousness and culpability)30 and a non-exhaustive list of more specific sentencing criteria.31
8.21
These factors, as well as the normative starting points32 are employed not only to determine the level of the offender's responsibility and consequent punishment, but also to choose between a custodial and non-custodial type of sentence.33
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=206 |
9.1
In the following chapters, we will concentrate on examining methods of implementing sentencing policy and of regulating judicial sentencing discretion which have been developed in other jurisdictions. Broadly speaking, two approaches are discernible: those of court sentencing guidelines and of sentencing starting points. The former is almost exclusively of North American invention; the latter is of continental Europe origin, but may in fact be very appealing to those weaned on the common law. They share many features in common, employ statistical methodologies which are in some degree interchangeable, and may on their face appear very similar. Moreover, both approaches have their roots in the principles of proportionality and just deserts which it is proposed should be pursued by sentencers in this country. However, presumptive guidelines are ostensibly much more rigorous in their control of judges' discretion. The two schools of thought are not internally uniform. Numerous US states, Canada and the US federal jurisdiction, have adopted guidelines schemes which are in many respects dissimilar these will be considered in detail in the following three sections, and their possible extension to Ireland assessed. The related but less imaginative and appealing notion of determinate sentencing will also be discussed. The two chief contending means of devising sentencing starting points the Finnish and the Victorian will then be examined in a similar fashion.
9.2
The State of Minnesota in the U.S. was the first jurisdiction to adopt a system of presumptive sentencing guidelines, which was a radical departure from previous, highly discretionary sentencing regimes in America, and which has subsequently been extremely influential. It was the trigger which set in motion a range of sentencing reform projects in the United States involving sentencing commissions, sentencing guidelines, parole abolition or parole guidelines,
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=207 |
mandatory sentence laws, determinate sentencing, plea bargaining bans and
rules, and appellate sentence review.1
9.3
A combination of institutional arrangements what Tonry calls the sentencing commission model2 was central to this new departure. The Minnesota scheme involved:
|
9.4
The sentencing commission was deemed indispensable because it was thought to possess the institutional capacity to develop sentencing standards of much greater subtlety and specificity than any legislature could (not to mention the judicial bench).3 Its important political role in promoting a policy which was in very many respects revolutionary will be alluded below.4 First, the components of the scheme will be set out.
9.5
The guidelines apply only to felony convictions. Felony offences are divided into ten categories based on levels of seriousness. Offenders are categorised into seven groups on the basis of criminal history scores (largely grounded on the number of prior felony convictions). The resulting rankings are used to calculate the applicable presumptive sentence by means of a guideline matrix (See Table 1) a table with offence severity and criminal history as its axes. The interior cells of the table contain the presumptive sentence ranges. The sentencing court in any case needs simply to refer to the cell at the intersection of the row and column relevant to the defendants' crime, and his past record. Those whose offence and prior convictions, if any, place them in a cell above or to the left of the bold black line are presumptively not to receive a state prison sentence (the numbers in such cells indicating the prison sentence to be imposed on failure of probation or similar conditions). For those whose cases fall below the dividing line, the single number is the presumptive sentence in months, but the judge may impose any sentence from within the narrow range shown at the bottom of each cell. Tonry states succinctly the advantages of such a scheme:
Presumptive sentencing guidelines provide a mechanism for expressing sentencing standards in a form that has more authority than voluntary guidelines, is less rigid than mandatory sentencing laws, and is much more specific than the maximum and minimum sentences set out in the |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=208 |
criminal codes.5 |
9.6
It should be noted that the presumptive sentence is not mandatory, but only substantial and compelling circumstances allow a departure from it. Such a departure must be supported by written reasons, and either prosecution or defence can appeal the decision to depart. This has given Minnesota its first meaningful system of appellate sentence review6 and has helped clarify the appropriate considerations in a sentencing court's decisions to depart from the presumptive sentence. It is the third distinctive plank in Tonry'ssentencing commission model. There is a distinction between those departures from the presumptive sentence which are dispositional, and those which are durational.
9.7
Dispositional departures include both execution of a presumptively stayed sentence, and stay of a presumptively executed sentence. The sentencing court may address the question of whether the presumptive sentence would be best for the defendant as an individual and for society.7 In practice, this is a question of his amenability or unamenability to probation.8
9.8
Social factors such as age, remorse, prior record, co-operation with the authorities and with the court, etc. are all relevant in such cases.
9.9
Social and other factors are excluded from consideration in respect of durational departures. The guidelines provide that race, sex, employment or social position, or the defendants exercise of constitutional rights (i.e. the decision to contest his or her guilt at trial) should not be used as reasons for departure. The appellate courts have also ruled out any consideration of prior criminal record, or of the elements of the offence, standing alone, as these are employed in the first place to calculate the presumptive sentence.9
9.10
Justifications for departure must not be too vague or speculative (if only because they would be of little use to a reviewing court). Instead, durational departure must normally rest on the particular characteristics of the offence i.e. whether the defendant's conduct was significantly more or less serious than that typically involved in the commission of the crime in question.10
9.11
The guidelines provide a non-exclusive list of factors that illustrate a typical criminal conduct.
9.12
In mitigation, they suggest aggression by the victim, lack of judgment due to physical or mental impairment, and the minor or passive role of the offender in the crime, where applicable. Aggravating factors include cruelty and victim
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=209 |
vulnerability. Consideration of the course of conduct underlying the charge for which the defendant is being sentenced11 can allow sentencing courts to flirt with considering additional crimes for which the defendant was not convicted, though this is not otherwise permissible,12 e.g. as in Garcia, when ascertaining the circumstances of a kidnapping entailed examining allegations of sexual assault for which charges had earlier been dropped in a plea bargain.13 Unfortunately, no clear standard exists to distinguish such cases from those in which such a consideration is deemed improper.14 There exists considerable debate on such real offence sentencing and it does not conform entirely with our views.15
9.13
Appellate courts will not review a decision not to depart even in the presence of aggravating or mitigating factors; nor will they reverse a decision to depart unless there is a clear abuse of discretion.16 Where no reasons are stated a sentencing departure is not allowed.17 However, a reviewing court may also consider other bases of departure not expressly stated by the trial judge if the stated reasons are insufficient. Thus, as Simon points out,
the standard of review of sentencing departures is quite deferential to the sentencing court. Only clearly erroneous decisions will be reversed.18 |
Appellate courts will also be concerned with the extent of the departure from the presumptive range. Evans concerned two consecutive sentences of 15 years where the guidelines indicated consecutive sentences of two years each. The Minnesota Supreme Court concluded that generally in a case in which an upward departure in sentence length is justified, the upper limit will be double the presumptive sentence length.19 But in highly exceptional cases, a greater degree of departure might be permitted. This concession has led to a distinction between aggravating and severely aggravating circumstances between which, unfortunately, no clear boundary has been established by the Minnesota courts. Thus, little effective guidance has been provided to sentencing courts in this area. This may be due in part to the insignificant history of appellate review in America. The long maximum sentences in indeterminate sentencing systems, intended to permit the individualisation of punishment, which were so prevalent in the United States, were unconducive to the establishment of judicial standards of review. It was a significant achievement of the Minnesota Commission that it secured to the extent it did accountability of lower courts for their sentencing.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=210 |
9.14
A number of important features of the Minnesota sentencing guidelines scheme are attributable to bold policy decisions by the Sentencing Commission.20
|
9.15
Tonry reserves special praise for the work of the Commission in ensuring the adoption, and successful implementation of these measures with a minimum of inconvenience.27 Some reference to the methods of the Commission should be made, simply because similar schemes, as we shall see, have met with rejection or failure in other jurisdictions. The Commission had an unusually talented staff, and a politically knowledgeable chair. Also, members representing the judiciary and prosecutors could argue for the interests of their constituencies, and later persuade them of the merits of the Commission's package. The Commission's work was an open political process, in which the views of all interested groups could be expressed. Therefore, necessary compromises had been made, and considerable consensus reached, before its proposals were presented to the legislature. All these factors gave the Minnesota Guidelines Scheme considerable political potency, and probably account for their successful adoption in practice (schemes in many other states having been ignored or circumvented by judges and lawyers).
9.16
Nonetheless, the Minnesota Sentencing Guidelines are open to substantial criticism, of two varieties. The first concerns problems inherent in the system's design.
9.17
A major weakness in the design of the Guidelines was that they were limited from the outset to sentences of imprisonment, thus excluding some 80% of felony convictions which result in other penalties, and permitting unrestrained
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=212 |
discretion to continue.28 This was despite the enabling legislation placing non-incarcerative sanctions firmly within the Commission's ambit. In as much as up to one year's jail incarceration may be imposed as a condition of probation, the absence of guidance could well have produced considerable disparity29 jail here is quite distinct from state prison, and is not subject to the guidelines. Hardly surprisingly, there was little change in jail use in the period of the Guidelines' introduction.30
9.18
Allen sums up very effectively another criticism of the appealing, but possibly deluding, simplicity of the scheme's design:
Another problem arose from the simplicity of the system whereby each felony conviction is given one point on the criminal history score axis. There is no grading of these convictions to reflect the gravity of the offences; but grading would seem to be necessary if fairness between offenders is to be maintained. This failure to grade past convictions would also seem to increase the significance of past convictions in many cases over and above the significance of the current offence. This can result in an offender found guilty of a minor offence receiving a substantial prison sentence because he has a high criminal history score. The punishment then ceases to be proportionate to the gravity of the offence thus conflicting with the basic premise of a sentencing system founded on the just deserts rationale.31 |
9.19
This suggests an even greater cause for concern, that the two elements of offence severity and criminal record, so central to the reduction of discretion and of disparities at the sentencing stage, can be manipulated prior to that point. Many critics charge that the Minnesota System has simply caused discretion to shift from judges to prosecutors, where it is subject to even less scrutiny than before. Multiple charging of property offenders can see their criminal history scores rise very fast to levels justifying imprisonment, while the very great degree of certainty about the consequences of conviction of any charge preferred against an offender increases the influence of the prosecutor, who makes that choice, in the plea-bargaining process.32 That both of these factors were exploited by prosecutors is clear one reason is that they did not tend overwhelmingly to endorse the Commission's view on the non-imprisonment of property offenders. Tonry remarks on the issue as follows:
For example, an offender who in 1978 might have been permitted to plead guilty to one of four charged counts of larceny, might in 1982 be |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=213 |
required to plead guilty to all four. The next time he appeared in court, under the guidelines he would have four prior convictions and therefore be eligible for prison. The Commission changed its rules on counting prior convictions in an effort to offset this prosecutorial manipulation, with some success. Nonetheless, the experience demonstrates that even in Minnesota prosecutors will wilfully attempt to undermine policies with which they disagree.33 |
9.20
While charge negotiations (and reductions) also increased, and sentence negotiations diminished34 this latter practice has not disappeared. Pursuant to sentence negotiation is the single reason most commonly given by judges for departing from the guidelines, even though the Minnesota Supreme Court has held that this is inadequate justification; in practice, defendants who have agreed to a departure pursuant to a sentence negotiation, which will almost always be a departure downwards, are unlikely to lodge a sentence appeal.35
9.21
A conscious policy decision had been made, however, given the experimental nature of the scheme, that it was premature to constrain prosecutorial discretion. As it happens, prosecutorial manipulation has never extended to radical subversion; and efforts to counter it in other jurisdictions have had some success, as will be seen below.36
9.22
The second chief line of criticism concerns the implementation of the Minnesota Guidelines after the initial, apparently very successful stage. After a few years of guidelines experience, judicial practice began to revert to old habits: for low record violent offenders in 1983, imprisonment rates were significantly below those of the two previous years (though still ahead of the levels of the 1970's); for long record property offenders, the 1983 imprisonment rate ... was almost at the same level as the pre-guidelines imprisonment rate.37
9.23
Also, in 1982 and 1983, the prison population increased substantially. This was partly due to legislative increases of sentence severity for certain offences, but also, according to Knapp, to the increased power of the prosecutors being used to effect harsher sentences.38 However, Tonry has remarked that the problem has abated thanks to Commission alterations to the guidelines with the object of reducing average sentence lengths.39
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=214 |
TABLE E
APPENDIX I
IV. SENTENCING GUIDELINES GRID
Presumptive Sentence Lengths in Months
Italicised numbers within the grid denote the range within which a judge may sentence without the sentence being deemed a departure.
Offenders with non-imprisonments felony sentences are subjects to jail time according to law.
|
|
CRIMINAL HISTORY SCORE |
||||||
SEVERITY LEVELS OF CONVICTION OFFENCE |
0 |
1 |
2 |
3 |
4 |
5 |
6 or more |
|
Unauthorized Use of Motor Vehicle Possession of Marijuana |
I |
12* |
12* |
12* |
13 |
15 |
17 |
19 1820 |
Theft Related Crimes ($250$2500) Aggravated Forgery ($250$2500) |
II |
12* |
12* |
13 |
15 |
17 |
19 |
21 2022 |
Theft Crimes ($250$2500) |
III |
12* |
13 |
15 |
17 |
19 1820 |
22 2123 |
25 2426 |
Non-residential Burglary Theft Crimes (over $2500) |
IV |
12* |
15 |
18 |
21 |
25 2426 |
32 3034 |
41 3745 |
Residential Burglary Simple Robbery |
V |
18 |
23 |
27 |
30 2931 |
38 3640 |
46 4349 |
54 5058 |
Criminal Sexual Conduct 2nd Degree (a) & (b) |
VI |
21 |
26 |
30 |
34 3335 |
44 4246 |
54 5058 |
65 6070 |
Aggravated Robbery |
VII |
24 2325 |
32 3034 |
41 3844 |
49 4553 |
65 6070 |
81 7587 |
97 90104 |
Criminal Sexual Conduct 1st Degree Assault, 1st Degree |
VIII |
43 4145 |
54 5058 |
65 6070 |
76 7181 |
95 89101 |
113 106120 |
132 124140 |
Murder, 3rd Degree Murder, 2nd Degree (felony murder) |
IX |
105 102108 |
119 116122 |
127 124130 |
149 143155 |
176 168184 |
205 195215 |
230 218242 |
Murder, 2nd Degree (with intent) |
X |
120 116124 |
140 133147 |
162 153171 |
203 192214 |
243 231255 |
284 270298 |
324 309339 |
1st Degree Murder is excluded from the guidelines by law and continues to have a mandatory life sentence
□At the discretion of the judge, up to a year in jail and/or other non-jail sanctions can be imposed as conditions of probation
□Presumptive commitment to state imprisonment
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=215 |
9.24
The Minnesota experiment's initial success, and widespread disillusionment with the previously prevailing norm of indeterminate sentencing, led to that state's being followed by a wave of imitators, with mixed success. That movement has culminated in the adoption of the US Federal Guidelines.
9.25
In some states, the new scheme met with utter failure; in others, its effect was diluted by compromise; in yet others, substantial and valuable refinements were made which addressed some of the problems experienced in Minnesota.
9.26
In the state of Maine, a Sentencing Guidelines Commission was established in 1983, but its funding was insignificant, no full-time professional staff were appointed, and its members were ill-informed about developments elsewhere. It failed to produce guidelines, (many of its members had opposed them from the outset), and recommended only that a new commission be established.
9.27
In South Carolina, the Sentencing Guidelines Commission (established in 1982) made proposals which were rejected by the State Legislature, largely because its guidelines were opposed by the judiciary (including those judges who had served on the commission).40
9.28
These cases illustrate Tonry's point on the importance of the sentencing commission, and on the necessity of gaining political consensus on guidelines proposals. In New York state in particular, the guidelines movement was derailed by political opposition. That state's committee was very well staffed and funded, and had experience both of guidelines systems and of New York politics. A number of proposals, and eventually draft guidelines, were produced. However, the committee had failed to reach a consensus on its aims or motives; an especially influential member dissented; its report was exploited to fuel political disputes between various interest groups: and its proposed guidelines were rejected by the New York Legislature.41
9.29
In Connecticut, the sequence of events was most unusual. From 1979 on, its Commission developed a descriptive sentencing grid based on research into past sentencing practices, with the usual array of provisions for departures, mitigation, and so on. But the commission then publicly opposed adopting such
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=216 |
a scheme, and recommended the abolition of indeterminate sentencing and of parole, and the introduction of a statutory determinate sentencing system (which was done in July 1981).42
9.30
Pennsylvania's is an interesting case. As in the above instances, the Commission on Sentencing was a weak body, politically speaking, and failed to win the support of vital interests and constituencies in advance of the presentation of its initial guidelines, which succumbed to the law and order lobby in the legislature in 1981. Presumptive guidelines revised in accordance with the directions of the legislature were resubmitted in 1982 and passed into law. These new guidelines embodied a number of key compromises. Sentencing standards were more severe, and judicial discretion wider.
9.31
Most unusually, the guidelines prescribe ranges for minimum sentences only parole release has been retained, and judges have a full discretion over the maximum. Despite this, three ranges of minima are prescribed for every offence normal, aggravated and mitigated. No criteria are set for aggravation or mitigation, or for total departure from the guidelines except that the reason for any departure should be stated.
9.32
Because of all this, the high compliance rates claimed for the Pennsylvanian system are largely spurious. Substantial disparities can occur even within the guidelines, as Tonry points out, because judges can use the aggravating/mitigating factors at will, and because no efforts have been made to account for the role of plea bargaining in sentencing.43
9.33
There is some debate on the extent of this problem. Tonry is of the view that it renders appellate review almost toothless:
[B]ecause the guideline ranges are broad, and because there are no rules governing when judges may depart from them, Pennsylvanian appellate courts will have difficulty knowing the basis by which a sentence appeal can or should be evaluated.44 |
9.34
However, an analysis of Pennsylvanian case-law does not bear this out entirely. Dowling has suggested that the guidelines have acquired the force of mandates which the sentencing judge deviates from at his peril and where in explaining his non-compliance he needs the elegance of a Holmes, the wit of Musmanno, and the profundity of Blackstone, if he is to satisfy his appellate brethren ... A 'common law' of punishment has grown out of successive appellate
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=217 |
decisions.45
9.35
As Schwartz puts it, these decisions have come to govern sentencing more than the guidelines.46 The shift in the degree of discretionary power accorded to trial courts was achieved in some cases by subterfuge, in Dowling's view: appellate courts would reverse the trial court under the guise of a failure to articulate properly the reasons for its sentence47 when they ultimately disagreed with the sentence imposed.48
9.36
Furthermore, in Commonwealth v Bullicki,49 having rejected the trial judge's sentence on a technicality, the Pennsylvania Superior Court remanded for sentence to be imposed within the range of the guidelines. In Commonwealth v Radabaugh,50 the trial judge imposed a higher than usual sentence for a drug offence, for stated reasons the Superior Court remanded for sentence specifically to be imposed within the minimum or mitigated range of the sentencing guidelines, despite a recognition by the Sentencing Commission itself that major drug trafficking may warrant a more severe sentence than suggested under the guidelines.51
9.37
This process culminated in the decision in Commonwealth v Hutchinson, in which the Pennsylvania Superior Court prescribed that only in exceptional cases and for sufficient reasons may a court deviate from the guidelines,52 despite the absence of this language in the sentencing code.
9.38
Dowling and Tonry approach this issue from very different points of view. Dowling is a Pennsylvanian judge and proponent of judicial discretion; Tonry is an advocate of classical guidelines systems, and rightly apprehends that unstructured discretion within such systems can make them effectively impotent. As it happens, Dowling's views have prevailed in Pennsylvania. The process described above has been reversed on constitutional grounds in Commonwealth v Sessions.53
9.39
Due to the inclusion of legislators and judges on the Sentencing Commission, and in order to avoid a violation of the separation of powers doctrine, the court held that the guidelines cannot, without more be given the effect of law, either as legislation or regulation, so as to by themselves alter the legal rights and duties of the parties or the court.54 The trial court has no 'duty' to impose a sentence considered appropriate by the Commission, and
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=218 |
need only take notice of the Commission's work.55 In the later Commonwealth v Devers56 a long line of decisions which had required an explicitly detailed statement by the trial judge of the reasons for the sentence imposed was abandoned and the court attacked the requirement that the judge tick off the statutorily mandated factors as a ritualistic litany like prayers before meals.
9.40
The result of this reversal of policy is that Tonry's criticisms stand the earlier attempt to transform the operation of the guidelines, in order more closely to mirror schemes such as that in Minnesota, failed. In any event, the collapse of appellate review, and of the moves to attribute more binding effect to such guidelines as exist, may not change very much. Because the parole board makes release decisions, it can, when it chooses, disregard idiosyncratic maximum sentences.57 Whether the parole board can exercise the same principled and general (as opposed to individualised) control over sentence review as a Superior Court might is, however, open to question.
9.41
Tonry would of course advocate the implementation of more rigorous guidelines; Dowling advocates the abandonment of appellate review in all but the most exceptional cases. Given the triumph of Dowling's view in Pennsylvania, and the almost unlimited judicial discretion remaining in the system, that State's presumptive guidelines have been almost fatally compromised they are effectively voluntary in character and relatively unhelpful even to those judges who choose to abide by them. It might be speculated that the existing Pennsylvania guidelines could form the nucleus of a viable system of starting points a speculation which will not, however, be pursued in this paper.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=219 |
TABLE F: PENNSYLVANIA GUIDELINES
Offence gravity score |
Prior record score |
Minimum rangea |
Aggravated minimum rangea |
Mitigated minimum rangea |
5 |
0 |
012 |
1218 |
non-confinement |
For example: Criminal |
1 |
312 |
1218 |
1 1/23 |
Mischief (Felony III): Theft |
2 |
512 |
1218 |
2 1/25 |
by Unlawful Taking (Felony |
3 |
812 |
1218 |
48 |
III): Theft by Receiving Stolen |
4 |
1827 |
2734 |
1418 |
Property (Felony III): |
5 |
2130 |
3038 |
1621 |
Briberyb |
6 |
2436 |
3645 |
1824 |
4 |
0 |
012 |
1218 |
non-confinement |
For example: Theft by |
1 |
012 |
1218 |
non-confinement |
receiving stolen property, less |
2 |
012 |
1218 |
non-confinement |
than $2,000, by force or threat |
3 |
512 |
1218 |
2 1/25 |
of force, or in breach of |
4 |
812 |
1218 |
48 |
fiduciary obligationb |
5 |
1827 |
2734 |
1418 |
|
6 |
2130 |
3038 |
1621 |
3 |
0 |
012 |
1218 |
non-confinement |
|
1 |
012 |
1218 |
non-confinement |
|
2 |
012 |
1218 |
non-confinement |
Most Misdemeanour I'sb |
3 |
012 |
1218 |
non-confinement |
|
4 |
312 |
1218 |
1 1/23 |
|
5 |
512 |
1218 |
2 1/25 |
|
6 |
812 |
1218 |
48 |
2 |
0 |
012 |
Statutory limitc |
non-confinement |
|
1 |
012 |
Statutory limitc |
non-confinement |
|
2 |
012 |
Statutory limitc |
non-confinement |
Most Misdemeanour II'sb |
3 |
012 |
Statutory limitc |
non-confinement |
|
4 |
012 |
Statutory limitc |
non-confinement |
|
5 |
212 |
Statutory limitc |
12 |
|
6 |
512 |
Statutory limitc |
2 1/25 |
1 |
0 |
06 |
Statutory limitc |
non-confinement |
|
1 |
06 |
Statutory limitc |
non-confinement |
|
2 |
06 |
Statutory limitc |
non-confinement |
Most Misdemeanour III'sb |
3 |
06 |
Statutory limitc |
non-confinement |
|
4 |
06 |
Statutory limitc |
non-confinement |
|
5 |
06 |
Statutory limitc |
non-confinement |
|
6 |
06 |
Statutory limitc |
non-confinement |
Notes
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=220 |
9.42
Interesting refinements of the classical Minnesota style guidelines have been introduced in Michigan, and in Washington. These serve to combat some of the problems presented by that initial experiment.
9.43
Michigan adopted presumptive guidelines by Supreme Court order in 1984, after an initial experimental period. This employed a grid with six levels of criminal history, and three of offence seriousness i.e. it embodied the same key variables as the Minnesota matrix. The focus is on the facts of the crime and the prior record of the offender. Other indirect attempts to measure the potential for rehabilitation (or stated conversely, the prospects of recidivism) were thought by the Sentencing Guidelines Advisory Committee to be inappropriate for inclusion in the sentencing guidelines.
9.44
The introduction of the guidelines saw the diminution of statistically significant racial disparity in sentencing in all of the nine crime groups (formerly a considerable problem) and an overall compliance rate of some 80% was achieved.58 Interestingly, the guidelines are largely descriptive they are designed to reproduce and reinforce current mean sentencing practice, rather than to prescribe entirely new standards. One approach is not necessarily preferable to the other in any jurisdiction, levels of satisfaction (or otherwise) with prevailing standards should dictate which is adopted.59 Adherence to a coherent sentencing policy seems a prerequisite for the sort of satisfactory sentencing practice which would justify a descriptive scheme.
9.45
Because the guidelines are meant to reflect present attitudes, substantial deviations from them are an even greater cause for concern than in a prescriptive system high levels of departure suggest that the reflection of current practice is not sufficiently accurate. McComb remarks as follows:
One particular area, mentioned by numerous judges, concerned the guidelines' handling of the violent crimes contained in the Assault, Criminal Sexual Conduct, and Robbery crime groups. Certain crimes in the assaultive crimes groups have compliance rates in the vicinity of 60%. These problem areas were investigated in depth. Armed robbery, because it is the most frequently occurring violent crime, was the most conspicuous example. If it were clear that the sentence ranges for armed robbery were so low, it would be a simple matter to increase the recommended sentence ranges. The problem is that there were an equal number of departures above and below the recommended sentence ranges in armed robbery. Although the nature of the problems differed from grid to grid, the low compliance rates in the assaultive crimes could |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=221 |
not be overcome by adjusting the recommended ranges or adding additional variables. In short, the problems defied simple analysis.60 |
9.46
It became apparent that the point values for the prior record variables and offence variables, the 3 =3= 6 grid structure and the recommended sentences were not consistent with current sentencing practice or with each other (or both). Offenders placed in the same grid cell were not always very similar in point of culpability, thus deterring compliance.
9.47
A substantial revision of the guidelines was conducted. 4 x 4 grids were substituted for 3 x 6; four levels of prior record were thought sufficient to divide up the realm of prior offences (instead of 6). Prior Record Levels are now stated as follows:
A |
No Prior Record |
0 points |
B |
Low Prior Record |
124 points |
C |
Moderate Prior Record |
2549 points |
D |
Extensive Prior Record |
50 + points |
9.48
At the same time, a fourth level of offence severity was added to separate out the various degrees of culpability:
I |
Low Offense Seriousness |
0 9 points |
II |
Medium Offense Seriousness |
1024 points |
III |
High Offense Seriousness |
2549 points |
IV |
Very High Offense Seriousness |
50 + points |
9.49
The importance of these changes will become clear after a discussion of the major innovation of the revised guidelines.
9.50
It was necessary to reassess, and to distinguish from each other, factors of greater and of less significance, in the allocation of the offender to a place in the grid, so that similarly circumstanced offenders could be similarly located.
9.51
In both the old and revised schemes, the judge calculates a number of points for each prior record variable (PRV) and each applicable offence variable (OV). In the original model, points from zero to four were attached to various factors to illustrate their order of importance within the context of each variable. The following two examples are illustrative.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=222 |
OV 1 |
Weapon: Presence, Type and Use |
4 = |
a firearm discharged or pointed at victim: touching with other weapon |
3 = |
a firearm displayed but not pointed |
2 = |
any weapon, other than a firearm, displayed in a threatening manner |
1 = |
any weapon, other than a firearm, displayed; a firearm implied or possessed, but not displayed |
0 = |
no weapon displayed, implied or possessed |
OV 9 |
Offender's Role |
3 = |
leader in multiple offender situation |
2 = |
active participant in multiple offender situation |
1 = |
alone |
0 = |
minor or peripheral role |
9.52
But the intervals between factors were just one point, even though discharging a firearm may be signally more serious than displaying one, and so on. The relationship between the categories of offence variable also was hardly accounted for in the former system e.g. leading a number of offenders was equivalent, in point terms, to displaying a firearm, which is arguably more serious. McComb summed up the problem thus:
While existing point values capture the order of importance within a specific variable, they do not constitute an interval scale that can be used to compare categories within or between variables.61 |
9.53
Over 50,000 cases were analysed, to try accurately to assess the reasoning of sentencing judges.62 The resulting scoring system reflects not only the order but also their relative magnitude.63 Scoring is now on a scale of one to one hundred, and OV1 and OV9 were redesigned as follows:
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=223 |
OV 1 |
Weapon: Presence, Type and Use |
25 = |
a firearm discharged by offender during commission of the offence |
15 = |
a firearm pointed toward victim or touch with another weapon |
5 = |
a firearm displayed, implied, or possessed; any other weapon displayed |
0 = |
no firearm displayed, implied, or possessed; no other weapon |
OV 9 |
Offender's Role |
10 = |
leader in multiple offender situation |
0 = |
not a leader |
9.54
The old and reformed scales for OV2 illustrate how important is the scoring within the variable and in relation to other variables:
OV 2 |
Physical Attack and/or Injury |
6 = |
victim killed |
5 = |
serious impairment of body function or permanent serious disfigurement |
3 = |
bodily injury |
1 = |
touching beyond that needed to commit the instant offence |
0 = |
no touching or assault |
OV 2 |
Physical Attack and/or Injury |
100 = |
victim killed |
50 = |
victim treated with excessive brutality |
25 = |
bodily injury and/or subjected to terrorism |
0 = |
no injury |
9.55
McComb offers the following comments on the new scales:
Notice that within the context of OV2, the fact that a person is killed is now four times more important than bodily injury. Comparing OV1 and OV2, it is apparent that bodily injury is of the same importance as the aggravated use of a firearm. Each of these, in turn, are only half as important as excessive brutality. Finally, all are substantially less important than the fact that the victim is killed.64 |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=224 |
9.56
It is now worth looking again at the revised grid. The point values for the Prior Record Levels are set so that the extensiveness of the prior record is consistent with the verbal descriptions attached to each of the four levels, from no previous convictions at Level A to Level D, which includes all those who have had at least two high severity felonies. Level B does not include anyone who has been convicted of a high severity felony, while Level C embraces those who have a single high severity felony on their records, or two of low severity.
9.57
It will be appreciated that this is a great deal more sophisticated than the simple Minnesota points allocation system, so prone to manipulation by the prosecution through multiple charges; it is illustrative of the possibility of countering abuses through improved system design, and Minnesota has proceeded to introduce some reforms to its own method of computing criminal history scores. Similarly, the Offence Variable Levels are much more reflective of the needs of the system in the second edition of the Michigan model. In general, that model can be concluded to be a successful development of Minnesotan innovations.
9.58
Washington's Sentencing Reform Act, 1981 came into force in 1984. It shares many features with the Minnesota scheme. Parole was abolished, the role of sentencing was declared to be punishment, there was a shift towards incarcerating violent offenders, and a presumptive grid was established, based on the same factors as Minnesota's (but with somewhat broader sentencing ranges see Table G).
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=225 |
TABLE G
Washington sentencing guidelines
Seriousness level |
Offender score |
|||||||||
|
0 |
1 |
2 |
3 |
4 |
5 |
6 |
7 |
8 |
9 or more |
XIV |
Life sentence without parole/death penalty |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
||
XIII |
23y 4m |
24y 4m |
25y 4m |
26y 4m |
27y 4m |
28y 4m |
30y 4m |
32y 10m |
36y |
40y |
|
240320 |
250333 |
261347 |
271361 |
281374 |
291388 |
312416 |
338450 |
370493 |
411548 |
XII |
12y |
13y |
14y |
15y |
16y |
17y |
19y |
21y |
25y |
29y |
|
123164 |
134178 |
144192 |
154205 |
165219 |
175233 |
195260 |
216288 |
257342 |
298397 |
XI |
6y |
6y 9m |
7y 6m |
8y 3m |
9y |
9y 9m |
12y 6m |
13y 6m |
15y 6m |
17y 6m |
|
6282 |
6992 |
77102 |
85113 |
93123 |
100133 |
129171 |
139185 |
159212 |
180240 |
X |
5y |
5y 6m |
6y |
6y 6m |
7y |
7y 6m |
9y 6m |
10y 6m |
12y 6m |
14y 6m |
|
5168 |
5775 |
6282 |
6789 |
7296 |
77102 |
98130 |
108144 |
129171 |
149198 |
IX |
3y |
3y 6m |
4y |
4y 6m |
5y |
5y 6m |
7y 6m |
8y 6m |
10y 6m |
12y 6m |
|
3141 |
3648 |
4154 |
4661 |
5168 |
5775 |
77102 |
87116 |
108144 |
129171 |
VIII |
2y |
2y 6m |
3y |
3y 6m |
4y |
4y 6m |
6y 6m |
7y 6m |
8y 6m |
10y 6m |
|
2127 |
2634 |
3141 |
3648 |
4154 |
4661 |
6789 |
77102 |
87116 |
108144 |
VII |
18m |
2y |
2y 6m |
3y |
3y 6m |
4y |
5y 6m |
6y 6m |
7y 6m |
8y 6m |
|
1520 |
2127 |
2634 |
3141 |
3648 |
4154 |
5775 |
6789 |
77102 |
87116 |
VI |
13m |
18m |
2y |
2y 6m |
3y |
3y 6m |
4y 6m |
5y 6m |
6y 6m |
7y 6m |
|
12+14 |
1520 |
2127 |
2634 |
3141 |
3648 |
4661 |
5775 |
6789 |
77102 |
V |
9m |
13m |
15m |
18m |
2y 2m |
3y 2m |
4y |
5y |
6y |
7y |
|
612 |
12+14 |
1317 |
1520 |
2229 |
3343 |
4154 |
5168 |
6282 |
7296 |
IV |
6m |
9m |
13m |
15m |
18m |
2y 2m |
3y 2m |
4y 2m |
5y 2m |
6y 2m |
|
39 |
612 |
12+14 |
1317 |
1520 |
2229 |
3343 |
4357 |
5370 |
6384 |
III |
2m |
5m |
8m |
11m |
14m |
20m |
2y 2m |
3y 2m |
4y 2m |
5y |
|
13 |
38 |
412 |
912 |
12+16 |
1722 |
2229 |
3343 |
4357 |
5168 |
II |
090 |
4m |
6m |
8m |
13m |
16m |
20m |
2y 2m |
3y 2m |
4y 2m |
|
Days |
26 |
39 |
412 |
12+14 |
1418 |
1722 |
2229 |
3343 |
4357 |
I |
060 |
090 |
3m |
4m |
5m |
8m |
13m |
16m |
20m |
2y 2m |
|
Days |
Days |
25 |
26 |
38 |
412 |
12+14 |
1418 |
1722 |
2229 |
Note
Bold type presents presumptive sentence ranges in months. Midpoints are included as a reference point (y = years, m = months). 12+ equals one year and one day. For a few crimes, the presumptive sentences in the high offender score columns exceed the statutory maximums. In these cases, the statutory maximum applies.
Additional time added to the presumptive sentence if the offender or an accomplice was armed with a deadly weapon: 24 months (Rape 1, Robbery 1, Kidnapping 1) 18 months (Burglary 1) 12 months (Assault 2, Escape 1, Kidnapping 2, Burglary 2 of a building other than a dwelling, Delivery or Possession of a controlled substance with intent to deliver)
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=226 |
9.59
However, a number of lessons were learned from the Minnesota experience. For example the guidelines extend to both felonies and misdemeanours (whereas Minnesota's dealt only with felonies). More importantly, the Washington Commission was alive to the potential in guidelines systems for prosecution manipulation both of the offender's criminal history score (through multiple charging) and of the offence seriousness level (through charge bargaining). Such manipulation is facilitated by the relative certainty of sentence for particular combinations of offence and prior record. It was decided to try to structure the discretion of the prosecution by promulgating statewide prosecutorial charging and bargaining guidelines.65
9.60
Washington has parted company with Minnesota in a more worrying fashion in respect of appellate review, despite the two states' guidelines making almost identical provision for it. In both cases, departure from the guidelines is permitted only for substantial and compelling reasons.66
9.61
There are three grounds for review of such sentences:
|
9.62
This reluctance by Washington's appellate courts to review sentencing departures extends to review of the extent of departures from the presumptive ranges. In particular, in State v Stalker,78 Minnesota's doubling rule was dismissed as an arbitrary imposition, not necessarily desired by the legislature, and restrictive of the trial judge's discretion. It was observed by the majority in Oxborrow that the sentence would have been grossly inadequate if limited to a mere doubling of the presumptive range, and that in Minnesota the rule had proven to be difficult to apply and somewhat unworkable.79
9.63
Utter J, in dissent, urged the contrary, saying that the rule would give principled guidance to the sentencing courts.80 While it has already been admitted that the Minnesota position is problematical, it is submitted that it offers scope for some principled control of discretion, which must have been intended when the legislature provided for a meaningful appellate review of exceptional sentences.81 In one hundred years, only one sentence has successfully been overturned on appeal due to a trial court abuse of discretion in sentencing a criminal in Washington.82Altman comments that appellate review under the Sentencing Reform Acts standard could result in the appellate
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=228 |
courts merely rubber-stamping the trial courts' exceptional sentences.83
9.64
The contrary argument is that the legislature recognised that not all exceptional fact patterns could be anticipated and that the trial court is in the best position to tailor exceptional sentences to the facts of each particular case.84 Nonetheless, the abuse of discretion standard must lead to some degree of sentencing disparity, i.e. the prescription of disproportionate sentence lengths for similarly committed crimes.85
9.65
Goodloe J argued in Armstrong for the introduction of the Minnesota doubling rule on the extent of departures, especially if the only substantive ground for reversing a departure was to be abuse of discretion. This should apply to most exceptional cases, save where the nature of the crime is so outrageous and heinous that a sentence greater than twice the presumptive range is justified the distinction should be made by comparing the nature of the offence committed to the typical offence contemplated by the statute.86 While difficult at first, a body of case-law would eventually build up to help the Court make the necessary distinction between ordinary and extraordinary exceptional cases.
9.66
Nonetheless, the Washington Supreme Court rejected the doubling rule in Oxborrow, as was remarked above, with the result that appellate review in that state has been effectively disarmed by those whose task it was to implement it. The adoption of an almost impassable review standard in Washington is certainly disappointing. However, it is as well to remember that such disparities as do arise will exist only among those who receive departure sentences. In 1985, only 3.5% of cases decided under the Sentencing Reform Act resulted in exceptional sentences the potential disparity thus compares well with the enormous disparity problems under Washington's former sentencing system.87 This does not, however, excuse the downgrading of the effect of appellate review in a limited number of cases, where the potential for injustice is especially great.
9.67
From an initially very similar starting point, Florida's courts moved in a very different direction in respect of appeal policy. In State v Mischler,88 it was held that an appellate court's function in a sentencing guidelines case is merely to review the reasons given to support departure and determine whether the trial court abused its discretion in finding those reasons 'clear and convincing'.89
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=229 |
9.68
This apparently deferential standard of review has in fact been developed to exclude a large number of considerations from the sentencing process. It was held in Mischler that the court's reasons must be supported by facts proven beyond reasonable doubt (though later legislation substituted for this a requirement merely of the preponderance of the evidence)90 and that the reasons must be of such weight as to produce in the mind of the judge a firm belief or conviction, without hesitancy, that departure is warranted.91
9.69
The Mischler court also established a number of categories of reasons which may never justify departure from the guidelines. Some are actually prohibited by the guidelines themselves e.g. prior arrests without accompanying convictions.92 Others are factors already taken into account in calculating the guidelines score e.g. prior criminal record.93 Such a rule is common to most such systems.
9.70
Inherent components of the crime of conviction are also excluded, e.g. in Mischler, breach of a fiduciary relationship could not be an aggravating factor in a sentence for embezzlement. Otherwise, departure would be appropriate in almost all cases of embezzlement, so that the guideline sentence would in fact rarely be imposed which result would be inconsistent with the concept of sentencing guidelines.94
9.71
The corollary to this provision against undermining the guidelines is that common or typical aspects of a crime do not justify departure either this rule was expressed in State v Lerma, when it was held that emotional hardship and physical trauma on the victim were sufficiently common factors of all sexual batteries to exclude them as grounds of a sentence departure.95 This is a useful and intelligent principle, and should be more widely adopted.
9.72
Departures based on disparate regional perceptions of the severity of a crime, or on the sentencing judge's dissatisfaction with the guidelines are also excluded.
9.73
It is clear thus, that Florida's simple, abuse of discretion, standard of review is qualified by numerous other, entirely laudable limitations on the judicial discretion. The result has been that departure sentences have been rejected in myriad instances,96 despite the apparently deferential standard of review.
9.74
Unfortunately, this may be a result, in the view of the Florida Commission, of an undue concentration by sentencing judges on finding means of departure from the guidelines.97 In fact, this process has been aided by the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=230 |
State legislature the decision of the Florida Supreme Court to review the extent of departures from guidelines was reversed in a statute of 1986.98 In that respect, the hands of the Florida appellate courts have been tied more tightly than the courts of Washington tied their own.
9.75
The reaction to indeterminate sentencing practice in California was rather different from that in Minnesota and the other states discussed above. On their face, the reforms adopted have much in common with the Minnesota model, but there are also considerable points of divergence, and the California scheme is ultimately the weaker of the two.
9.76
In 1976, the Uniform Determinate Sentencing Bill was enacted in California. It shares with the cases already discussed a commitment to consistency in sentencing, which objective is to be achieved in accordance with a policy of just deserts. Section 1170a of the Amended Penal Code states that the purpose of imprisonment for crime is punishment, and that this is best served by terms proportionate to the seriousness of the offence with provision for uniformity in sentence of offenders and mandatory prison sentences for a number of offenders committing the same crime under similar circumstances.
9.77
Mandatory life prison sentences are retained for first and second degree murder, and for kidnapping for ransom. In all other cases, the judge has a discretion as to whether imprisonment or a community sanction is more appropriate. In this respect, the determinate sentencing law (DSL) differs markedly from the Minnesota matrix, with its express policy commitment to prison in the case of certain offences, and not in the case of others. In fact, the DSL gives no guidance at all on the exercise of this in/out discretion, other than the negative guidance provided by the increased statutory prescription of mandatory sentences of imprisonment.99 This must be accounted a major flaw of omission in the system's design, probably due to the fact that it was introduced as part of an integrated overhaul of the whole sentencing system and structure.
9.78
The real area of operation of the DSL is reached when the prison term is considered by the judge (he or she having decided upon imprisonment or the decision having been made for him or her by a mandatory imprisonment requirement). The law lays down three possible prison terms for each felony, the higher and lower making provision for aggravation and mitigation respectively. The term is decided on the basis of only one of the axes on a Minnesota style grid, as it were that of offence gravity. Only afterwards does criminal history enter the judge's calculations, along with other considerations, when he or she must decide whether or not to enhance the term. Enhancements of specified durations may be added if the offender has previous convictions, used or carried a firearm, caused injury, or stole more than a certain amount of money, e.g. two
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=231 |
years could be added for each violent offence previously committed. In all cases, the factual basis of, and reasons for, the sentence must be set out.
9.79
It should be noted that the Californian innovation involves a curious mix of judicial discretion and judicial constraint there is considerable freedom where there exists a choice between imprisonment or an alternative sanction, and on the question of enhancement, while at the intermediate stage, when the basic term is established, the sentencing judge's range of choice is very limited. For example, the sentence for burglary, previously 715 years indeterminate (i.e. with release being determined by the Adult Authority), became 6 months, 2 years or 3 years.100 This degree of restraint becomes fairly meaningless with discretionary enhancement yet a rather brutal form of consistency has been achieved by making heavy enhancements mandatory in many cases, while at the same time the base prison terms in the DSL have also been subject to continuous upward amendment. Thus, the greatest achievement of the new scheme, the massive reduction in the upper terms of imprisonment, as in the example of burglary above, has been under assault from two directions from within, by the express increase of base terms, and by the snowball effect of enhancement. The scale of this assault is frightening. From 1st January, 1980, five years were added to the base term for each prior conviction for sex offences and violent offences. In 1982, Proposition 8 of the new Victims' Bill of Rights prescribed mandatory enhancement of 10 years for each prior prison term served for violent sex offences, and that prison be the mandatory sentence for first-degree burglary (which covers all burglaries of residential property). In 1980, nine specific sex offences became subject to mandatory sentences and larger enhancements.101
9.80
The result has been a doubling of the imprisonment rate for felons.102 Furthermore, it is said the DSL institutionalises double jeopardy by the system of enhancements for prior prison terms which effectively punishes the offender again for the same offence.103 This is a symptom of the failure of the designers of the DSL to address the issue of commensurability. While the Californian scheme may achieve consistency between similarly circumstanced and culpable offenders, it has allowed penalties to diverge from the offences committed, because of the huge influence of penalty enhancements. As Allen remarks, the Californian sentencing system is a counterfeit just deserts model,104 because while disparities may have been reduced, many of the punishments imposed are grossly unfair in themselves, being quite incommensurable with the seriousness of the crimes committed.
9.81
Davis submits that the DSL has in fact departed from its stated
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=232 |
objective: developments in California have less to do with 'just deserts' and more to do with incapacitation. The original philosophy of the DSL owed much to the retributive view of punishment; the offender deserves to suffer for his wrongdoing, he pays the price and then re-enters society with a clean state. Incapacitation, on the other hand, reflects the view that criminals should be locked away until they are no longer a danger to society.105
9.82
As must be clear from that description, incapacitation is a concept more easily associated with indeterminate sentencing than with the stated aspirations of the DSL one might see it is a negative expression of rehabilitative theory.
9.83
It can be concluded that the Californian determinate sentencing scheme is highly unsatisfactory. It remains to be asked whether its faults are attributable in the main to poor design, or whether the notion of determinate sentencing is inherently flawed. Allen does suggest that the problems of escalating sentence levels encountered in California might not have arisen if oversight of the sentencing system had been entrusted to an independent sentencing commission rather than to a legislature which is so susceptible to short-term political pressures.106
9.84
It is submitted that if the initial discretion on imprisonment were subject to some guidance; the role of criminal history as a sentence enhancing factor were reduced; determinate community sentences were also prescribed; and general penalty levels lowered by an independent sentencing commission (or by a more responsible legislature), the DSL might be a more appealing piece of legislation. Yet in that case, it would be difficult not to compare it to a matrix guidelines system (perhaps one better designed than in Minnesota); and not to find it wanting, by the comparison, as a means of achieving the goals substantially shared by both schemes. Ultimately, the justice envisaged by determinate sentencing is procrustean; the grid system's guidelines can be simpler, clearer, and more just in their combination of criminal record and offence gravity in assessing the culpability, or desert, of the offender; while they provide a better structured, and easily reviewable, discretion to judges who wish to depart from them.107We provisionally recommend that a determinate sentencing law not be adopted as a means of implementing sentencing policy in this jurisdiction.
9.85
The work of the Canadian Sentencing Commission, which reported in 1987,108 is part of a general process of reconsideration and reform of the criminal law begun in that country in 1979. The process has continued, in respect of sentencing, since the publication of the Commission's Report and a
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=233 |
number of other documents have since been published in this area.109
9.86
As has already been remarked above, the Commission advocated as a rationale for the sentencing system the principle of proportionality, but stressed the accountability rather than the punishment of the offender. This was to be the guiding motivation for a package of interdependent reforms. One development ostensibly inspired by the just deserts principle was the passing of legislation in 1988 allowing courts to consider victim impact statements in determining the appropriate sentence to be imposed on an offender.110 However, most of the package remains to be implemented. Among its recommendations are:
|
9.87
The Standing Committee on Justice (the Daubney Committee) reported subsequently and dissented from some of these proposals.114 In particular, it recommended the retention of parole. A public opinion poll conducted for the Department of Justice suggested its retention, with 80% in its favour.115 The Canadian Ministry of Justice advocated a Sentencing and Parole Commission, to provide the mechanism for the formulation of guidelines and of conditional release strategies within a consistent policy framework.116
9.88
With respect to guidelines, the Daubney Committee proposed that these
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=234 |
be advisory only.117
9.89
It is apparent, therefore, that the proposals of the Canadian Sentencing Commission were received with less than unanimous approval. Nonetheless, their approach to the drafting of sentencing guidelines contains some new ideas which are worthy of consideration.
9.90
The Law Reform Commission of Canada, in its submission to the Sentencing Commission, proposed the use of benchmarks:
A benchmark sentence or disposition indicates the norm in the usual case. It would be an indication of the usual disposition in the normal case. Because individual circumstances vary, it should be possible for a court to depart from the benchmark, but in order to maintain a rough equality among cases of roughly equal seriousness such departure should be limited to a 10% or 15% variation either way depending on aggravating or mitigating circumstances. Exceptional cases, all would agree, cannot be dealt with by general rules or benchmarks. Accordingly, for a limited number of cases where the circumstances are clearly compelling for a departure which is greater than 15% from the benchmark, the court should be able to impose a sentence, according to the principles stated, giving reasons, and subject to appeal by either Crown or defence counsel.118 |
9.91
Among the objections of the Sentencing Commission were that the classes of offences for which benchmarks would be formulated were very broad, and included offences for which actual sentencing practice was very different. Benchmarks would thus force uniformity on a diversity of practices. In general, it was considered that the LRCC benchmark proposal was much influenced by the Minnesota model. Being based on a much simpler structure it would be even cruder in effect.119
9.92
Neither was a US-style two-dimensional guideline matrix recommended. It was decisively rejected by judges, and was therefore deemed to be unworkable.120
9.93
The proposed guidelines would inform the judge whether the presumptive sentence would involve a community (ie non-custodial sanction) or would include a term of imprisonment. Offences would be assigned one of four presumptions:
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=235 |
IN (i.e. custody);
OUT (i.e. community sanction);
QI (qualified in i.e. custody unless it is a minor instance of the offence and the offender has no relevant criminal record); and
Q0 (qualified out i.e. community sanction unless it is a serious instance of the offence and the offender has a relevant criminal record).121
9.94
The Commission provides the following example of the eight possible outcomes of applying the presumptive qualified out disposition to theft over Can$1,000. Four comply with the presumption, four depart:
Compliance Outcomes
|
9.95
The more complex approach to the decisions whether or not to incarcerate an offender was deemed to avoid the in\out rigidity of the Minnesota system,123 and also Minnesota's perceived exclusion of an effective policy role for appellate courts.124
9.96
For those cases resulting in custody, a presumptive range is provided. It is worthwhile looking at the guideline prototype for an offence like theft over Can$1,000, illustrated in Table H.125
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=237 |
TABLE H
SAMPLE CANADIAN GUIDELINE PROTOTYPE
I. Group of Offences: |
|
Theft Over $1000 |
|
|
s283\294(a), Criminal Code |
|
|
Possession of Property obtained by Crime Over $1000 |
|
|
s312\313(a), Criminal Code |
|
|
False Pretence Leading to Theft Over $1000 |
|
|
s319\320(2)(a), Criminal Code |
|
|
Fraud Over $1000 or Pertaining to a Testamentary Instrument |
|
|
s338(1)(a), Criminal Code |
II. Maximum |
6 Years |
|
III. Presumptive Disposition |
Qualified Presumption of Non-Custody (QO) (ie. out unless it is a serious instance of the offence and the offender has a relevant criminal record). |
|
IV. Guidelines |
Range*: 12 Years |
ADVISORY INFORMATION
V. Current Practice:
(These data reflect sentencing under the current system which includes full release on parole as early as one-third and remission based release after an inmate has served two-thirds of sentence. To get an idea of time actually served by inmates, these sentences must be discounted to a greater degree than would the ranges proposed by the Commission).
1. Theft: Similar data are provided in respect of the other offences in this group
Percentiles (m = months, y = years)
Source |
25th |
50th (Median)* |
75th |
90th** |
Correctional Sentences Project (s283,294) |
1m |
3m |
5m |
1y |
Sentencing Commission (a294(a)) |
4m |
18m |
|
|
|
VI. Case Law:
No clear principles emerged which were relevant to the entire group of offences.
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=238 |
9.97
The statistical scheme adopted in order to illustrate current practice is not very helpful, as it does not indicate the differing circumstances in which different sentences were handed down. By describing outcomes but not inputs, it is of little use to the judge who has to decide where to locate the case before him or her on the scale of seriousness.126
9.98
This weakness is surprising, as it is at variance with the Commission's own analysis of the need for sentencing information, which would view the data provided as being more relevant to the formulation of guidelines than to their application:
The kind of information needed to determine policy broad numerical figures on major trends is to be sharply contrasted with the type of information which is relevant to the sentencing judge in solving particular cases, and, particularly, in reviewing cases. Whereas the latter must be detailed and sensitive to differences between cases, the former is general and aims at identifying the common features of a vast number of cases.127 |
9.99
The proposed guidelines also contain a non-exhaustive list of aggravating and mitigating circumstances which could be used to determine the sentence level within the presumptive range, where custody is involved, or to provide valid grounds for departing from the guidelines.128 Judges would be required to give reasons for any departures. Thus, a considerable degree of judicial discretion is maintained, but parameters for effective appellate review on foot of defence or Crown appeals are established. It was recommended that guidelines also be formulated in respect of community sanctions.129
9.100
At least one commentator, Allen, has praised the Canadian Report as well-reasoned however, his remark that the guidelines would benefit from being part of a package of reforms resulting from a complete overhaul of the whole sentencing system may not hold true, in the light of the reservations of other influential Canadian bodies about some of the package's contents. Allen is also impressed by the fact that the guidelines do not appear to be susceptible to tabulation, and that the offender's past convictions would not be determinative of his sentence in the way they are e.g. in Minnesota, but rather are a factor to be taken into account in deciding whether to depart from the presumptive sentence.130
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=239 |
9.101
Prior to the introduction of the US Federal Guidelines in the 1980's, federal judges' discretion in sentencing seemed almost infinite, as long as the sentence imposed did not exceed broad statutory limits.131
9.102
In the seminal case of Williams v New York,132 the Supreme Court expressly disapproved of rigid and mechanical concepts in sentencing that unnecessarily restricted judicial exercise of discretion; in United States v Tucker, it was noted that the sentencing judge may appropriately conduct an inquiry broad in scope, largely unlimited either as to the kind of information he may consider, or the source from which it may come.133
9.103
The reaction to this state of affairs was led by Marvin Frankel, a former Federal District Judge. Judge Frankel was an early advocate of sentencing commissions, composed of judges, lawyers, criminologists and penologists, which could determine which substantive considerations should enter into the sentencing determination, and develop procedural rules for the implementation of those considerations. In his landmark work of 1973, Criminal Sentences: Law Without Order, he declared:
Those of us whose profession is the law must not choose any longer to tolerate a regime of unreasoned, unconsidered caprice for exercising the most awful power of organised society, the power to take liberty and ... life by process of what purports to be law.134 |
9.104
Frankel was particularly critical of the absence of any requirement for judges to give reasons for their sentences, and of their reluctance to do so for fear of reversal upon appeal. That the criticisms of Frankel and others were well-founded has been borne out by research conducted by the Federal Sentencing Commission, established as a result of the change in attitudes to sentencing which he helped to initiate. Considerable disparities were found in sentencing practice in various areas:
The region in which the defendant is convicted is likely to change the length of time served from approximately six months more if one is sentenced in the South to twelve months less if one is sentenced in Central California .... [F]emale bank robbers are likely to serve six months less than their similarly situated male counterparts ... [and] black [bank robbery] defendants convicted ... in the South are likely to actually serve approximately thirteen months longer than similarly situated bank robbers convicted ... in other regions.135 |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=240 |
9.105
Other statistical studies showed, for example, that in the Second Circuit, punishments for identical actual cases could range from three years to twenty years imprisonment.136
9.106
Senator Edward Kennedy introduced an early sentencing guidelines bill in the Congress in 1975,137 but a consensus did not emerge on the need for such measures until, almost a decade later, Congress took a particular interest in the guidelines established by the United States Parole Commission in the 1970's. As with the judiciary, the Parole Commissioners had been reluctant to move beyond decision-making on an individual basis their policy was to treat each case on its merits. The guidelines advocated the determination of each prisoner's release date mainly upon two dimensions (thus leading to the original matrix), namely, the seriousness of the instant crime, and the probability of recidivism, calculated from a salient factor score based on nine personal characteristics whose success at predicting post-parole conduct was statistically validated.138 Any departure from the policy matrix was to be explained, and every six months a review of such departures was made by the board sitting in banc.139
9.107
Leslie Wilkins, one of the initiators of the Parole Guidelines matrix, has pointed out that it was designed as a management or policy tool, but gradually, as it moved from parole to the courts, became a legal instrument involving legislatures. The Parole Board sought to protect itself and its independence from accusations of disparity in its decision-making by illustrating, through the adoption of the guidelines, that its determinations were principled and in accord with an explicit policy.140 It was hoped that the judiciary would defend collectively its independence from legislative (political) intervention in similar fashion; but the judges seemed to prefer to defend the right of each individual judge to independence.141 9.108 Instead, presumptive sentencing guidelines tended in most states to be a political innovation (though as we have seen, they could not be assured of success without judicial support). This was also the case in respect of the Federal Guidelines: although the Sentencing Commission was established, by the Sentencing Reform Act 1984142 as an independent commission in the judicial branch of government, to avoid separation of powers difficulties, the ultimate responsibility for its establishment was political.
9.109
The Commission comprised seven members (including three federal judges) appointed by the President, confirmed by the Senate and instructed to
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=241 |
write, by April 1987, sentencing guidelines which would automatically take effect 6 months later unless Congress passed another law to the contrary.143
9.110
The authority granted to the Commission to carry out its mandate was thus very considerable. That mandate was a complex one, which Ogletree summarises in detail as follows:
The Act requires courts to impose sentences which reflect the seriousness of the offencepromote respect for the lawprovide just punishment for the offenceafford adequate deterrence to criminal conductprotect the public from further crimes of the defendant and provide the defendant with needed educational or vocational training, medical care, or other correctional treatment in the most effective manner. To implement these goals, Congress gave the Sentencing Commission the responsibility to determine under what circumstances an individual would be subject to imprisonment, a term of probation, a fine, or some combination of these sanctions.144 Moreover, Congress created a grading scheme to be employed by the Commission to rank each offence according to its seriousness. Although the Sentencing Commission was expected to draft guidelines and develop policy statements that would eliminate disparities, it was also expected to develop policy statements that would leave federal judges with sufficient flexibility to impose individualised sentences warranted by mitigating or aggravating factors not taken into consideration in the general sentencing guidelines. Congress mandated that the Commission take numerous factors and circumstances into account, to the extent that they are relevant, in establishing categories of offences. The factors included the grade and nature of the offence, the mitigating and aggravating circumstances, the public concern generated by the offence, the deterrent effect a sentence might have on others, and the incidence of the particular offence in the community and in the nation. Congress authorised the Commission to consider, in establishing the categories of defendants, the relevance of an offender's age, education, vocational skills, mental and emotional condition, physical condition (including drug dependence), previous employment record, family and community ties, role in the offence, criminal history, and dependence on criminal activity for a livelihood. Additionally, the Commission was expected to develop means of measuring the effectiveness of sentencing, penal, and correctional practices in fulfilling the purposes of sentencing articulated by Congress in the federal sentencing statutes. Finally, the Sentencing Commission was given the authority to |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=242 |
promulgate guidelines to determine whether multiple sentences should be ordered to run concurrently or consecutively and to develop policy statements regarding the application of the guidelines or any other aspect of sentencing or sentence implementation that in the view of the Commission would further the purposes set forth in the sentencing statutes. The Commission was also authorised to establish a sentencing range for each category of offence involving each category of defendant,145 as long as, in cases involving imprisonment, the maximum of the range did not exceed the minimum of the range by more than the greater of twenty-five percent of the sentence or six months. The Commission was also required to insure that its guidelines and policy statements were entirely neutral as to the race, sex, national origin, creed, and socio-economic status of offenders.146 |
9.111
Judges might depart from the Guideline range, but only upon giving reasons, and the imposed sentence would be subject to appellate review for reasonableness.147
9.112
The circumstances of the Guidelines compilation were less than ideal. No prosecutor, judge or defence attorney was appointed with extensive experience in federal sentencing practices the absence of a defence lawyer was thought to be especially lamentable. More importantly, the timetable set by Congress for the enactment of the guidelines was arbitrary and unrealistic, and an extension was refused when requested.148 The federal task was also more difficult than that of state commissions like those of Minnesota and Washington for two substantive reasons. First, the Federal Criminal Code has many more crimes than most State codes: against Minnesota's 251 and Washington's 108 statutory crimes, the Federal Commission had to deal with 688 statutes, including such complex criminal laws as the Racketeer Influenced and Corrupt Organisations Act.149 Secondly, the political homogeneity in individual states may have made it easier to achieve consensus. While there was near unanimous nationwide support for the concept of federal guidelines, serious political differences emerged once the Commission reduced that concept to a detailed reality.150
9.113
The Commission began its task by conducting public hearings, and by establishing a research programme to consider summary reports on some 100,000 federal cases, and detailed reports on some 10,000.
9.114
It then tested its guidelines against the actual sentences imposed.151 Furthermore, the guidelines' impact on the federal prison population and on other components of the federal criminal justice system was assessed. In
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=243 |
September 1986, after extensive consultations with federal agencies, public meetings, etc, detailed preliminary draft guidelines were published.152
9.115
These were widely criticised as inflexible, unduly harsh and difficult to administer. Their application to real cases was found in some studies to lead to disparities of even greater magnitude than had previously existed, as well as to serious computation errors for example, in a mock sentencing exercise in the Eastern District of Pennsylvania.153
9.116
A revised draft was submitted for public review in January 1987, after the consideration of thousands of pages of submissions and the elimination of some flaws. Despite further criticism,154 only two days of public hearings were held to solicit comments; the guidelines were put before Congress without any subsequent test or trial a month afterwards.155
9.117
They automatically became federal law on November 1, 1987, but have since been subjected to several substantial amendments.156
9.118
The guidelines are largely descriptive of prior sentencing practice, though not entirely so this point will be returned to. They feature a grid or matrix which is a more complex version of the Minnesota model. This is the Sentencing Table, which has 43 offence levels on one axis, and 6 criminal history categories on the other. The determination of both of these scores is more refined (and complicated) than in most of the State systems already described.
9.119
The offence level is calculated by determining the base level of the particular criminal offence, and by adjusting this level usually upwards in accordance with a host of offence characteristics identified by the guidelines. Some of these are summarised by Allen as follows:
For example, the amount of money involved in theft or robbery or the use of a weapon can lead to an increase in the base level. Further increases may be made because of the vulnerability of the victim, the offender's organisational role in the offence, the offender's abuse of a position of trust or the offender's wilful obstruction of the administration of justice during the investigation or prosecution of the offence. The base level may also be adjusted downwards where the offender's role in the offence was minimal, or where he has demonstrated a recognition and affirmative acceptance of personal responsibility for the offence by, for example, voluntary payment of restitution or voluntary admission to |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=244 |
the authorities of involvement in the offence (but not for a 'guilty' plea), or voluntary surrender to the authorities.157 |
9.120
For the offender's criminal history, points are not simply added according to the number of previous convictions, as in Minnesota, but vary on the basis of their seriousness as determined by the length of any prison terms already served.158
9.121
Certain prior sentences are not counted or are counted only under certain conditions.159 The court may depart from the criminal history score if it appears significantly to under-represent or over-represent the seriousness of the defendant's criminal history or the likelihood that he or she will commit further crimes. In addition, if the offender is a career offender, his or her criminal history category is prescribed as category VI and the offence level is augmented to ensure that career offenders receive a sentence of imprisonment at or near the maximum term authorised.160 If the defendant committed the offence as part of a pattern of criminal conduct from which he or she derived a substantial portion of his or her income, his or her offence level must be set at least at 13 and such an offender is not eligible for probation.161
9.122
The meeting point of the two scores on the Sentencing Table gives the appropriate range of sentences. As has already been adverted to, the guidelines deal not only with imprisonment but also with probation, community service, supervised release, fines and restitution.162
9.123
Breyer offers the following useful illustration of the guidelines' operation:
Imagine the case of a bank robber, with one serious prior conviction (i.e. a sentence of imprisonment exceeding thirteen months), who robs a bank of $40,000, while pointing a gun at the teller. The sentencing judge (and probation officer) would proceed through the following steps.163
.... If the Commission has done its job as it hopes, the resulting term of confinement about four to five years should strike most observers as about the typical time such an offender would have served prior to the Guidelines.175 |
9.124
Both the defendant and the government may appeal final sentences imposed in violation of (1) the law, (2) the sentence specified in a plea agreement,176 or (3) as a result of an incorrect application of the guidelines.
9.125
There are a number of further new or refined features of the Federal Guidelines which bear discussion. These will arise in the treatment which follows of the voluminous debate which has accompanied their introduction. The debate sheds considerable light on the problems faced in designing a guidelines system.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=246 |
9.126
The main criticism of the guidelines upon their introduction was their failure to specify the objects of sentencing. Professor Paul Robinson, a member of the Commission who dissented from the final draft, strongly criticised the adopted guidelines for failing to articulate a clear purpose:
What's the standard by which one can judge during the field study whether sentences are being applied disproportionately? Because the commission has no stated sentencing policy, one has no way of knowing whether a sentence fulfils the goals of the commission or not. An example of this would be in sentencing a drug addict. One judge might give a long prison term as a deterrent. Another judge, more inclined to rehabilitation, might give probation conditioned on treatment. Both are rational sentences that have some policy behind them. They are different policies, which explains why we have so much disparity in the system today. But what this commission is supposed to do is to decide, even in hard cases like that, what policy ought to be pursued. That's the way that greater consistency in sentencing under the Act is supposed to be brought about. This requires research into which one of these sentences, for example, is going to reduce crime most in the future. Instead, by its mathematical averaging, the commission has come up with irrational sentences.177 |
9.127
Ogletree endorses this view. He cites the Senate Report on the issue as suggesting that the language proposed by Congress requires the judge to consider the four purposes of sentencing rehabilitation, punishment, incapacitation and restitution before imposing a particular sentence.178 He submits that federal judges need efficient guidance in choosing between the various purposes available to justify a sentence imposed on a particular defendant, and that the guidelines ultimately submitted for congressional approval failed to provide such guidance.179 This is an unusual stance, and seems to be shared by Robinson. While both reject bastardised sentences,180 based on mathematical averaging of past sentencing practice (which will be discussed immediately below), their alternative is not the choice of a single philosophy as the guiding force of the guidelines. They would, rather, preserve all the possible objects, under the broader rubric of crime control. In each case, whichever object would tend to reduce crime most in future would operate. Thus, empirical
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=247 |
research might suggest that incapacitation operated best on violent criminals, rehabilitation on sexual offenders, and retribution on those guilty of crimes relating to property. Guidelines would thus be formulated in each sphere based on the most applicable philosophy.181
9.128
It is submitted that this, if it is a correct assessment of their position, is unsustainable. It is certainly inconsistent with the model of sentencing policy proposed in this paper. Quite apart from the fact that the present popularity of at least one of the possible objects of sentencing just punishment is founded on its rejection of utilitarian goals like crime control, such a selective approach must be a licence for disparity. Even if one does not take their statements literally (that a sentencing policy must be chosen in each particular case), and presumes them to intend only that different offence types would be governed by different policies, there would be, in such a scheme, huge disparities in sentencing as between offence-types. Robinson is adamant that offences be ranked in order of seriousness,182 yet such a ranking would point up disparities if crimes of violence and against property, adjudged to be of equal severity, were sentenced on different grounds: the violent offender might be incapacitated for a long period while the property offender might be sentenced to a short period of rehabilitative community service. What Robinson is really advocating is the adoption of a general object of prevention of recidivism based on predictive factors. But it was despair of the disparities produced by such a philosophy in individualised sentencing which first motivated the guidelines movement there is no evidence that its application on an offence basis (based on an assessment of the typical offender in each offence category), while possibly effective in pursuit of its stated goal of crime control, would reduce the perceived problems of disparity, unfairness and disproportion in sentencing. Robinson's failure to appreciate the real philosophical (and effective) differences between sentencing objects is illustrated by his approach to the ranking of offences by seriousness (in itself a laudable aim). He stated that [d]eterrence and just punishment both call for more serious offences to be sanctioned more seriously, thus demanding systematic offence ranking.183Robinson does not appear to realise that offence severity rankings in pursuit of just punishment objectives would probably differ markedly from those formulated as part of a 'deterrence' system. In the former case, seriousness should be gauged from the harm done or contemplated and the moral culpability of the offender who inflicted such harm; in the latter, if the system were realistic and empirically based, the key indicator of seriousness would be the recidivism rate of typical offenders of that type. For example, the recidivism rate (and thus, the need for adequate deterrence) might be low for an offence, like manslaughter, which is nonetheless one of considerable gravity in point of harm, and of desert and moral guilt.184
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=248 |
9.129
The weaknesses of Robinson's alternative proposals do not, however, excuse the guidelines from his attacks automatically. The eclectic approach of the Commission, purporting to combine a number of policies in a single set of rigid presumptive guidelines, has been comprehensively criticised elsewhere in this paper.185
9.130
This is not to say that empirical study of sentencing practice, and the adoption of a descriptive approach to the introduction of some of its elements into guidelines, is in all circumstances ill-advised. The work of the Commission in examining the common factors in the decision of some 100,000 cases could be very valuable if properly employed. Essentially, the rationale for each such decisive factor must be identified. Where this corresponds to the sentencing theory which has been chosen for the decision on quantum of punishment under the guidelines (e.g. just deserts), the factor can be employed to help in the formulation of offence-seriousness rankings, or as an aggravating or mitigating factor within the guidelines. This can help combat the problem identified by Breyer of such decisions being made, unguided, by Commission members. Similarly, factors attributable to other sentencing philosophies such as rehabilitation and incapacitation can be introduced as specified key factors in the decision on the choice of penalty. In response to Robinson's allegations of their mimicking the mathematical averages of past sentences, his colleagues stressed both the sophistication of the multivariate statistical techniques employed, and the relative subtlety of the results obtained186:
By using advanced statistical techniques, we were able to estimate the average time served for offender/offence combinations. To illustrate, the average time served was estimated for typically occurring variations of burglary offences, including the value of the property taken, the degree of planning, the possession of a weapon, and whether the case was adjudicated through a plea of guilty or by a trial. The results of these analyses were then used as a starting point for the guidelines.187 |
9.131
The results of such analyses were not universally followed:
We reviewed the results of these analyses to determine whether the structure and degree of significance were logical and reasonable, and made changes where they were not.188 |
9.132
As the Supplementary Report makes clear, robbery provides a notable example. Research showed that the average sentences for robbery of an individual were considerably lower than those for the much more common (in the federal system) offence of bank robbery, even adjusting for other relevant factors.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=249 |
Because it did not find a persuasive rationale for this, the Commission made little distinction between such offences.189
9.133
Thus, a quasi-prescriptive, evolutionary mechanism was established alongside the guidelines' more descriptive features. This is in line with the Commission majority's stated belief that our proposed changes should evolve from, not represent a sharp break with, existing practice.190 That is a belief which the authors of this study endorse (not least because of the necessity of achieving judicial support for any proposed reforms). That such practice should be informed by coherent policy statements is, however, imperative.
9.134
The sentencing factors which emerged from the Commission's studies are the subject of continuing discussion in particular, the important role granted to criminal history as the key offender characteristic is open to criticism. The debate on this point, including that on the specific features of the US Guidelines' provisions, is rehearsed elsewhere suffice to note here that the Federal approach is quite sophisticated, but the weight attributed by it to criminal history is, as in most guideline grid systems, probably excessive.
9.135
The factors to be taken into account, are also a focus of debate on levels of detail in guidelines. Robinson commences his argument on this point by citing the instruction to the Federal Commission that the guidelines take account of every important factor relevant to sentencing, so that departures would be rare, arising only where there was an unusual factor that was not adequately taken into consideration by the Commission at the time of drafting.191Robinson submits that it is the most basic function of any rational sentencing system to provide appropriately different sentences for cases that are meaningfully different: there must be no free harms, and significant mitigatory factors should be reflected in reduced sentences. He accused the Commission of failing to make provision for much relevant conduct of the offender, the judge being permitted to take into account under the guidelines only such factors as are listed as applicable to a particular offence:192
For example, because the burglary guideline does not specifically aggravate the guideline sentence where the offender causes physical injury, the burglar who beats a homeowner will be treated the same as the burglar who does not. That is, the beating of the homeowner is free in burglary, as it is in a host of other offences.193 |
9.136
The culpability of an offender's state of mind, i.e. whether he was intentional, reckless or negligent, is also commonly ignored:
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=250 |
The statutory definition of an offence generally requires a minimum level of culpability recklessness (or negligence), for example and the guidelines generally assume this level of culpability. Because the guidelines do not adjust for a higher level of culpability, the court must depart from the guidelines to account for an offender who intentionally commits the offence. Thus, the offender who intentionally burns a lumber-producing forest is treated the same as the camper who negligently fails to extinguish his campfire, unless the court departs.194 |
9.137
As well as such general factors, the guidelines fail to consider scores of more specific features of offences that are relevant and commonplace, and many of which were recognised by Congress in the definition of the offence, e.g. risking the victim's death in kidnapping, child abuse or exploitation in pornography, the perpetration of acts of perversion or the causing of extreme psychological injury in rape.195
9.138
Ogletree echoes Robinson's grievance in respect of offender (as opposed to offence) characteristics. Of the many factors suggested by Congress including the defendant's age, education, vocational skills, mental and emotional condition, physical condition or drug dependence, previous employment record, family responsibilities and community ties the Commission concluded that only his or her criminal history, dependence on criminal activity for a livelihood, and acceptance of responsibility for his or her wrongdoing were relevant. This disappoints Ogletree: A system that fails to consider the offender's personal characteristics places too great an emphasis on the harm caused by the offender's act and too little emphasis on circumstances which would serve to mitigate the punishment.196
9.139
It is Robinson's contention that skeletal non-comprehensive, guidelines maintain disparity, by creating the opportunity (indeed, the need) to depart from the guidelines in cases with features not provided for in the guidelines.197 That such departures are invited (or directed) for the predictable and the commonplace,198 without an articulated policy to guide the judge and with no legal limit to a departure sentence other than the statutory maximum, is suggested to be inimical to the purging of present anomalies in sentencing practice.199 The guidelines, it is Robinson's contention, are not only skeletal, but fatally vague as well. For example, for the offences for which no guidelines were formulated, judges are directed to apply the most analogous guideline; and if no sufficiently analogous guideline exists, the court may impose any sentence that is reasonable.200
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=251 |
9.140
Without an express policy to influence such decisions, such discretion is fatal: Each instance creates the opportunity for different judges to supply their own criteria, definitions and interpretations of key provisions, and thus generate different sentences for similar cases.201 Robinson continues that for some offences, the conditions for departure are so numerous and broad that one is hard-pressed to think of a case that would not fall under at least one of the conditions described in the commentary. He cites the guideline on the mishandling of hazardous or toxic substances or pesticides (s2Q1.2), which includes the following commentary, as an instance of the licence which is still given the judge in sentencing under the federal system:
Because of the wide range of potential conduct arising out of the handling of different quantities of materials with widely differing propensities, a departure either upward or downward may be warranted. Depending upon the resultant harm from the emission, release or discharge, the quality and nature of the substance or pollutant, the duration of the offence and the risk associated with the violation, a departure of up to two levels in either direction from the offence levels prescribed in these offence characteristics may be appropriate.202 |
9.141
The result is that Robinson views the guidelines as neither comprehensive nor binding.203 Furthermore, as well as maintaining disparity (while the one admittedly inadequate remedial body, the Parole Board, has been abolished), this lack of guideline comprehensiveness makes effective appellate review almost impossible,204 and prompts judicial development of the guidelines to provide the substance and direction that they lack. Robinson opposes this both because judges are rarely eager to reduce their own discretion,205 and also because such development must of necessity be reactive, unsystematic, uncoordinated and on a case-by-case basis,206 and excludes the possibility of guiding policy decisions by empirical studies and analysis.
9.142
The Commission has been extremely vocal in its defence of the Guidelines against such criticisms. On the issue of the factors relevant to sentencing, it refers to the tension between the mandates of uniformity (to treat like cases alike) and proportionality (to treat different cases differently). It rejects having only a few, easily-administered categories of crime, but suggests that introducing too great a level of detail would also be impractical:
At the same time, a sentencing system tailored to fit every conceivable wrinkle of each case can become unworkable and seriously compromise |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=252 |
the certainty of punishment and its deterrent effect. A bank robber with (or without) a gun, which the robber kept hidden (or brandished), might have frightened (or merely warned), injured seriously (or less seriously) or tied up (or simply pushed) a guard, a teller or a customer, at night (or at noon), for a bad (or arguably less bad) motive, in an effort to obtain money for other crimes (or for other purposes), in the company of a few (or many) other robbers, for the first (or fourth) time that day, while sober (or under the influence of drugs or alcohol), and so forth.207 |
9.143
Quite apart from the multiplicity of combinations and permutations of factors which might arise, many are said to be context specific, i.e. the infliction of injury may be of varying importance depending on the offence under consideration the risk involved varies and also, the effect of multiple harms need not be simply additive.208
9.144
Even more telling is the suggestion that complexity and what Robinson calls comprehensiveness may be counter-productive to the guidelines' aim of eliminating sentencing discrepancies:
The greater the number of decisions required and the greater their complexity, the greater the risk that different judges will apply the guidelines differently to situations that, in fact, are similar, thereby reintroducing the very disparity that the guidelines were designed to eliminate.209 |
9.145
On the other hand, the granting of considerable discretion in a simple broad-category scheme also is thought to introduce too great a tendency towards disparate sentencing into the system. There is thus a practical stalemate. The Commission ... had to simply balance the comparative virtues and vices of broad, simple categorisation and detailed, complex sub-categorisation, and within the constraints established by that balance, minimise the discretionary powers of the sentencing court. Any ultimate system will, to a degree, enjoy the benefits and suffer from the drawbacks of each approach.210
9.146
In respect of departure policy, the Commission defends the Guidelines as carving out a heartland, a set of typical cases embodying the conduct that each guideline describes.211 It does not limit the kinds of factor that could constitute grounds for departure in an unusual case firstly because of the difficulty of foreseeing and capturing a single set of guidelines that encompasses the vast range of human conduct potentially relevant to a sentencing decision and secondly, because despite the courts' legal freedom to depart from the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=253 |
guidelines, they will not do so very often this is due to the considerable efforts taken to make the guidelines reflect the most significant factors in current sentencing practice.212
9.147
The Commission in its Supplementary Report points out that the offence level numbers from 1 to 43 correspond to a series of overlapping ranges that increase in width (so far as permitted) as the offence level increases. The levels overlap so as to limit the significance of small changes in a sentencing factor and to limit the importance of disputed sentencing factors. The minimum of any range is at or below the centre of the next lower range, and ranges that are two levels apart have at least one point in common.213 This system reflects the attempt to balance the competing demands of broad- and narrow-category schemes.
9.148
In respect of the alleged exclusion of important factors, the Commission remarks that in the choice of elements for inclusion in the criminal history score, regard was had for reliability in field scoring. Field scoring reliability refers to the accuracy and consistency with which decision-makers can score actual cases, and is affected by a number of factors, including the complexity of the items and the difficulty in obtaining verified information about the items.214 Clearly, reliance on sentencing factors, no matter how apparently relevant, which are not readily quantifiable must create an opening for disparity in decision-making.215 The fact-finding mechanism employed is therefore very important but it must be one which is workable and efficient as well as reliable. The Commission rejected as over-simplistic some state guideline systems, in which the sentence depends almost entirely on the literal offence of conviction. At the same time, as we have seen, it limited the number of factual issues upon which the guidelines rely, focusing on a relatively manageable number of frequently occurring factors, avoiding giving a specific weight to every nuance.216
9.149
Factual stipulations by the parties are permitted, in order to speed up the process, and avoid unnecessary disputes, but they must be fully representative of the facts of the offence. The Court is encouraged to place primary reliance on the presentence report, and the parties are required to indicate in advance of the sentencing hearing their positions on all the relevant sentencing factors areas of agreement can then be easily identified.217 The Commission did not set out procedural rules for the resolution of any remaining factual disputes but given their importance to the guidelines system, greater formality was expected.218
9.150
A related question is that imposed by the competing rationales of procedural and substantive justice, and of real offence and charge offence
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=254 |
sentencing. Sentencing merely according to the offence charge is irrational; but has as seen, adding to the severity of sentence with every harm caused can be impracticable, procedurally and otherwise. Breyer argues that here too, the Commission achieved a benign compromise. The offence charged dictates the base offence level, but it is then the real features of the offence (and of the offender's record) which influence the actual sentence arrived at.219
9.151
Robinson alleges that reliance on the specific code provisions of federal law (described by Congress itself as archaic, fragmented and overlapping), and on the inclusion of some types of behaviour (e.g. arson) under a host of different code sections reproduces this legislative fragmentation: The identical arson conduct might fall under any number of guideline sections, each with different values of seriousness and different aggravating factors. What is needed is a consolidation of offences and reliance upon generic offence categories.220 He suggests as a possible solution that the guidelines be based on the American Law Institute's Model Penal Code.
9.152
The Commission's response was that it did not have the political or institutional authority to rewrite the United States Criminal Code under the guise of writing sentencing guidelines.221 It might have added that the reliance on an offence definition other than that of the offence of which the accused was convicted might create huge difficulties.
9.153
Nonetheless, the problem pointed out by Robinson is significant, and suggests that coherent sentencing can only take place in the framework of a coherent criminal law.
9.154
In this treatment of the debate between Robinson and the Commission on sentencing factors and levels of detail in guideline systems, it is worth noting the later's response to Robinson's own proposals. His ideas that the Commission should adopt a highly detailed, mechanical guide line system that would aggravate punishments for each and every harm an offender causes and presumably lessen punishment for each and every relevant mitigating background factor,222 were the foundation of the Commission's first July 10 draft of 1986. This was widely condemned for its impracticality by many commentators, including Judge Frankel. The Commission itself drew the following conclusion:
The reason that Professor Robinson's approach drew so little support from any quarter (academics included) is that it did not provide a practical solution to the problems viewed as important by the different segments of the criminal justice community. Those particularly concerned with lessening disparity in sentencing saw in the complexity of the July 10, 1986, draft, in its need for elaborate new fact-finding, and |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=255 |
in its use of complex mathematical formulae involving multiplication of quartic roots, the likelihood that different judges would apply the system differently to similar cases, thereby aggravating the disparity problem. Those professionally concerned with crime control saw in its fact-finding demands the need for lengthy new hearings, complex arguments and appeals, all of convicted criminals would, in fact, receive appropriate special treatment of unusual cases saw in its rigid, mechanical rules and near total absence of discretion, the elimination of a court's ability to deviate when, for example, unusual facts in a specific case cried out for special treatment.223 |
9.155
In response to Robinson'svisionary ideas, the Commission adopted a more limited view of its role. Breyer stresses the compromises necessary to formulate a workable system, the restraints on resources, the imperative of evolutionary reform: The baseline must always be the status quo ante, not an idealised theoretical future.224
9.156
One of the key compromises to which Breyer refers is that concerning the intractable sentencing problem of concurrent and consecutive sentencing, of the additivity of harms (or of free harms). The Commission admitted that it found it especially difficult to develop rules for sentencing defendants convicted of multiple violations of law, each of which makes up a separate count in an indictment it is felt that while each additional harm must increase the punishment for wrongful conduct, the warranted increase need not be proportionate (if only because the extent of damage or injury caused is often fortuitous). Breyer gives the following instance:
Column A |
Column B |
1. D, in a brawl injures one person seriously |
1. D, in a brawl injures six persons |
2. D sells 100 grammes of cocaine |
2. D sells 600 grammes of cocaine |
3. D robs one bank |
3. D robs six banks |
4 D, driving recklessly, forces another car over a cliff, injuring the other driver |
4. D, driving recklessly, forces another car over a cliff, injuring the other driver and five passengers.225 |
9.157
He suggests that while most people believe that the behaviour in Column B warrants more severe punishment that that in Column A, it should not be six times worse.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=256 |
9.158
In Minnesota, concurrent sentencing is the norm in case of multiple offences, based on the most serious charge of conviction;226 Washington's guidelines call for multiple counts to be served concurrently, each count being added to the offender score,227 (though separate crimes arising from the same criminal conduct count as one crime for criminal history). But in both states, an exception is made allowing (in Minnesota) or mandating (in Washington) consecutive sentences in cases of multiple offences against the person arising from separate and distinct criminal conduct.228
9.159
Other guidelines have distinguished between types of crimes, requiring, for example, concurrent sentences for multiple counts charging property crimes but consecutive sentences for crimes against the person.229 This approach is contrary to principle however. In respect of property crimes, column B is treated no more severely than column A; in respect of crimes against the person, it may be far too severe.
9.160
The Federal Guidelines attempt to conform to principle by treating additional counts as warranting additional punishment, but in progressively diminishing amounts. Three types of circumstance are catered for.
|
9.161
As in most jurisdictions, the vast majority (some 85%) of US federal criminal convictions result from guilty pleas, so that the provision in the guidelines for sentencing in such cases are highly important. The Commission's studies indicated that sentences were an average of 3040% below those for similarly circumstanced defendants who were convicted as trial.233 Yet larger reductions could be identified in cases resulting from negotiated pleas.
9.162
The Commission considered but rejected a proposal which would have continued the sentencing judge's very considerable discretion to give a sizeable sentence reduction because of the entry of a guilty plea this might have led to unwarranted disparity and unpredictability. Nor did it wish narrowly to limit the availability of a sentence reduction for a negotiated plea this would have involved ignoring the offence of conviction in favour of real offence sentencing (which would involve by-passing the higher standard of proof required at trial), and might have led to a reduction in the number of negotiated pleas. A compromise was sought between these two antithetical positions.234 A further factor in favour of a compromise would be that while acceptance of responsibility may be deserving of reward, this should not be so great as apparently to penalise those who avail of their constitutional right to trial. That some reward by way of sentence reduction is permissible may be justified by the possibility of acquittal on some of the charges, or at least of the risk that some of the relevant factors appearing in the pre-sentence report might have been provable, had the case gone to trial.235 A pragmatic consideration is the saving of prosecutorial and judicial resources which results from a guilty plea.236
9.163
S3E1.1 of the guidelines accordingly allows a 2 level reduction of the offence level where the defendant clearly demonstrates a recognition and affirmative acceptance of personal responsibility for the offence of conviction. This reflects substantially less consideration than typically was given to those pleading guilty. Also, the reduction is not available as of right to those who plead guilty. This is left to the judge's discretion. His or her decision may be based on such factors as the timeliness of the defendant's acceptance of responsibility, his voluntary withdrawal from criminal associations, his or her voluntary payment of restitution to the victim prior to the adjudication of guilt, his or her voluntary surrender to the authorities before changes were filed, and assistance to them in recovering the evidence and proceeds of the offence.237
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=258 |
9.164
Nor is the reduction available for a guilty plea.238 The commentary on the relevant provision is as follows:
A defendant may manifest sincere contrition and take steps toward reparation and rehabilitation even if he exercises his constitutional right to a trial. This may occur when a defendant decides to go to trial to assert and preserve issues that do not relate to factual guilt, to make a constitutional challenge to a statute, or a challenge to the applicability of a statute to his conduct, or to raise evidentiary issues that may result in an acquittal.239 |
9.165
This provision is quite independent of those which regulate plea-bargaining.
9.166
We now turn to the notion of sentencing starting points and of informed judicial discretion. This is a method of influencing and regulating judicial sentencing discretion, but is nonetheless designed to leave that discretion largely intact. As developed on the continent (and especially in Finland), it entails the compilation of a data base on past sentencing practice, which identifies the most important elements in the sentencing decision and attempts to gauge how they affect the penalties actually handed down. This data base provides the starting point from which to begin the process of deciding from which part of the spectrum of penalties for an offence to choose a sentence. The tables which provide the judges' starting points may appear to be similar to guideline matrices, but they are not presumptive. They are merely aids to the conscientious judge who wishes to conform his sentencing to the practice of his colleagues and to the legislatively ordained sentencing policy. Ultimately, only this policy binds the judge, and it is permissible to depart from the starting point tables in order to comply with it. The judge's discretion is preserved, but within the context of a coherent policy framework, and starting points are designed to assist and inform him or her in the exercise of this discretion, rather than to limit or constrain it.
9.167
Though very different from presumptive guidelines in motivation and intended effect, starting point schemes can be devised in a similar manner, and can encounter similar dilemmas and problems, e.g. on levels of detail, on the quantification (objective or subjective) of material factors, on the assessment of criminal history or of multiple sentences. In continental Europe, where the notion of starting points was developed, the schemes adopted have been largely descriptive, i.e. based on present sentencing practice (such practice being informed by a reformed and coherent sentencing policy in the Finnish case). In Canada, an experimental descriptive programme run by Doob and Park is sufficiently similar in conception to be included in this treatment. The Victorian
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=259 |
Sentencing Committee has proposed what might be called a quasi-descriptive statistical scheme which could also be the nucleus of a model of sentencing characterised by informed judicial discretion, and which will be outlined and discussed below. Common law jurisdictions wary of American-style presumptive guidelines may have a lot to learn from such ideas.
9.168
Horstkutte has remarked that in Germany, there have been some attempts to formulate pathfinders these, however, have been abstract in nature and not very helpful.240 The Federal Court has indicated that the middle of the scale is not the starting point for finding the punishment in an average case. As penalty scales cover both the most and least serious cases, and as most cases are, in practical experience, closer to the least serious in terms of gravity, de facto normality assigns an average case to a place on the penalty scale closer to the minimum than the maximum.241 Attempts, however, to define a normative (as opposed to a de facto) average case, to which a normative average sentence would be assigned as a comparative starting point, have been rejected by the Federal Court. The Federal Court thought that the model of increasing and decreasing a normal penalty does not sufficiently reflect the complexity of sentencing.242
9.169
In the circumstances, then, German judges derive chief guidance in sentencing from their own experience and instincts, and from some felt tradition. Only in exceptional cases does the Federal Court quash a sentence which is in conspicuous disharmony with prevailing practice.
9.170
The starting point scheme in Finland is a great deal more sophisticated than the de facto system operated in Germany; but like the German practice, it is rooted much more in descriptive than in prescriptive factors. Chapter 6 of the Penal Code contains a model for the sentencing decision, known in Finland as the idea of normal punishments, embodied in paragraph 1. This provision requires the judge to pay special attention to the uniformity of sentencing practice. According to the travaux preparatoires, this means that the offence may be met with a normal punishment, i.e. the penal sanction most frequently imposed in similar cases;243 in exceptional cases, a penalty outside the starting point range can be resorted to.244 Compiling a set of starting points is a two-stage process:
|
9.171
Lappi-Seppδlδ cautions that references to a normal offence of punishment are simplifications. Instead of one normal offence it would be better to speak of several 'typical offences', and the corresponding 'zones of normal punishment'.245
He goes on to remark that the sentencing judge therefore requires three types of information:
|
9.172
Most official statistics (including Ireland's and Finland's before the new system was introduced) do not yield sufficient information to answer the first two questions.
9.173
Ireland's annual Garda Report on Crime gives a detailed account of the number of crimes reported, prosecutions taken and convictions obtained each year on an offence-by-offence basis.
The 1988 Report may be taken as an example.246 Some salient offender characteristics sex and age group are recorded in respect of all indictable offences, and of non-indictable traffic offences.247 Also, the sex, age group and nationality are recorded of all persons charged under the Misuse of Drugs Acts 19771984.248
9.174
Some offence characteristics are also published, in exceptional cases. Charges under the Misuse of Drugs Acts are broken down according to the type
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=261 |
of drug involved, though this information is not correlated with that provided about those charged.249
9.175
A table is provided of the value of property stolen in (i) offences against property with violence and (ii) larcenies, etc. without violence, broken down into the number of instances involving various monetary amounts.250 Armed robberies, and aggravated burglaries involving firearms are analysed according to geographical location the type of premises affected, and the value of property stolen.251 In the latter two cases, the tables concern offences committed and reported, not convictions obtained.
9.176
This summary of the relevant contents should suggest that the Garda Report on Crime is not at present of much utility to sentencers, save to illustrate the prevalence and (in a very few cases) the varying seriousness of certain offences. No information is given on dispositions after conviction, nor is such information as is given about offenders and offences correlated in any way. However, the provision of some information about offenders and offences does suggest that such information may be accessible in all cases, and may be put to use in future.
9.177
The Annual Report on Prisons and Places of Detention can supply more potentially useful data. Again, the 1988 Report may serve as an example. This includes a table giving the sentence lengths for imprisonment or penal servitude for those committed in that year on an offence-by-offence basis. Thus, for example, of a total of 240 committals for assault, we find 44 persons sentenced for less than three months, and five for over three years.252
9.178
Unfortunately, the Report on Prisons cannot simply be read with the Crime Report in order to connect convictions with dispositions. First, no information is provided on sentence other than of incarceration. A second area of disparity is in offence classification the prison data are rather more general in their definition of offences than the Crime Report.253 Thirdly, the fact that both reports concentrate on the activities of a calendar year can produce distortions. The 1988 Crime Report concerns itself only with offences which became known to the Gardai in that year. For example, for the 20 murders reported in 1988 there were 5 persons convicted.254 There were 10 committals to prison for murder in the same period. The reason for the discrepancy is that the Garda figures do not take account of those convicted in 1988 of murders committed in previous years. A conviction for a crime in any calendar year other than that in which the infraction became known to the Gardai is unaccounted for
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=262 |
in the Garda Report of that year, but will resurface mysteriously in the Prisons Report (and then only if it resulted in a sentence of imprisonment, penal servitude or detention). Obviously, some method of tracking cases from year to year will need to be devised, if the information available to the Gardai and the prison service is to be usefully combined.
9.179
A fourth possible incompatibility lies in the way data are complied. The Garda Report is chiefly concerned with offences. It does not indicate whether the same sequence of events can lead to more than one listed offence, or whether a single person may feature more than once in the conviction column, for different offences both of these eventualities, and particularly the latter, seem very likely. But the Prisons Report concentrates on numbers of offenders, or rather prisoners. It advises that in the case of an individual committed under sentence for more than one offence, only the principal offence is recorded in the tables, which is that for which the heaviest sentence is imposed, or for which the statutory maximum penalty is the more severe in cases of equality.255 A uniform method of counting offenders or offences should have to be devised in order for the two sets of data to be comparable.
9.180
The mode of recording of length of sentence in the Prisons Report may also bear some attention. When an individual is committed to serve concurrent sentences, the longest sentence is recorded; in the case of consecutive sentences imposed at the same time, the sentences are recorded in the tables as one sentence equal in length to the sum of the sentences added together.256 Such data will be of little use, and probably misleading to later sentencers faced either with a sole instance of the principal offence, or with some combination of offences. At its simplest the failure of the Prisons Report to indicate the proportion of sentences for the various offences which are in fact of composite origin is a considerable oversight. Irish courts have been very properly advised to impose sentence for all counts of conviction, even if all sentences are to run concurrently,257 and it should be possible to give a more accurate depiction of this process in the figures for imprisonment and other disposals.
9.181
The Prisons Report tables also indicate the sex of offenders, and give a more useful account of the age profile of the various types of offender (with five age groups over the age of 21 years).258 The number of previous sentences of imprisonment or detention of persons committed on conviction is also recorded; but no information is provided about the number who had other sentences imposed in the past. Thus, those who served sentences of community service, or had a suspended sentence imposed, etc. are placed in the same category as first-time offenders.
9.182
The Annual Report on the Probation and Welfare Service gives very
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=263 |
similar information to that in the Prisons Report on some non-incarcerative disposals. However, it only deals with those community disposals which involve supervision by the Probation and Welfare Service.259 Therefore, unsupervised sentences like suspended sentences of imprisonment are lost in a gap between the fields of coverage of the two reports.
9.183
The Probation and Welfare Service Report is concerned with those offenders placed on probation, under Community Service Orders, on recognisances under the Misuse of Drugs Act, 1977, and on supervision during deferment of penalty. Again, potentially useful information is presented, but in a way which fails to correlate the various types of data. One can ascertain the total number of Community Service Orders made during the year, and the aggregate number of hours ordered to be performed;260 the number of such orders made, categorised by the age and by the sex of the offender;261 the criminal offence from which such orders originated;262 and the number of orders for various periods of service e.g. 4080 hours, 81120 hours, etc.263 Roughly similar data are provided in respect of probation orders and other supervised community disposals.264
9.184
It will be appreciated that if rather different questions were asked, and if information were mustered and presented in a rather different fashion, much of the data required to institute a Finnish-style quantitative data base for sentencers is already available within the criminal justice system. In respect of crimes of theft, we are already well informed about the prevalence of such offences; about the value of property which is involved; about the number, age and sex of those sentenced to imprisonment therefor, and about the length of sentence imposed. Information on levels of prior conviction (or of previous sentences of incarceration at any rate) seems readily available. Gaps remain, as well as two grave problems. One is the time lag between the two chief present sources of statistics. The other is the lack of correlation between the information we have. How does the average sentence of a woman aged between 17 and 21 years convicted of larceny of property valued between £200 and £300 differ from that of a man aged between 40 and 50 years, with three prior convictions, of over £5,000?
9.185
Finland's deployment of sentencing data in a more meaningful and helpful manner bears further examination. Special analyses have been conducted in Finland of all cases of assault, theft, fraud, and drunken-driving, and are proposed for most common offence-types. Lappi-Seppδlδ describes the process as follows:
The empirical analysis of normal punishments can be divided into two |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=264 |
steps. The first step is to describe the effect of different sentencing criteria. The next step consists of the description of typical or normal offences. This means that the offence is divided into sub-categories by means of the sentencing criteria already identified during the previous step. The crime description which covers all forms of manifestation of the crime is thus divided into narrower descriptions which cover only part of the possible manifestation of the type of crime in question. The final aim of the analysis is to give the judge more exact descriptions of typical situations and corresponding zones of normal punishments. This should lead, in the end, to a more uniform sentencing practice with less and smaller deviations from the decisions made in previous cases.265 |
9.186
For example, cases of theft were classified into sub categories by three factors:
|
The following table resulted:
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=265 |
TABLE 1
PUNISHMENT IMPOSED FOR COMPLETED THEFT
The offender's previous criminality |
The amount of stolen goods (FMK 1980) |
|||
|
-499 |
500999 |
10001999 |
2000+ |
GROUP 1 NO BREAKING AND ENTERING |
|
|
||
A. First offender |
|
|
|
|
Fines (%) |
(90) |
(57) |
(67) |
(43) |
Median (dayfines) |
24,0 |
34,4 |
41,0 |
.. |
Median (months) |
1,2 |
2,3 |
2,8 |
.. |
B. Criminal Record |
|
|
|
|
Fines (%) |
(46) |
(23) |
(23) |
|
Median (dayfines) |
33,3 |
38,8 |
41,4 |
|
Median (months) |
2,1 |
2,8 |
3,0 |
3,8 |
Intermediate range (mth) |
2,03,0 |
2,63,8 |
2,24,4 |
3,54,8 |
C. Recidivist |
|
|
|
|
Fines (%) |
(4) |
(2) |
|
|
Median (months) |
2,4 |
3,4 |
4,6 |
6,6 |
Intermediate range (mth) |
2,03,7 |
3,14,6 |
4,25,8 |
.. |
GROUP 11 BREAKING AND ENTERING |
|
|
||
A. First offender |
|
|
|
|
Fines (%) |
(56) |
(26) |
(14) |
(4) |
Median (months) |
2,4 |
2,2 |
2,7 |
3,8 |
Intermediate range (mth) |
1,83,8 |
2,03,5 |
2,33,8 |
3,34,9 |
B. Criminal record |
|
|
|
|
Fines (%) |
(20) |
(8) |
(10) |
(1) |
Median (months) |
2,7 |
3,3 |
4,0 |
4,3 |
Intermediate range (mth) |
2,33,9 |
3,54,4 |
3,55,5 |
4,05,6 |
C. Recidivist |
|
|
|
|
Fines (%) |
() |
(3) |
() |
() |
Median (months) |
4,3 |
4,6 |
5,3 |
6,5 |
Intermediate range (mth) |
3,45,8 |
4,35,9 |
5,16,5 |
5,37,9 |
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=266 |
9.187
The intermediate range is the middle half of the applied penal scale. It consists of punishments within the latitude between the lower limit of the upper quarter and the upper limit of the lower quarter.266 This analysis gives courts a firm starting point, enabling them to find out the penalties imposed for offences committed approximately in the same manner, when the amount of stolen goods has been about the same value and when the offenders have had approximately the same kind of criminal record. It is at this point that other mitigating and aggravating criteria (listed non-exhaustively in the Code, and informed by its central sentencing objectives) may be taken into account. It is important to point out that the empirical analysis does not relieve the judge from normative evaluations; it only provides the relevant information that is needed in order to give the judge a practical 'starting point' for his decision.267
9.188
It is this which chiefly distinguishes the Finnish scheme from US-style presumptive guidelines systems. The Finnish scheme is persuasive rather than presumptive, and only furnishes a guide on the point of departure for the exercise of judicial sentencing discretion, rather than dictating the ultimate outcome of that process. Robinson's assertion that there exist in the US Federal Guidelines free harms offence features not catered for in the grid cannot therefore be levelled at the Finnish innovation. In effect, the difference may only be one of approach. In the US, departures are possible to take account of unforeseen factors. But these departures must be justified by the judge, and may be subject to rigorous scrutiny (while decisions which adhere to the letter of the guidelines effectively are not). In Finland, it is expected that the trial judge will advance from the point of departure provided by the descriptive table in order to take into consideration all other relevant factors this is not a step which of itself must be defended. Furthermore, it is a step made easier and more logical by the provision of both an indicative list of possibly relevant factors which might influence sentence, and a coherent core sentencing objective for the entire process.268
9.189
Ultimately, the table does no more than marshall the evidence of past sentencing practice it is the provision to the judiciary by statistical methodology of a useful analytical tool. Therefore, the Finnish model is less ambitious and should be less provocative to the judiciary. The compilation of tables such as that instanced above can be seen merely as an aid to detecting disparity in subsequent decisions, and to appreciating current sentencing patterns. From this, judges can draw their own conclusions. As such, the introduction of such analysis in this country would be a welcome step.269
9.190
A word of warning should be voiced however, on a number of counts. First, as Robinson pointed out, reliance on past practice only makes sense if one
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=267 |
is satisfied that that practice reflects the sentencing object(s) which one wishes to achieve. It may therefore be necessary to delay any such scheme until coherent sentencing principles have taken root in judicial practice. Secondly (and again, this cautionary note derives from Robinson), this mode of analysis makes no allowance for possible disparities as between offences and the maximum or minimum penalties available therefor. If this is perceived to be a problem, its solution remains within the legislative ambit. Thirdly, the success of such a scheme must be dependent both on the enthusiasm for it of trial judges, and the availability of an effective mode of appeal by both accused and prosecution.270
9.191
The Finns have adopted a more prescriptive approach in respect of new or reformed offences, or those which are uncommon (so that statistical analysis of practice might not be very helpful). The example given by Lappi-Seppδlδ is drunk driving. The main aim of the reform of the relevant legislation in 1977 was to cut down the use of unconditional imprisonment and to reduce sentencing disparities. What is termed a semi-official proposal for normal punishments was introduced by the judiciary. Once this initiative was taken by the judges, the proposal was discussed in training seminars organised by the Ministry of Justice.271
9.192
The severity of sanctions was graded mainly according to the blood alcohol concentration (BAC) of the accused. The following table shows the initial proposal and subsequent judicial practice. Comparison suggests that the recommendations were taken seriously, and the second table below illustrates that sentences became more uniform.272 The diagram in the second table describes the practice of eight courts before and after the 1977 reform, and shows a gratifying and dramatic narrowing of the differences between their sentencing practices for drunk driving.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=268 |
TABLE J
FINNISH DRUNK DRIVING TABLES
Fig. 1
PROPOSED AND ACTUAL PENALTIES FOR DRUNKEN DRIVING
BAC o/oo |
Proposed penalties Dayfines Prison |
Court practise Dayfines Prison (Mean) |
||
0.50.9 |
1030 |
|
22,9 |
|
0.91.2 |
3040 |
|
31,2 |
|
1.21.5 |
4060 |
|
40,1 |
|
1.51.9 |
|
1 month |
|
1,4 months |
1,92,19 |
|
1,5 months |
|
2,0 |
2,22,49 |
|
2 months |
|
2,2 |
2,5-over |
|
3 months |
|
2,8 |
Fig. 2 The choice of sanctions for drunk driving of eight courts before and after the introduction of normal punishments.
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=269 |
9.193
The relative merits of the Finnish scheme, are further discussed below, and are compared to those of the statistical system proposed by the Victorian Sentencing Committee in 1988. Unfortunately, we have no information on the practical steps taken to gather the information necessary for Finland's descriptive starting points. Doob and Park have, however, given an account of their Canadian experiment from its inception. Though similar in many ways to Finland's scheme, theirs addresses some problems which the Finns did not.
9.194
The information system devised by Doob and Park does not suggest a sentence, nor does it indicate what the 'normal' sentence is; all the system does is to give judges information about the range and distribution of sentences given for each offence and allows the judge to choose for more careful consideration and study those cases that are, in his or her view, comparable to the one before him or her.273 Their scheme is not as spare and structured as the Finnish, allowing the judge to focus on individual past cases.
9.195
About two thirds of Canadian judges surveyed by the Canadian Sentencing Commission has indicated that a computer system providing statistical summary information about current sentencing trends would be useful274Doob and Park set out to supply this demand with a system founded on the premise of proportionality and designed to provide descriptive data.275
9.196
Work began on the project in 1979. Since it was a system designed for use by judges, all important decisions were made in consultation with the judges using the system.
9.197
Existing data were quickly dismissed as a source of information relevant for the system. It was decided that since judges were most interested in knowing about sentences for cases as other judges saw those cases, that the information about cases should come from judges (or at a minimum should be collected under the authority of judges).276
9.198
An important constraint on the system was that data had to be collected on a form which judges could complete quickly. This was operationalised by a decision that the data collection sheet could be no longer than would fit on one side of one sheet of paper (including instructions), and it had to be in a checklist format. It was felt to be unrealistic to expect a busy judge to spend more than a minute completing the form for routine cases.277
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=270 |
9.199
It was decided to use subjective assessments of relevant sentencing factors, even when some sort of objective quantification might have been possible. The example given by Doob and Park is that of prior criminal record:
Without being too imaginative, the following dimensions could be used to define criminal record: (a) the number of previous convictions, (b) the recency of the last conviction, (c) whether the past record includes violent offences, (d) the length of time since the offender first was convicted, (e) whether the present offence was more serious than the most recent offence he had been sentenced for, and (f) the nature or severity of the offender's most recent sentence. It does not take a mathematical wizard to realise that if there are even as few as three or four levels of each of these six variables, there are over 700 combinations of aspects of this one variable criminal record.278 |
9.200
Certainly this would be unmanageable, so that it was wise to adopt more general assessments of criminal history: none, inconsequential or unrelatedsome but not serious; and substantial.279 But it should still be possible to try to streamline judges' perceptions of the seriousness of a prior criminal record by reference to items (a) to (f) quoted above. The provision of guidance on such matters could be achieved by a combination of qualitative analysis of trial decisions and of appellate judgments, and by a sentencing commission/judicial studies board.
9.201
In all, six material case factors were chosen:
|
9.202
Each had three levels, as described above for criminal history. The factors chosen are rather different from those employed by the Finns, which have as their focus the matters described at (A) and (C). (E) and (F) would probably be impermissible under a just deserts policy such as that proposed in this paper,280 and factor (B) could very likely be embraced by factor (D)'s catch-all category of aggravating and mitigating factors.
9.203
The inclusion of undefined aggravating or mitigating factors within the statistical calculation marks a considerable point of difference from the starting
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=271 |
points scheme conceived by the Finns. That scheme treats such factors as being reasons to depart from the heartland of unexceptional cases which the calculated starting points purport to represent; Doob and Park treat aggravating and mitigating factors as being integral to the presentation of all cases.
9.204
In fact the Finnish notion of identifying starting points from past practice, from which is an instant case the judge moves to take account of particular factual circumstances (aggravating or mitigating, or relevant to penalty-type) to devise an appropriate sentence, is posited on a doubtful premise. It seems to assume either (i) that none, or no significant number, of the dispositions which make up the sentencing statistics was greatly affected by such individual circumstances ie. that it is the relevant offence and offender characteristics employed in the statistical analysis which dictated case outcomes; or (ii) that if significant numbers of outcomes were influenced by aggravating, mitigating or other circumstances, that these must have cancelled each other out, so as to achieve the apparent effect described at (i) immediately above.
9.205
Otherwise, the statistics would not provide an accurate starting point from which to consider individual and exceptional case elements such elements would already be embodied, in an indecipherable melange, in the starting point tables. Nor can one be immediately convinced of the correctness of either of the possible premises just outlined. While skilful reading of past cases should allow the most material case factors to be expressly embodied in the statistical analysis, other factors of great influence on sentencers, perhaps less common, must remain unaccounted for; nor is there any reason to believe in a balance of aggravation and mitigation which negates the effect of both.
9.206
This problem is avoided by Doob and Park by the express (and correct) acknowledgment of the role special aggravating or mitigating facts must have in influencing sentence in past as well as present cases. But the inclusion of such factors (under a rather too general and unhelpful rubric) within the depiction of past cases makes the Doob/Park information system ill-suited to be the basis of a starting point system. There can be no useful division of cases into the normal and the exceptional, when the depiction of the normal includes an account of the exceptional. Starting points are intended to provide points of departure for the judge who is presented with unusual and relevant circumstances which are deemed not to be accounted for in the data available; but in fact, sentencing statistics are affected by such circumstances, to the degree to which they influences past sentencing decisions. Doob and Park are right, then, to try to accommodate them in their analysis of the case (though one might question the means employed).
9.207
What, then of Finland's descriptive starting points? It might be suggested that the sentencing judge, in every case, should pronounce the appropriate sentence for the basic offence before him (composed from the material case factors), before going on to impose the actual sentence or offender circumstances. The former could be recorded for the purpose of starting point statistics. This would have several advantages:
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=272 |
|
9.208
It remains doubtful, however, if the answer to the underlying problem of the Finnish scheme lies in this suggestion. Potential drawbacks include:
|
9.209
The foregoing discussion need not conclude with a definite rejection of starting points schemes. It may be decided that the conceptual flaw in the Finnish model is not of such great practical effect as to deprive it of all efficacy; alternatively, a different starting point model prescriptive or quasi-descriptive could be designed.
9.210
Let us return for the moment to the Doob and Park information system. A case description sheet is depicted in Table K.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=273 |
TABLE K
Case Description Sheet (8 November 1985 revision)
Please fill this in for each person sentenced for an indictable offence or for a hybrid which was proceeded on by way of indictment. For cases with multiple counts, fill out the sheet for the most serious count only or, if this is impossible to determine, the first count on the indictment.
Name of accused:
Offence:
Is the accused being sentenced for more than one offence at this time:
No
Yes, for unrelated offences
Yes, for related offences
Date:
Judge:
Please rate the case before you on each of the six factors (A through F) by placing an X in front of the phrase that best describes the case before you. If a factor is completely irrelevant to the particular case, feel free to leave that factor blank.
(A) Relative severity of this particular offence as compared to other instances of the same offence:
Less severe than most
About the same as most
More sever than most
(B) Involvement of the offender: premeditation of and participation in the offence
Minimal
About the same as most
Substantial
(C) Previous criminal record of the accused
None, inconsequential, or unrelated
Some, but not serious
Substantial
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=274 |
(D) Presence of aggravating or mitigating circumstances
None, or they offset each other
Mitigating
Aggravating
(E) Impact on victim
None or minimal
Substantial, and redressed
Substantial, and not redressed
(F) Prevalence of this type of offence in the community
Not serious in the community
Average
Serious in the community
Now, please circle the factor or factors (A through F) that you feel are the most important dimensions in determining the sentence for this case.
Sentence: Check and complete those that are appropriate:
Absolute or conditional discharge
Probation
Restitution
Compensation
Community Service Order
Fine of $
Imprisonment for: Years Months Days
Accused in custody awaiting trial: No Yes, but not relevant to sentencing.
OPTIONAL comments: You may add a few words if there are special factors or circumstances which aren't covered by the above factors.
9.211
A number of other points of difference from the Finnish scheme can be pointed out. First, this is an all-purpose form. There are not the carefully compiled material case factors of the Finnish statistics. This has the virtue of convenience, but probably diminishes the degree to which the data collected can
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=275 |
help judges in future cases. As was already remarked, victim impact and offence prevalence are not matters of which we feel it proper for judges to take cognisance. If these were to be removed, and individual forms were to be devised for separate offences, or offence groups, there would be room to include specifically some of the more common offence features which are thought to be relevant to desert and to sentence. To follow the Finnish example, one might include as the most important factors for theft the amount of stolen goods, and whether or not there was breaking and entering. Another might be of violence. Less common factors would still be accommodated under the rubric of aggravation and mitigation in this way. Some more objective elements could be added to a scheme criticised in some quarters as too subjective.282
9.212
Using a computer disk, the judge employing the Doob and Park information system chooses the relevant offence. A second screen of choices then appears, on which the judge can describe the instant case in terms corresponding to the information form featured just above. To do this, the judge simply presses the appropriate key, and then describes the record by pointing to the most appropriate of the three descriptions which then appear on the screen in this way. Cases of interest can be selected by using up to the maximum six factors which are contained on the original sheet filled out by the judge. Table L is a replica of this second screen.
TABLE L
245.1 (1)(B) Assault bodily harm [153 PC, 55 CA Cases
You can select from O to 6 factors. Select a factor using the =1= key. Remove a factor using the key. The and keys move the arrow. Pressing F10 tallies the distribution; ESC lets you return.
FACTORS |
Relative severity of the offence |
Involvement of the offender |
Previous criminal record of the accused |
Aggravating or Mitigating circumstances |
Impact on victim |
Prevalence in the community |
Previous criminal record of the accused |
None, inconsequential |
Some, but not serious |
Substantial |
Table L: Sample Factors screen showing the manner in which comparable cases are selected from the population of cases in the system.283
9.213
Table L illustrates how a user would instruct the computer to select, simultaneously, those cases where the offender was described by the judge as
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=276 |
having a substantial previous criminal record and cases where there were aggravating circumstances. The judge will be shown fewer sentences as the number of factors chosen increases. Presumably, however, the range of sentences given those cases will also be narrower.284
9.214
A third screen then appears (in between 15 and 45 seconds) giving the distribution of past sentences presented as the most serious component of the sentence divided up into ten categories. Two columns show respectively the sentences in the judge's own province, and in the other combined Canadian provinces. A third column gives the decisions in similar cases of the provincial Court of Appeal, and the fourth shows the total distribution of sentences by that court for all cases of the instant offence. An example of this screen is given in Table M.
TABLE M
245.(1)(b) Assault bodily harm [Cases through 87/03/31]
Previous criminal record of the accused Substantial
Aggravating or Mitigating circumstances Aggravating
|
Man |
Can |
CA-Sel |
CA-Tot |
Discharge, Probation, Restitution, Compensation |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
Community Service Order |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
Fine |
0 |
0 |
0 |
5 |
Imprisonment 1 day to 1 month |
0 |
0 |
0 |
4 |
Imprisonment 31 days to 3 months |
0 |
0 |
0 |
7 |
Imprisonment 3.1 months to 6 months |
3 |
6 |
1 |
11 |
Imprisonment 6.1 to 11.9 months |
1 |
1 |
0 |
3 |
Imprisonment 1 year to 17.9 months |
1 |
1 |
2 |
7 |
Imprisonment 18 months to 2 years less 1 day |
0 |
2 |
1 |
8 |
Imprisonment 2 years or more |
0 |
1 |
1 |
5 |
Composite sentences |
0 |
0 |
1 |
5 |
TOTAL |
5 |
12 |
7 |
55 |
Move the arrow F5: Print the distribution F6: Print indiv. cases F7: View indiv. Cases ESC: Return to Factors F1 Begin Afresh
Table M: Sample Distribution screen showing the sentences given for offences described according to the factors listed. The most severe component of the sentence is shown. Composite sentences refer to the situation when an offender is sentences for more than one offence yet the sentence is expressed as a single composite sentence.285
9.215
The judge can then, if he or she wishes, examine individual cases more carefully on the screen, or on a computer printout. Summaries of the Court of Appeal's decisions have also been made available. Thus, qualitative date are provided.
9.216
Doob and Park point out that at least one advantage of having appellate and trial data presented side by side is that one can quickly see that the cases heard by the Court of Appeal and, therefore, the distribution of final sentences,
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=277 |
are different from the Provincial Court cases. If one were to try to infer the overall distribution of sentences, or the average sentence, from Court of Appeal cases, it appears that one would usually arrive at estimates that are higher than those given at the Provincial Court level. Since it appears that most appeals in Canada are initiated by offenders rather than by the Crown, most sentences would be expected to be at the high end of the distribution. The information system, as designed at present, puts these sentences in context.286
9.217
It will be clear that the data provided in the Doob and Park model are intended to be used rather differently to the information supplied to judges in Finland. It is sought to present it in an intelligent and relevant fashion, but the system does not purport to make any calculation, however basic no median sentence is presented, only a distribution of sentences. Nonetheless, Doob and Park believe that this information can provide the trial judge with a starting point. By this term, they appear to have in mind something not unlike the Finnish idea, but which is not characterised by the same element of calculation at the outset. Their model of the sentencing decision is more fluid and discretionary at all stages, but it is envisaged that it have a sound foundation of hard information:
[T]he current Provincial Court data, as cold and statistical as they might be ... give the sentencing judge explicit information about the current range and the kinds and severity of sentences that have most often been given in the past. The range and most common sentence might or might not be the same as the range and most common sentence that the judge might have considered. They might be used, then, as a starting point if the judge wanted to use colleagues' decisions for this purpose. The judge might look first at the distribution of sentences given in comparable cases and then consider how the specific characteristics of the case being sentenced should be considered with the normative data in mind .... Finally, the judge might look at the Court of Appeal decisions in the range being considered. In this way, the number of possible Court of Appeal cases could be reduced to a manageable number. Then the judge could examine the narrower range of Court of Appeal decisions to evaluate the sentence being contemplated.287 |
9.218
It may be that so unstructured an approach is to be preferred. No matter how insistent one might be that a Finnish-style table of starting points was advisory only, there is the danger either that judges would reject them as an intrusion, or else would adhere to them too unquestioningly, thus giving them a de facto presumptive quality. Neither of these alternative dangers can be said to be presented by Doob and Park's information tables.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=278 |
9.219
Unfortunately, at the conclusion of their project, Doob and Park were forced to conclude that it had failed in all but one of the provinces (Saskatchewan) where it had been conducted. Initial judicial enthusiasm had evaporated elsewhere, and recourse to the information system had declined. They attributed this to a mistaken premise. They had started with the idea that judges would want to have easily accessible to them knowledge of current sentences being handed down in comparable cases. In fact, they concluded that this was not the case.288
9.220
This is a disturbing conclusion. They rehearse a number of reasons for it, but ultimately trace it to one central problem: that we do not have an agreed-upon model of sentencing in Canada.289 Such is the diversity of approaches to sentencing by trial judges, and the perceived importance of appellate courts in their attempts to introduce some sort of order to sentencing, that trial judges have little incentive to have regard to the practise of their colleagues. it is to be hoped, therefore, that the adoption of a coherent sentencing policy such as that proposed in this paper would bring the added benefit of increased judicial recourse to sentencing information, however compiled and presented.
9.221
A reassuring point about Doob and Park's scheme is its cost. Though a total of Can$325,000 was spent, this was over an experimental period of some 10 years, and covered five separate provincial jurisdictions. They estimate that even if one were to develop a completely new system from scratch ... the one-time only costs of development would be less than Can$50,000 with continuing costs of less than Can$5,000 per year (if the data are provided by the province).290
9.222
The Victorian Sentencing Committee concerns itself in its 1988 Report with the development of information aids for sentencers.
9.223
It stresses the necessary distinction between quantitative and qualitative data.
9.224
Statistics collected in most jurisdictions fail to provide much necessary information:
What is required is a policy incorporating rules prescribing the way in which information about the offence and the offender should be selected, classified and aggregated to determine the appropriate goals of sentence and to give effect to those goals in particular cases.291 |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=279 |
9.225
As Lane LCJ noted in Bibi, consistency of approach is the key to combating disparity.292 This involves:
|
9.226
Therefore, statistics must be compiled in the context of coherent policy development.293
9.227
For that reason, reliance on statistics presently available in most jurisdictions is suspect. At present, most differentiate according to outcomes (sentence type and length) but not according to relevant inputs (offence and offender characteristics).294 The Victorian Committee reviews three proposed schemes for remedying this deficiency Wilkins's, Hogarth's, and Doob's before suggesting its own.
9.228
This is an attempt to provide statistics linking major offence and offender characteristics, and weights for them, with quanta of sentence. To use this system for a particular case, the judge must allot points in terms of the extent to which the case is characterised by the offence and offender characteristics identified in the statistical analysis. The scores on the two dimensions identify the appropriate cell on the table. Each cell will have associated with it statistics on the percentage and length of imprisonment in similar circumstances in the past (and each subsequent resort to the grid can be used to keep it up to date). This information comprises the guidelines. It may be necessary to use several tables in any case, each table covering a group of legal offence categories, but Wilkins provides rules on how case elements are to be aggregated: the rule of multiple regressions.295
9.229
However, the Victorian Commission has a number of criticisms of this approach:296
|
9.230
This system is designed to identify the ranges of sentence for various combinations of offence and offender characteristics.
|
9.231
One of the chief drawbacks of Hogarth's scheme, especially for smaller jurisdictions, is that it is based on a very large number of offence/offender combinations, and a sentencing range should be available for each combination based on a reasonable number of fairly recent decisions. For more serious offences in states like Victoria (or Ireland) the requisite amount of case-law will simply be unavailable to satisfy the scheme's thirst for cases.300Hogarth's proposals also share with Wilkins' and the Finnish system the possibly unfounded assumption that judges consistently apply a known sentencing policy regarding the scaling, weighting and combining of material case factors.
9.232
Doob and Park recognised the chief weakness of the Hogarth system outlined above, and sought to simplify it, as we have seen, by confining themselves to six broad case characteristics, each of which had three general categories of seriousness. The Victorian committee suggested that the problem with this approach is that individual judges must assess how the elements of the cases before them fit these qualitative categories. No guidance could be sought from Doob's scheme in making this subjective decision, so that the scheme failed to fulfil one of the desiderata for uniformity in sentencing, namely that each of the offence and offender characteristics should be defined objectively in relation to seriousness.302
9.233
Doob and Park are in fact quite enthusiastic about the subjective element in their information system. As they remark, judges are most interested in knowing about sentences for cases as other judges saw those cases.303 The problems involved in assessing criminal history have already been adverted to by way of example of how almost infinite combinations of objective variables could clog up an information system. Doob and Park see this as being quite unnecessary:
When the judges who were part of the steering committee discussed issues like criminal record, a number of things became clear. First, they seemed to talk about the variable in broad subjective terms, e.g. a serious record, or a record which was irrelevant and their sentence, it seemed, would be guided by such a judgment. To the extent that this is the case, then, a judge who wanted to know how a case would be sentenced by another judge would be better off getting the answer to the question. What sentences have you handed down to people with |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=282 |
'serious' criminal records for this offence? than he or she would be in knowing what sentences had been handed down in cases where the person had three convictions one fairly recent, and one involving a threat or small amount of violence. If the sentencing judge knew that this hypothetical case had been seen by the other as involving a serious criminal record, the sentencing judge could interpret the sentence accordingly. Knowing the objective information would not tell the information-seeking judge whether the information-providing judge had seen the record as serious, or as somewhat less serious than that. A strong case, in addition to the practical issue, can be made, then, for the use of subjective ratings by the judges as the basis of an information system for judges to use as an aid to sentencing.304 |
9.234
There is much to be said for this approach, but it works on a rather disturbing assumption. It seems, consciously but nonchalantly, to admit disparity by the back door. Doob and Park would have judges hand down similar sentences based on the perceived similarity of cases; but possibly quite marked differences in the perceptions of different judges do not discontent them.
9.235
This situation is not irremediable. As a quite separate objective, to be pursued by qualitative guidance by appellate courts, sentencing commission or judicial studies board it could be sought to streamline judges' perceptions and therefore their subjective assessments. To take again the example of a prior conviction record, policy statements could be agreed on how the various objective elements number of past convictions, recency of last conviction, violence, severity, etc. should be interpreted in assessing (subjectively) the seriousness of an offender's criminal history.305
9.236
Also, it is quite possible to introduce to Doob and Park's scheme a leavening of simple objective case factors, depending on the offence concerned. This was suggested above. One must, however, be careful to avoid Hogarth's mistake, which was to introduce so great a number of objective variables as to give his system an unquenchable thirst for cases.
9.237
Concluding that the three most readily available statistical models were inadequate, the Victoria Committee sought to develop an alternative. Only Wilkins' scheme had offered a rule specifying how judges could combine numerous case elements in order to reach an overall assessment. it was considered, however, that this rule multiple regression was not faithful to the structure of judicial thought. Associated with this failing was the perceived failure of average sentences adequately to represent individual judge's sentencing objectives. A satisfactory scheme must commence, the Committee submitted, from an appropriate model of judicial decision-making and objectives. In particular, they sought to distinguish two types of decision within the sentencing
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=283 |
process:
|
9.238
Thomas defined the tariff as a framework to which a sentencer can refer in order to determine what factors in a particular case are relevant and the weight to be attached to each of them. He proposed three steps:
|
9.239
The committee criticises Thomas for choosing a number of combinations of case factors, rather unsystematically, to characterise offences like burglary, when the variety of possible factual scenarios (and therefore of material case factors) is almost infinite. He accordingly failed (probably inevitably) to provide a logical structure in which peculiar combinations of case characteristics could be systematically and precisely related to sentence. The Committee suggests an alternative calculation in accordance with readily calculable dimensions. For burglary, four were suggested, based on reviews of sentencing decisions in several jurisdictions:
|
9.240
In the case of most offences, it is surmised that this element the identification of material offence factors could be easily enough formulated from existing legal literature. The other elements are more difficult the classification and weighting of case facts in relation to case factors, rules for combining case factors, and ascertaining the appropriate types and levels of sentence for the various combinations of case factors. The statistical technique adopted by the Victorian Committee is multi-attribute utility measurement (MAUM).308
9.241
One identifies, or determines:
|
9.242
Stage (iii) severity scaling is the easiest of the tasks remaining. Whether it be by consultation with judges, sentencing commission study, legislation, or public opinion sampling is a policy decision. If one seeks statistical guidelines which purport to be descriptive rather than prescriptive, the former option seems more apposite, and was resorted to in Victoria.309 We call this approach quasi-descriptive.
9.243
Judges were asked to rate various degrees of financial loss, or of violence inflicted, on a scale of 0100, and in relation to 2 extremes (e.g. in respect of financial loss, $100 and $120,000 defined the two extremities of the scale). The results of a consultation of seven County Court criminal judges are indicated in Table N.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=285 |
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=286 |
9.244
The judges were then asked to quantify the relative weights of the four factors in the determination of the overall seriousness of an offence stage (iv) in the MAUM process. Each judge's task was to identify, for each of the possible pairs of offence factors, the more important of the two and the importance of this factor relative to the other. An excerpt from their conclusions is given in Table O.
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=287 |
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=288 |
9.245
This indicates that total value of the theft makes .88 the contribution of violence to the victim to the assessment of the overall seriousness of the offence characteristics. When the relationship of the four is determined, it is expressed in proportions of 100 (e.g. 31, 25, 22, 22).
9.246
Stage (v) requires the determination of the overall seriousness of the offence characteristics of a particular burglary by aggregating the assessments on each of the component offence factors, having regard to the factor weights. Thomas submits from his study of English appellate decisions that the ultimate quantum judgment is reached by adding or subtracting, as it were, points for aggravating or mitigating circumstances relating to the crime.310 The simplest rule describing the judicial determination of the quantum of seriousness of an offence would be a weighted additive value function. This rule states that to determine the overall seriousness of an offence one simply multiplies the single attribute serious assessments of each offence factor by the appropriate factor weight, and then sums these multiples. the equation representing this rule is the formal statement of this element of sentencing policy.311
9.247
The final step is to determine the types and levels of sentence appropriate for various combinations of these offence characteristics. Offender characteristics and mitigation enter the equation at this point. Thomas' model of sentencing policy is different in its approach to this question from that suggested in this paper, and therefore it is not proposed to discuss the treatment of this topic here. Suffice to say that the judge would complete a detailed proforma covering the relevant offence factors, which would be processed by computer to give the ceiling sentence for that particular combination of case factors. The judge could then at his discretion consider the case for mitigation, or whether there were any material elements of the instant case for which the scoring system did not make adequate or proper allowance, and which warrant an adjustment in sentence.312
9.248
The Victorian Committee does remark that the offence characteristics may require further consideration, while certain offender characteristics should also be incorporated, e.g. criminal history.313
9.249
The Victorian Report goes on to consider how a statistical data base can be used to guide numerically the work of sentencing judges. The guidance judgments of the english Court of Appeal (Criminal Division) are outlined, as are the guidelines systems of Minnesota (which it concludes to be unable to cope with multiple case factors) and the federal US. The statistical basis of the latter
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=289 |
is criticised as imprecise and intuitive, while the guidelines themselves masked the conflicts and gaps in sentencing policy and practise for which the US Commission substituted its own judgments. The failure of the US Commission to employ the level of detail originally planned in describing case characteristics is noted the Commission abandoned this attempt at developing what is described as a pure real offence system on two grounds: (1) it would have had to decide precisely what factors are material to sentence and how the courts aggregate this information; (2) it found no practical way of taking into account the large number of potentially material case factors across a range of circumstances the proposed solution was so complex that it was impracticable.314 The frank acknowledgement by the Canadians of their failure to provide a reasonably certain rule for the combination of case information is also cited.315
9.250
The ultimate conclusion of the Committee on this point is that some sort of numerical guidance should be attempted, but it does not commit itself to a particular model. The instant proposal is no more than a numerical aid to the common law approach.316 In effect, the Victorian Committee's proposed quantitative data base could become the source of quasi-descriptive starting points for the guidance of sentencing judges, on Finnish lines.
9.251
A number of problems may be identified in the Victorian statistical scheme. First, it too relies on averages of judges' sentencing assessments, which may diverge widely in fact in such cases, an average may not be very representative of anyone's position. The danger of such an adverse effect is decreased, however, where one can be satisfied that judges have adopted and fairly consistently follow a single coherent statement of sentencing policy. If such were the case, however, one might be inclined to adopt a more purely descriptive approach than has been advocated for Victoria. The statistics compiled by Victoria are descriptive not of how judges have acted in the past, but of how they believe they would or should act. Even if the answers corresponded exactly for both cases, the former is still the more appealing source of authority. The doctrine of stare decisis exercises a strong hold in the common law world, and in other contexts (e.g. in respect of locus standi) the courts have been very wary of dealing with hypothetical cases, pronouncements on which will generally be obiter anyway.
9.252
One wonders also whether the criticism levelled against Hogarth could not also be applied to the Victorian Sentencing Committee's proposal. It was remarked that a sentencing range should be available for the various possible combinations of offence and offender factors based on a reasonable number of fairly recent decisions (which it was feared did not exist in respect of more serious offences). But the Victorian scheme entails a jurisdiction's judges, in a single sitting as it were, making a number of decisions on the seriousness of conduct, and on the relative weight of factors, which decisions become the basis
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=290 |
for the system's calculated assessment of every possible combination of the chosen case factors. A quasi-descriptive data base which can be compiled, perhaps, in an afternoon may not convince those for whom the justification for a descriptive scheme is the accretion of judicial authority over time. Certainly, if an accurate means of analysing and breaking down the components of actual judicial decisions could be devised, these would be a preferable source of data. Large numbers of individual cases should give rise to and illustrate a pattern of sentencing decision-making of whose authenticity one might be mor confident than of that of entirely hypothetical conclusions.
9.253
However, analysis of sentencing decisions is beset by problems. One cannot isolate individual factors and determine the precise weight attributed to them by judges. it is difficult to exclude factors which are material but uncommon. One can be beset by almost infinite fact combinations and permutations if it is sought to record judges' responses to discrete objective case factors; while the alternative, which is to record their subjective assessments of widely-defined case factors may not satisfy all. As we have seen, these problems need not be fatal. It may be that (in the Finnish case) the distortion is not statistically significant. With regard to Doob and Park's experiment, a compromise which balanced objective and subjective factors might be sufficient. Nonetheless, the correlation of inputs and outcomes of sentencing decision-making which can be provided by descriptive models is of necessity only approximate.
9.254
This is a problem which does not arise for the Victorian proposal. It produces objective starting point data which are pure, in so far as they derive from hypothetical case scenarios unadulterated by aggravating or mitigating circumstances other than those chosen as material case factors. It is precisely this hypothetical quality, however, which makes the Victorian scheme less immediately appealing to common lawyers. it is a quality, however, which makes it even better suited than the Finns' own data base for the operation of a starting point system of the Finnish type.
9.255
It might finally be noted that the Victorian scheme does not appear to be very transparent. Though the mode of their calculation seems convincing, the relative weights of case factors, stated as fractions of 100, must be incomprehensible to the onlooker (and possible also to the judges).
9.256
There is recognition by the Victorian Committee that a less complicated structure should be employed in respect of less serious offences. In this regard, much heed is paid to the ideas of Ashworth.317 His general scheme for devising guidance for sentencers did not include any provision for factor weights derived through trade-offs, but it is concluded that this additional detail is an
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=291 |
especially complicating element, while it could make no more than a minor contribution to the sentencing process for less serious offences. The imposed penalties for such offences do not cover a wide range:318 also (as in the Finnish example of drunk driving) there will rarely be more than a very few relevant case factors.
9.257
The system ultimately recommended is reminiscent of the English Magistrates' Association table of Suggestions for Traffic Offence Penalties,319 but responds to criticisms of this form of guidance which called for greater detail.320
9.258
The scheme is composed of five elements, set out as follows:
|
9.259
It is likely that even this level of analysis would be unnecessary for the most prevalent, minor offences of strict liability. Again, the Finnish example of drunk-driving is illustrative of the simplicity of approach which can be sufficient at this end of the scale of offences.
9.260
Any proposed quantitative guidance (if only the provision of numerical aids to the common law approach) will need to be complemented by a set of principles governing the exercise of the sentencing discretion. In this regard, the Victorian Committee was more impressed by Hogarth's proposals.
9.261
A routinely updated computer data base would aid qualitative decisions of judges availing of three files.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=292 |
9.262
File 1 would contain appellate sentencing decisions, including guideline judgments; these would be classified by legal offence category, and would be available both in summary and verbatim.
9.263
File 2 would contain a list of the offences and offender factors material to the aim/s of sentence.322 Factors deemed immaterial to sentence would also be outlined.
9.264
File 3 would contain statutory and case law covering the choice of the type of sentence, the quantum of sentence and the conditions under which the sentence is to be served.323
9.265
These proposals are merely designed to assist the hard-pressed sentencing judge. Certainly, the compilation of sets of relevant sentencing materials for this jurisdiction would be a great boon. Whether this would be by way of computer data base, or in more conventional printed form,324 will be a matter for judicial preference, and for the Department of Justice which might be responsible for funding it.
9.266
The Victorian Report has led to the circulation of a draft Sentencing Bill. In general, its provisions are less detailed, less prescriptive and less comprehensive than the form of guidance envisaged in the Report.325 More pertinently to the present discussion, the Judicial Studies Board Act 1990 (as yet unproclaimed) establishes a body with the responsibility of assisting the judiciary and magistracy in developing a system of guidance. (The actual statistical scheme for such a system is not set out, nor was this intended by the Sentencing Committee). However, the Victorian Court of Criminal Appeal has come down firmly against the sort of analysis of decision-making favoured by the Committee in Young (a 1990 case). The sentencing judge in that case relied on a method of determining sentence not dissimilar from that proposed by the Committee. He commented that he had found that approach helpful in that it requires the sentencer to go about the sentencing task in a more orderly way and helps to ensure that all relevant matters are considered. However the Court (Young CJ and Crockett and Nathan JJ) favoured an approach of intuitive synthesis, and stated:
It is sufficient for us to observe that we can find no warrant in authority or justification or advantage from a practical point of view in the adoption of an artificial process for arriving at an appropriate sentence or any process which unnecessarily limits further the discretion of a |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=293 |
sentencing judge. We think that the adoption of such a process is calculated to lead to error and injustice. Until Parliament or the High Court indicates to the contrary we are clearly of the opinion that artificial processes or methods should not be adopted in Victoria.326 |
9.267
Certainly this decision bodes ill for the implementation of a scheme whose success is dependent on judicial co-operation.
9.268
We have seen how the rather crude presumptive guidelines devised for Minnesota have been developed and refined over the past decade or more in other jurisdictions. The fear that discretion was being shifted to prosecutors was somewhat allayed, though it was not banished, by the regulation of the charging process e.g. in Washington. In Washington also, criminal history scoring methods were adopted to avoid both prosecutorial manipulation, and simple unfairness to those with numerous but trivial prior convictions. Penalties other than imprisonment were addressed in the US Guidelines. In Michigan, the weights of both offence and criminal history factors are adjusted so as better to reflect their relative gravity inter se. In the US Federal Guidelines, sophisticated rules were enacted to govern guilty plea discounts and the effect of multiple offences. Factors contributing to the calculation of sentence were chosen through painstaking analysis of prevailing practice, and according to their reliability in field scoring. If some guidelines schemes (such as the federal one) were built on the sandy foundations of incoherent sentencing policy, this obstacle was surmountable. It must have seemed at times during the discussion above that well-designed sentencing guidelines were the best available method of promoting just deserts and reducing disparity. Certainly the levels of adherence to them in some US jurisdictions seemed to suggest that the war against sentencing disparity could be and was being won. But any such suggestion had to be accompanied by a qualification: adherence to presumptive guidelines can only reduce disparity when those guidelines take account of, and attribute appropriate weight to all the criteria by which we believe offenders should be compared. Failure to incorporate important criteria relating to offence severity and culpability, mitigation and so on constitutes a failure of the guidelines in tackling disparity.
9.269
This leads us to an insoluble problem, highlighted by the debate between Robinson and his colleagues on the US Sentencing Commission about free harms and levels of detail in presumptive guidelines. If one sees the guidelines as carving out a heartland, embodying only the criteria that exemplify the typical or most common case of each offence addressed, then account must be taken of atypical or uncommon circumstances by a departure from the guidelines. Such untravelled territory is not regulated in the way the heartland is; the factors considered may not be at all reliable in field scoring (i.e. objectively quantifiable); and the decision to depart will usually be discretionary, so that some judges may
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=294 |
choose to do so, and others not. In such circumstances, disparity is to be feared.
9.270
The alternative is to develop guidelines of great complexity. But this too is problematical. Constructing guidelines which one could confidently claim were comprehensive would be an infinite and sisyphean labour. Also, the spectre of disparity again raises its head. As was pointed out by the US Commission, the greater the number of decisions required and the greater their complexity, the greater the risk that different judges will apply the guidelines differently to situations that are in fact similar (or vice versa).
9.271
A compromise such as that attempted in the Federal Guidelines is possible, but it must import elements of both problems into the sentencing process. It still represents a failure of the guidelines movement to live up to its claims.
9.272
One might counter that the problem of disparity also bedevils the sentencing process in jurisdictions which have remained attached to the traditional model of unrestricted judicial sentencing discretion; and that guidelines at least place some order on judicial practice, introduce consistency as between unexceptional, heartland cases, and allow us to highlight the continuing problem of disparity in a more structured context. However, it is submitted that the structure of presumptive guidelines (and this is the chief point of our critique) is itself a force for disparity.
9.273
Presumptive guidelines almost invariably prioritise some relevant sentencing criteria (the simpler, more easily verified, or more common ones) over others. A particular offence is allocated a place in the matrix according to the presence or absence of certain circumstances (violence, criminal history, etc.). Let us imagine a case, where there are other salient circumstances not provided for in the guidelines, e.g. a high degree of intention when the requisite mens rea for the offence is only recklessness, or a threat to a peculiarly vulnerable person. The judge who departs from the guidelines to take account of these factors when sentencing must justify doing so; the decision of a judge to ignore them will be unassailable, so that many judges may take this safer but less appropriate route. The Canadian Commission has sought to avoid this by allowing appeals against presumptive sentences as well as against departures. This is exceptional, and it is not clear, in the context of a presumptive guidelines system, that such appeals will be effective.327
9.274
Thus, presumptive guidelines tend to establish a two-tier hierarchy of sentencing factors, which cannot be defended. It is possible, however, to replicate some of the benefits of guidelines systems while avoiding this great
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=295 |
shortcoming.328 The guidelines grid has the great merit, already acknowledged, of regulating sentencing practice in that heartland of uncomplicated cases whose salient features it anticipates. The starting point grid or calculation, however formulated, can perform a similar task; but is not presumptive. A table of starting points is in no way binding. It should serve merely to inform the judges of how they and their colleagues have applied sentencing policy in the past (or how they believe they would apply it), when dealing with instances of an offence with similar characteristics. It is, therefore, only an aid or a guide to the application of sentencing policy. The basic statement of sentencing policy remains paramount, and in a particular case may dictate a sentence outside the range suggested by the table of starting points. On appeal, it is conformity to sentencing policy, not to the table of starting points, which the superior court should seek to enforce (and its decisions will hopefully be relied upon to improve the table). The judge's decision on sentence must be defended, if appealed, whether it constitutes a departure from the starting point or not. It is central to the notion of a starting point, as its name suggests, that it constitutes only a point of departure. It is a source of guidance, but there is no presumption of completeness. (The possibility of completeness is an implicit, but impossible, premise of presumptive guidelines, even if this is not admitted). Aggravating and mitigating factors, listed non-exhaustively, have the same status as the factors employed to calculate the starting point.329 It is as much an error of principle to follow the grid or formula and to ignore other material factors as it is to depart from the grid or formula without good cause. Appellate review, in such a system, is not simply a means of policing and enforcing guidelines it is a potent vehicle for judicial guidance of sentencing practice, and can help ensure consistent adherence to sentencing policy.
9.275
It should finally be remarked that starting points systems have much to learn from the refinements of guidelines developed in US. Rules for sentencing for multiple offences, for assessing the seriousness and relevance of criminal history, and for the objective quantification of material case factors are all examples of the achievement of a sentencing movement which was, unfortunately, undermined from the start by its own flawed premise and overreaching ambition.
9.276
Appealing though it is, the notion of structured sentencing starting points of the Finnish type, laid out in a form not dissimiliar to a guidelines matrix, is not without its pitfalls. First, there is always the danger that the starting points could become presumptive in practice, which only a vigilant appellate court can prevent. Alternatively, they may be considered by judges to be presumptuous, and rejected outright.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=296 |
9.277
Secondly, there is the question of how such starting points are to be compiled. The merits and drawbacks of the Finnish and Victorian models have been rehearsed above, and it is not yet possible to reach even a tentative conclusion.
9.278
It may be that a less structured approach should be favoured. Doob and Park's sentencing information system performs no preliminary steps for the judge, save to marshall in a simple format an account of past disposals in apparently similar cases. The presentation of sentence distributions in cases which are broadly comparable is all the information needed if one conceives of judicial sentencing decision-making as a process of intuitive synthesis. A combination of a coherent sentencing policy, appellate guidance and relevant information may be sufficient in a small jurisdiction like Ireland to ensure that judicial discretion is exercised in an informed and consistent manner. Also, it may be preferred by those who operate and work in the criminal justice system to the more apparently dirigiste options canvassed above. We reserve judgment for the moment.
9.279
Structured starting points are not dissimilar in conception to advisory sentencing guidelines, such as were introduced, with little success, in New York. Advisory guidelines also consist of highly structured information on current trends in sentencing. Wilkins offers the following definition:
The term 'guideline', as we use it ... refers to a system of data which functions as a tool in assisting decision-makers in arriving at individual and policy determinations.330 |
9.280
It is not clear how similar in detail the advisory guidelines designed by Wilkins et al are to the starting point models already discussed. Certainly, their statistical bases must be quite different, which could be at least as important as their shared assumption that judicial knowledge of actual sentencing patterns will lead judges to follow them in the majority of cases (a trend which in any event we hope will not become too automatic or uncritical).
9.281
Advisory guidelines have been concluded elsewhere to have been a failure. The Panel on Sentencing Research of the US National Research Council stated in its Report that formal compliance with voluntary/descriptive guidelines has apparently been limited in the jurisdictions studied.331
9.282
Critics' concern with formal compliance may be misplaced, however it has been remarked on several occasions already that considerable disparity could be masked by almost universal adherence to sentencing guidelines. Also, one
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=297 |
must be mindful of the context into which a system of guidance is inserted. It will be remembered that Doob and Park attributed the failure of their programme largely to the lack of a coherent sentencing policy. There is an almost imperceptible but very material difference between advisory guidelines and starting points in respect of how they operationalise sentencing policy. Even with advisory guidelines, there is some level of presumption that the ordained sentencing ranges will be appropriate in most cases.
9.283
This is betrayed by the tendency to gauge success or failure by reference to levels of compliance. It is envisaged that in a starting points system, whether structured or intuitive, the primary reference point for judges will be sentencing policy any information provided quantitative or qualitative, is only an aid to its application in given circumstances. This strikes us as an important difference in emphasis.
9.284
The Canadian Sentencing Commission resolved to recommend against the adoption of advisory sentencing guidelines, wishing to avoid the mistake of importing into Canada a solution which has failed elsewhere.332 Ours is the reverse approach. We do not wish to impose on judges the levels of constraint associated with presumptive sentencing guidelines, whose success is at the very least uncertain. With judges' cooperation, similar goals of consistency and proportionality in sentencing may be achieved by a system which seeks to inform and guide rather than to restrain and curtail judicial sentencing discretion.
9.285
A number of problems associated with sentencing guidance by the Court of Criminal Appeal have already been highlighted.333 It seems likely, however, that these are not insurmountable. The obstacle of lop-sided case-loads can be overcome by permitting prosecution appeal against sentence.334 That appeals must be decided, and guidance given, on an individual and case-by-case basis is less problematical within a starting point system with a legislatively ordained, coherent sentencing policy. First, a judge sentencing a case whose circumstances have not been addressed by appellate review is not left without guidance -the policy, the list of aggravating and mitigating factors, and the summary of past (or ideal) sentencing practice which the starting points or data base embody, should all help him reach principled decisions. Secondly, these resources are all available to the appellate court as it attempts to formulate qualitative guidance for the courts below while deciding the cases before it. It is hoped that Irish superior courts will adopt the practice of handing down guideline judgments which go beyond the circumstances of the particular case they hear on appeal, to give their views on how judges can remain consistent with principle while sentencing for other, dissimilar instances of the same offence. If sufficiently specific, some means could be found to embody the substance of such guideline judgments in sentencing starting points, if these are favoured; alternatively, they could constitute a resource of qualitative guidance for judges in assessing how to
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=298 |
use the starting points and to conform to sentencing policy in the actual cases they decide. As was adverted to above, the means of dissemination of such appellate guidance would need to be greatly upgraded.335
9.286
It is now possible to reach some conclusions on the diverse subject matter of the foregoing chapter. These conclusions are summarised by the following provisional recommendations; it will be clear, however, that even an interim decision has been deemed unwise on some matters.
9.287
We provisionally recommend that a determinate sentencing scheme not be adopted in this jurisdiction.336
9.288
We provisionally recommend that a scheme of presumptive sentencing guidelines not be adopted in this jurisdiction.
9.289
We provisionally recommend the formulation of a scheme for the provision of quantitative sentencing information to judges, in the context of a coherent sentencing policy and of sentencing guidance by appellate courts; such information to be compiled over a period after the legislative introduction of a statement of sentencing policy. Information should be provided on sentences resulting from different combinations of material case factors.
9.290
We seek views on the design of a sentencing information system. Issues include whether the chosen material factors by which cases are compared should be objectively or subjectively defined; whether a descriptive or quasi-descriptive approach should be adopted; and whether the information compiled should be presented merely in the form of sentence distributions, or in the form of advisory starting points.
9.291
We seek views on the most appropriate method of compiling quantitative statistical sentencing information or guidance in respect of less serious offences.337
9.292
We provisionally recommend the continued supervision of sentencing practice, and the provision of sentencing guidance, by the appellate courts, in accordance with the proposed legislative statement of sentencing policy.
9.293
We provisionally recommend that the appellate courts resort to guideline judgments when presented by cases before them with a suitable opportunity to provide more general guidance on the application of sentencing policy to particular offences.
9.294
We seek views on how such qualitative sentencing data can be better communicated to sentencing judges.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=299 |
10.1
The traditional legislative practice of prescribing maximum penalties has been lauded by some as being the best method of distributing sentencing power between the legislature and the courts:
The prescription of a maximum sentence at the legislative level has three conspicuous advantages: it indicates to the subordinate sentencing authorities [i.e. the courts] the degree of seriousness with which the legislature, on behalf of the public at large, regards the offence; by its indefinite character up to that maximum it leaves flexibility and discretion to the subordinate sentencing authorities in their disposition of particular cases; and it protects the interests of the offender himself by setting a limit to restrictions on his liberty or freedom of action beyond which the subordinate sentencing authorities cannot go.1 |
10.2
However, a problem that has developed in all jurisdictions which have adopted this approach is that so often statutory maxima bear no relationship whatever to everyday sentences imposed. The Canadian Commission found that:2
It seems fair to say that the maximum penalties as they currently stand have little impact upon the sentences handed down by judges and only serve to confuse the public. |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=300 |
10.3
The Victorian Sentencing Committee noted a similar trend.3
Even a cursory examination of the Irish Annual Reports on Prisons and Places of Detention will indicate a similar trend here. For example, although the maximum penalty for burglary is 14 years' imprisonment,4 27% of those imprisoned for burglary in 1988 received sentences of between one and two years, and 35% received sentences of between two and three years. Less than 10% received sentences between five and ten years, whilst no sentence exceeded ten years in length.5
10.4
A second point of concern is the fact that there appears to be no logical or rational basis upon which maximum penalties are set by the legislature, other than by reference to existing sentences for other offences. Many of the maximum sentences which pertain to modern sentencing were set over a hundred years ago, and probably reflect a different view of the severity of crimes to that held today.
10.5
Thus, beyond having a doubtful deterrent6 effect, it is difficult to see why maximum penalties should be so high.
10.6
This begs the question of whether maximum penalties really do indicate to the subordinate sentencing authorities the degree of seriousness with which the legislature, on behalf of the public at large, regards the offence. If penalties were graded in severity so as to reflect gradations in relative seriousness of conduct, offences carrying the same maximum penalty should reflect a similar level of seriousness. Instead, one finds, for example, that the maximum penalty for blackmail7 is the same as that for murder i.e. life imprisonment.8 One would also expect to find that offences which were more serious would carry higher maximum sentences yet the maximum penalty for failure to produce books under the Companies Acts is 3 years imprisonment;9 although the more serious offence of abduction of a girl under sixteen has a maximum of only 2 years.10 Meanwhile, clipping or impairing silver coins carries a maximum term of 14 years penal servitude.11 The crux is that the current maxima do not accurately reflect society's views on offence seriousness (although constantly the courts rely on them as the principal criteria for determining offence seriousness when considering the minor/non-minor offence distinction)12; so a crime intended to be dealt with severely by the legislature may be dealt with leniently and vice versa. At the same time the current maxima do little more than confuse the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=301 |
public and give them the impression that the law treats, say, child abductors, more leniently than counterfeiters (which it does).
10.7
A third cause for concern is the primary emphasis of the current maxima on lengthy custodial sentences. They do not reflect the development of community sanctions. Far from reflecting the attitude that imprisonment is a sanction of last resort,13 the current maxima may even have the effect of promoting reliance on imprisonment.
10.8
We feel that there is much to be said in favour of a review of the set of statutory maxima that exists in Ireland. Current levels should be rescaled in line with modern perspective. This would have the advantage of at once both providing the courts with a useful reference point for gauging the relative seriousness of an offence against other offences and indicating to the public that the penalties which attach to offending conduct should be proportionate to the seriousness of the conduct.
10.9
In the course of our research we found the following twenty levels to represent the current set of maxima for conviction upon indictment; they are set out with some random examples of the crimes which carry them:14
(1) |
Penal Servitude for Life |
Stopping a mail with intent (s50(d), Post Office Act, 1908); Abortion (s58, Offences Against the Person Act, 1861) |
(2) |
Life imprisonment |
Rape, Aggravated sexual assault, (Criminal Law (Rape) (Amendment) Act, 1990, s3); Robbery (Larceny Act, 1916, s23, as amended) |
(3) |
20 years imprisonment |
Causing explosions likely to endanger life or property (s2, Explosive Substances Act, 1883, as amended); Usurpation of functions of Government (s6(1), Offences Against the State Act, 1939, as amended) |
(4) |
15 years imprisonment |
Carrying out unauthorised military exercises, (Offences Against the State Act, 1939 s6(1), as amended); Unlawful seizure of a ship (Criminal Law Jurisdiction Act, 1976, s10) |
(5) |
14 years penal servitude |
Forgery of title deeds (s2(2), Forgery Act, 1913); Killing an animal with intent to steal (s4, Larceny Act, 1916) |
(6) |
14 years imprisonment |
Forging a drug prescription (Misuse of Drugs Act, 1977, ss6, 7, 27(2); Carrying firearms with criminal intent (Firearms Act, 1964, s27(b), as amended by s14, Criminal Justice Act, 1984) |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=302 |
(7) |
10 years penal servitude |
Threatening to damage property (s3, Criminal Damage Act, 1991): Poisoning with intent to endanger life (s23, Offences Against the Persons Act, 1861) |
(8) |
10 years imprisonment |
Aiding an escape from lawful Custody (Criminal Law Act, 1976, s6(1)) |
(9) |
7 years penal servitude |
Counterfeiting copper coins (Coinage Act, 1861, s14, as amended); Abduction of a child under 14 (s56, Offences Against the Person Act, 1861) |
(10) |
7 years imprisonment |
Possession of a controlled drug other than cannabis (ss3, 27(1)(b), Misuse of Drugs Act, 1977, as amended); Membership of an unlawful organisation (s21, Offences Against the State Act, 1939, as amended) |
(11) |
5 years penal servitude |
Misprison of treason (Treason Act, 1939, s2); Simple Larceny (s2, Larceny Act, 1916) |
(12) |
5 years imprisonment |
Making false reports (Criminal Law Act, 1976, s12); Sexual Assault (s2, Criminal Law (Rape) (Amendment) Act, 1990) |
(13) |
3 years penal servitude |
Personation (second offence) at an election (Prevention of Electoral Abuses Act, 1923, s6(2)) |
(14) |
3 years imprisonment |
Unauthorised raising of funds for Credit Union (Industrial and Provident Societies (Amendment) Act, 1978, ss5, 28); False statement as to qualification to purchase land (Land Act, 1965, s45(6)) |
(15) |
2 years imprisonment |
Forgery of Vocational Education Certificate (Vocational Education Act, 1930, s121); Causing bodily harm by furious driving (Offences Against the Person Act, 1861, s35) |
(16) |
18 months imprisonment |
Theft of or possession of stolen dogs after previous conviction (Larceny Act, 1916, s5) |
(17) |
12 months imprisonment |
Malicious publication of a libel (Defamation Act, 1961, s11); Obstructing Court Officers (Enforcement of Court Orders Act, 1926, s24) |
(18) |
6 months imprisonment |
Unauthorised occasional trading (Occasional Trading Act, 1979, ss3(1), 9(1)); Keeping a brothel (Criminal Law (Amendment) Act, 1935, s13) |
(19) |
3 months imprisonment |
Interfering with a witness at a public inquiry (Witness (Public Inquiries) Act, 1892, s1); Dredging for Oysters (Larceny Act, 1861, s13) |
(20) |
1 month imprisonment |
Summary conviction for broadcasting indecent |
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=303 |
|
|
messages (Wireless Telegraphy Act, 1926, s11) |
10.10
We feel that the current set of 20 maxima or 14 if penal servitude is abolished is too great, and we believe that in reviewing maximum penalties the legislature should adopt a more limited set. Six to eight levels would be sufficient, depending on the level chosen for the ceiling (i.e. highest maximum). The provision of a smaller set has a number of conspicuous advantages. First, it would provide clearer definition and better differentiation between crimes in terms of their gravity because a smaller set means a sufficiently large interval between the steps on the scale. Secondly, as the Australian Law Reform Commission15 correctly points out, the wider interval would require the legislature to focus attention more carefully on the gravity of the offence in question when setting the maximum. Thirdly, adopting a smaller set would make the system less unwieldy.16
10.11
When choosing the appropriate maximum we would expect it to reflect contemporary views of seriousness and current sentencing practice. However, we would also encourage a concerted effort to reduce the emphasis on imprisonment by keeping sentence lengths to the minimum necessary to reflect offence seriousness.
10.12
The response to this situation in other jurisdictions has been to rescale maximum penalties in particular, maximum custodial penalties to bring them in line with modern perspectives on the seriousness of offences. The trend has been towards a reduced set of maximum penalties and a lesser emphasis on custody.
10.13
In England and Wales, the Advisory Council on the Penal System produced its report Sentences of Imprisonment: A Review of Maximum Penalties in 1978. The Council examined the sentences imposed by the courts in the years 1974 to 1976, and set a proposed level of maxima at the point where 90% of sentences were imposed. The effect of this was, for example in the case of burglary, to reduce the new maximum from 14 years to 3 years. The choice of 90% as the appropriate level was, upon the council's own admission, to some extent arbitrary17 but it felt that the other 10% would represent the common conception of the level at which an exceptional sentences would be warranted. But it was the Council's proposals on how this 10% should be dealt with, i.e. that the courts should be empowered to impose a determinate sentence of any length on an exceptional offender, which led to objection.18 This would have allowed
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=304 |
the courts an unfettered discretion to escalate the penalty to anything they considered appropriate despite parliament setting a maximum penalty. In effect, this provision defeated the purpose of the other proposals, and as a result, the Council's recommendations are reportedly gathering dust on the shelves of the Home Office.19
10.14
The Canadian Sentencing Commission also undertook a re-ordering of their maximum penalties.20 The Commission reviewed all the offences as they appeared on the statutes and sought to make the maximum penalty structure reflect, to a greater degree, current sentencing practice. In order to do so, the Commission obtained an aggregate sentence breakdown21 of all federal offenders. Examination of the most severe sentence imposed upon these individuals revealed that the average single longest sentence was 12 years. The average single sentence was substantially lower than the most severe maximum provided by the Code. The Commission concluded:22
Having considered the data on the length of time actually served in custody by long-term offenders and in consideration of other aspects of our sentencing proposals, the Commission concluded that 12 years in prison should be the maximum sentence to be imposed for a single offence in all but the most exceptional cases. In recognition that there are particular cases that require exceptional sentences, there is a procedure of enchancement of the sentence ... For offences other than murder and high treason, the Commission recommends that the current penalty structure be repealed and replaced by the following penalty structure:
Once the ceiling was set at 12 years, the Commission decided that intervals of three years would provide the necessary flexibility and differentiation between the levels of maxima in the upper ranges. It was felt necessary to retain the lowest band of six months, as one year was |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=305 |
perceived to be excessive for the least serious group of offences which comprise the bulk of the criminal court workload. |
10.15
Strangely (considering the Commission's own findings on the reliability of incapacitative sentencing),23 the Commission proposed an exceptional sentence scheme to accommodate the fewer than 1% of cases where the judge feels that, in the interest of public security, a custodial term longer than the maximum penalty period is necessary.24 The criteria recommended by the Commission for the enhancement of sentences were:25
|
10.16
The Commission attached a great number of procedural safeguards to the proposed system, such as giving the accused a forewarning of an application for enhanced sentence; requiring the consent of the Attorney General; requiring a pre-sentence report and placing the burden of proof of all the criteria upon the prosecution.26
10.17
It appears that no legislative steps have been taken on the Commission's proposals as to maximum penalties to date.27
10.18
The Australian Law Reform Commission, too, observed that the existing maxima in Australian jurisdictions were not set by reference to a uniform scheme, and proposed a new system of maxima based on different categories of offence, ranked according to seriousness.28 This ranking would take into account both public perception and sentencing practice. The Commission tentatively proposed eight categories of offences, A to H, ranging from life imprisonment in category A, reserved only for murder, to fixed monetary penalties in category H for parking violations and minor tax and customs matters:29
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=306 |
Category A should only contain the offence of murder punishable by a maximum penalty of life imprisonment.
Category B offences should have a maximum penalty of 15 years imprisonment. This category should only extend to offences regarded as extremely serious by the community, such as complicity in or conspiracy to murder, manslaughter and extremely serious forms of drug trafficking.
Category C offences should carry a maximum of 10 years imprisonment. Offences in this category might include armed robbery, hijacking aircraft, aggravated sexual assault, assault intentionally occasioning grievous bodily harm, kidnapping and other offences against the person involving acts endangering life.
Category D offences should carry a maximum of five years imprisonment and include breaking, entering and stealing, serious fraud or misappropriation, arson and driving causing death.
Category E offences should have a maximum penalty of two years imprisonment. This category might include theft, receiving, unlawful possession of stolen goods and reckless driving.
Category F offences should have a maximum of six months imprisonment and could include gaming and betting, theft under $1,000, escape from custody and indecent acts.
For Category G offences imprisonment should not be available as a penalty. This category should cover all offences not specifically allocated to other categories.
Category H offences should carry fixed monetary penalties dealt with on an infringement notice basis such as parking violations and minor tax and customs matters.
10.19
The Commission admitted that assigning the maximum penalty to an offence is ultimately a matter for the legislature. However it recommended that the parliament would adopt the eight categories and select the maximum penalty for a particular offence from that set of maximum terms.30 In making the choice of category, the following would have to be borne in mind: the principle that imprisonment is a sanction of last resort; the fact that, in general, offences which impinge upon personal security are considered more serious than offences which infringe the security of property. There should be a deliberate effort to ensure that offences for which the same maximum prison term is prescribed are of the same comparative seriousness.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=307 |
10.20
The Victorian Sentencing Committee also reviewed the state of maximum sentences in its jurisdiction.31 In its opinion the highest maximum sentence should be life imprisonment, but below that, the next most severe would be 12 years based on the fact that, taking parole and remission into account, a person would have to be sentenced to 18 1/2 years to actually serve 12. Since the Committee proposed the abolition of remission, 12 years was a suitable maximum. A three year interval for other maxima in descending order of severity resulted in this scale:32
life imprisonment
12 years
9 years
6 years
3 years
12 months
6 months
10.21
The Committee set out a table of proposed maxima to facilitate the implementation of its proposals. The criteria upon which the review were based included the reduction of the emphasis on imprisonment as a remedy, the contemporary views as to the seriousness of offences, and the rejection of incapacitative strategies.33
10.22
We provisionally recommend that the legislature undertake a review of the set of maximum penalties which currently exists in Ireland, and re-scales the levels in accordance with modern perspectives on offence seriousness and in accordance with the view that custodial sentences should be regarded as sanctions of the last resort. We provisionally recommend that the set of maximum penalties be diminished -between six and eight levels of maximum penalty would be sufficient.
10.23
Objection can be taken to the laying down of statutory minima on the grounds that:
there can be no rule of general application laying down a specific quantum of punishment that should be inflicted in the case of a particular offence.34 |
10.24
The advantages of minimum sentences are not clear, although a common
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=308 |
theme in their imposition both at home and abroad has been the belief that the legislative pronouncement of a minimum will lead to sentences having a deterrent effect.35
10.25
The Canadian Law Reform Commission concluded:36
While there are no available objective measurements on the effectiveness of such sanctions, experience does not show that they have any obvious special deterrent or educative effect. Generally, the reported research does not show that harsh sanctions are more effective than less severe sanctions in preventing crime. Other problems arise in denying judges discretion to select the appropriate sanction or the length of a prison term in individual cases. For one thing circumstances vary so greatly from case to case that an arbitrary minimum may be seen as excessive denunciation or an excessively long period of separation in the light of the risk and all the circumstances. Indeed, not every case falling within a given offence will require imprisonment for the purposes of isolation. Similar criticisms could be made of a sentencing provision that denies judges the power to choose between a custodial and a non-custodial sentence. |
10.26
The major disadvantages of minimum sentences, therefore, are that they may, on occasion, preclude the sentencer from imposing a sentence proportionate to the seriousness of the offending behaviour, while at the same time there is no clear evidence that minimum sentences serve any useful purpose at all. Any minimum sentences which are still in operation are, generally, a relic of by-gone days.
10.27
We provisionally recommend that the legislature refrains from the introduction of minimum sentences in the future, and that those still in force be abolished.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=309 |
10.28
Mandatory sentences are rare in Ireland,37 and those that are operative can be criticised on the basis that:
it is impossible at the legislative level to foresee and provide in adequate detail either for the multitudinous variety of circumstances under which serious crimes are committed or for the sometimes considerable differences of personality, background and intelligence between people who commit them. What is virtually certain is that legislatively imposed fixed penalties for serious crimes will require the frequent intervention of executive clemency.38 |
10.29
That has been the experience in Ireland in relation to the mandatory life sentence, for which the Government, acting through the Minister for Justice, determines when the prisoner should be released. There is now a well established policy at the post-judicial stage of sentencing that a life sentence is not to be taken literally.39 In the case of a life sentence, the discretion as to the duration of the term is shifted to the executive under Article 13.6 of the Constitution which provides:
The right of pardon and the power to commute or remit punishment imposed by any court exercising criminal jurisdiction are hereby vested in the President, but such power of commutation or remission may, except in capital cases, also be conferred by law on other authorities. |
10.30
Such power was conferred on the Government, and the Minister for Justice, by section 23 of the Criminal Justice Act, 1951. The result is that a life sentence is in practice an indeterminate40 sentence, because the offender does not know when he or she will be released, or if he or she will ever be released; however the average lifer can expect to be released within 8 to 10 years.41 According to official statistics,42 the following were periods actually served by 26 prisoners serving life sentences for offences including murder:
Less than 5 years: None;
More than 5 years, but less than 8 years: 11;
More than 8 years, but less than 10 years: 8;
More than 10 years, but less than 12 years: 5;
More than 12 years, but less than 15 years: None;
More than 15 years: 2.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=310 |
10.31
Secondly, although there is no case directly in point, it is not inconceivable that the lack of judicial participation in the determining of a mandatory sentence could amount to a breach of some notion of fair procedures, in some, if not all, cases. Does not the individual citizen, to use O'Dalaigh CJ's words,43 need the safeguard of the courts as much in the assessment of punishment for crimes which carry mandatory sentences as for others?
10.32
The right of the accused to have the matter tried by an independent court or arbitrator as established in The State (Healy) v Donoghue44 could be read to require judicial participation. What is at stake is the requirement of audi alteram partem which Davitt P in The State (Howard) v Donnelly45 found to be an essential of justice. In Howard the District Judge acted in excess of his jurisdiction in refusing to hear evidence likely to influence him to acquit the accused. At the sentencing stage, mandatory sentences deprive judges of the opportunity to hear evidence which might lead to mitigation; and thus possibly breach the audi alteram requirement.46 As against that, it can equally be said that in the case of offences warranting a sentence of life imprisonment, it is not unreasonable for the legislature to decide that there was no alteram partem to be heard on sentence.
10.33
In relation to murder, the objection has been fuelled in some jurisdictions by the anomalous felony murder rule. This anachronism is an attenuation of the ancient common law rule that anyone who kills in the course of commission of a felony is, in effect, strictly liable as a murderer. Time and again it has been argued that it is unjust to sentence on the basis of the offender's imputed, as
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=311 |
opposed to actual, state of mind. The Victorian Law Reform Commission commented that:47
... the fundamental objection, applicable to all doctrines of constructive murder, [is] that they offend against basic concepts of justice, because they subject persons to the severest of punishments for consequences of their acts which they in no way intend. |
10.34
Apart from revenue and excise offences and offences under the Customs Acts, there do not appear to be many offences in respect of which only one penalty may be imposed murder, capital murder and treason immediately come to mind.48 Other jurisdictions have reconsidered the place of mandatory sentences, in particular the mandatory life sentence for murder, in the sentencing process. The abolition of 'ordinary' mandatory sentences has posed no problem; however enormous controversy has surrounded moves to abolish the mandatory life sentence for murder.
10.35
The 11 member Select Committee of the House of Lords in its recent report49 recommended that the mandatory sentence of life imprisonment be abolished in regard to murder, and the sentence be left at the discretion of the court. The New South Wales Legislature abolished the mandatory nature of the life sentence for murder in 198250 as did that of Victoria in 1986.51 Both questioned the appropriateness of the time to be served by a murderer being determined in private by the Executive rather than in open court by a judge.52
10.36
A recurring issue was the general deterrent argument that a mandatory life sentence deters potential killers. There could be found no evidence of this effect, and certainly no evidence that any deterrent effect of a mandatory life sentence would be any greater than that of a maximum but discretionary life sentence.53 In the Australian State of Victoria, where the life sentence became discretionary in 1986, there has been no increase in homicide.54 Similarly the incapacitative element of life sentences was found to provide no greater public protection even though it is true that life prisoners remain on licence for life even after release. Murderers were found to present no special dangers to the public upon release, and persons convicted of other offences may present greater risks.55
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=312 |
10.37
Thirdly, the central objection to the mandatory life sentence for murder is, as Finlay CJ and the majority of the Supreme Court noted in The People (DPP) v Conroy (No 2),56 that some forms of murder are more serious than others, and some manslaughter may even be more serious than some murders:
there would not appear to me to be any grounds for a general presumption that the crime of manslaughter may not, having regard to its individual facts and particular circumstances be in many instances, from a sentencing point of view, as serious as, or more serious than, the crime of murder.57 |
10.38
In New South Wales much of the impetus behind the reform was provided by the public outrage at the life sentences received by Violet and Bruce Roberts, a mother and son who had murdered their husband and father Eric Roberts who had brutally terrorised and beaten them for years.58 The mandatory life sentence, it was felt, gave too much emphasis to the crime and not enough to the criminal.
10.39
One problem which faced reformers was the question of what should replace the mandatory life sentence. If the judge is given discretion, then there is little to distinguish murder from manslaughter. In order to maintain the public perception that murder is dealt with more severely than manslaughter the New South Wales Legislature gave the presiding judge a restricted sentencing discretion in murder cases rather than the unrestricted discretion for manslaughter.59 In England, the Select Committee recommended only that the judge specify reasons for selecting the sentence and to specify in open court the period of years necessary to satisfy the requirements of retribution and deterrence,60 but in that jurisdiction, there is still debate as to whether the law should continue with the murder/manslaughter dichotomy.
10.40
In the British House of Lords during April, 1991, there was an overwhelming majority vote of 177 to 79 in favour of abolishing the mandatory life sentence61 which is hardly surprising considering the recommendations of the House of Lords' select committee. A second vote, also carried by a 2 to 1 majority, was in favour of requiring the judge to state the penal term (i.e. the term proportionate to the seriousness of the offence and not any extra time which may be necessary for the protection of the public) if and when a discretionary life
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=313 |
sentence is imposed. The final group of amendments authorised the establishment of a judicial tribunal to determine the time of release of life-prisoners once the penal term has expired. In the case of murderers, they would always remain on licence for life even after release. Seven principal arguments for abolition were put; Ashworth summarises:62
|
10.41
The House of Commons, however, voted down the peers' proposals, by 236 votes to 158, at the instigation of the Home Secretary, Kenneth Baker. The turning point in the debate seems to have been the issue of who should decide when to release a life-prisoner rather than the question of whether mandatory sentences serve any useful purpose. Mr Baker said:
The best and fairest system is the one we have now where the life sentence is fixed by law and the responsibility then passes to the Home Secretary to decide how the sentence should be spent. That responsibility is part of the Home Secretary's general responsibility for the protection of the public, the preservation of the Queen's peace and the maintenance of public confidence in the criminal justice system.63 |
10.42
Amongst the arguments advanced in favour of retention was a direct rebuttal of point (vii) above, says Ashworth:
It was argued that the judges do not have experience of passing sentence for murder, and it was asked whether judges in this country would be comfortable with passing sentences of up to 60 years and possibly longer. Powerful as the arguments for abolishing the mandatory sentence are, this practical aspect of 'what exactly happens next' has never been described fully by the abolitionists.64 |
10.43
The chief argument in favour of the sentence rested on public confidence. Lord Waddington, upon reflection, said:
The criminal law has always reflected public attitudes. The public in general do feel that the mandatory sentence is appropriate to mark the heinous crime of murder out from all other crimes and that public opinion has to be listened to.65 |
10.44
Surprisingly, nobody appears to have conducted a public opinion poll to see if this is true.
10.45
In July, the peers responded with a defeat of the government's proposals,66 re-iterating the proposals that an independent body or parole board should have the right to review life sentences and that the judge should state the penal term. Two more votes removed the Home Secretary's power to delay the release of a prisoner on licence after a parole board decision.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=315 |
10.46
However the peers decided not to press for the ending of the mandatory life sentence because of fears that the whole bill67 might lapse. Lord Hailsham remarked:
One day people will see sense, even in the House of Commons, and the hairy heel of populism which they have followed will ultimately disappear. But in the meantime there is no great crisis if the status quo is preserved. We should allow them to have their silly way for once.68 |
10.47
The mandatory life sentence was introduced as a compromise when capital punishment was abolished in England, because it was felt that discretionary sentencing would be too lenient an alternative to hanging. Now that attitudes have changed and life imprisonment is the gravest penalty in the criminal justice system, it may be suggested that it in turn be replaced by a discretionary sentence. History shows that mandatory transportation, which in the 1800s was introduced to replace mandatory death for felony offences, was quickly replaced itself by discretionary penalties within the space of a few decades.69
10.48
It may now be time for this pattern of history to repeat itself. Already the European Court of Human Rights has decided in the recent case of Thynne, Wilson and Gunnell70 that prisoners serving discretionary life sentences have the right to regular and open judicial review of their sentences under articles 5 & 4 of the European Convention on Human Rights.71 Thus the discretion as to extent of sentence for life prisoners has been handed back to the judiciary where the life sentence was discretionary. The court noted that the discretionary life sentence differed from the mandatory life sentence, since the former is imposed with incapacitation and protection of the public in mind, while the mandatory life sentence is imposed on deterrent grounds. It is suggested that this distinction promotes the case against mandatory life sentences because those sentenced to a mandatory life sentence usually pose a lesser threat to the public upon release. Consequently, it may be concluded that mandatory life-prisoners should also have the right to regular judicial review of their sentences.72
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=316 |
10.49
At this stage, let us outline some of the options for reform which have been considered in other jurisdictions which might, at some stage, be relied on to reform this difficult area of penal policy.
10.50
In Hyam v DPP73 Lord Kilbrandon said:
My Lords, it is not easy to feel satisfaction at the doubts and difficulties which seem to surround the crime of murder and the distinguishing from it of the crime of such manslaughter. There is something wrong when crimes of such gravity, and I will say of such familiarity, call for the display of so formidable a degree of forensic and judicial learning as the present case has given rise to. I believe this to show that a more radical look at the problem is called for, and was called for immediately on the passing of the Murder (Abolition of Death Penalty) Act, 1965. Until that time the content of murder and I am not talking about the definition of murder was that form of homicide which is punishable with death. (It is not necessary to notice the experimental period during which capital murder and non-capital murder existed side-by-side). Since no homicides are now punishable with death, these many hours and days have been occupied in trying to adjust a definition of that which has no content. There does not appear to be any good reason why the crimes of murder and manslaughter should not both be abolished, and the single crime of unlawful homicide be substituted; one case will differ from another in gravity, and that can be taken care of by variation in sentences downwards from life imprisonment. |
10.51
Lord Kilbrandon suggests that the distinction between manslaughter and murder be abolished, and that the sentence for the new crime of unlawful homicide be imposed at the discretion of the trial judge. However, the chief objection to this course of action is that the present difference in labels has a declaratory and symbolic function. The New South Wales' legislature rejected such radical reform on the grounds that it would be unpalatable to the public:
In our culture, to describe someone as a 'murderer' is to employ the most bitterly and effectively stigmatising epithet available in the language. To remove that term from the law would be to risk possible public misapprehension and to invite the criticism (rightly or wrongly) that the moral force of the law was being lessened.74 |
10.52
It is unlikely, therefore, that this approach would be favoured by the legislature charged with the representation of public opinion, although logical and
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=317 |
reasonable to the judge, academic, or law reformer.
10.53
This was an option which was discounted in New South Wales. The idea was that various degrees of murder should be stipulated, and various maximum penalties set for each, somewhat along the lines of the US system so popular in television drama. The sentencer would then exercise his or her sentencing discretion in imposing the appropriate sentence within the limits of the maximum for that degree of murder. The main objection is that enormous difficulties would be encountered in drafting a provision which would satisfactorily demarcate differing degrees of murder.75 Another problem is that an offender could get off on a technicality if not charged with murder in the correct degree. In New South Wales is was argued that the inclusion of murder by intent to kill in first-degree murder (which it would be anomalous to exclude from the category of first-degree murder) would result in a first-degree sentence in the case of domestic killings, and this would have negated an important aim of the intended reform to allow a sentencing discretion in relation to domestic killings.76
10.54
Another option is to simply provide for a discretionary sentence for murder in exactly the same manner as for manslaughter, but retaining the different labels for the crimes. The House of Lords' Select Committee felt that such a move could lead to confusion and the ultimate diminishing of the primary function of the qualified defences, such as provocation and diminished responsibility, to murder. The Committee argued that it is proper to allow qualified defences which reduce the crime to manslaughter when the offence in question is murder, although for other crimes the same factors would simply go to mitigation, because murder is the highest offence and only the most heinous offences should be so classified.77Thomas argues to the contrary, saying that factors such as provocation and diminished responsibility vary in degrees, so it is artificial and arbitrary to draw a line between provocations which operate as qualified defences and provocations which simply go to mitigation.78 He maintains that such varying degrees are better left for consideration to the sentencing stage where a judge will decide their strength rather than at the trial stage where a jury will make the decisions. Ashworth comments, however, that Thomas' views ignore the argument that juries and the wider public expect the grosser forms of mitigation (e.g. provocation) to be reflected in a lesser verdict than murder.79
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=318 |
10.55
Another objection to unrestricted discretion is that it would permit the possibility of sentencers prescribing sentences of thirty, forty of even fifty years, if American experience is anything to go by. Glanville Williams remarks:
Murders often arouse strong emotion, and if a judge were allowed to sentence to any fixed term he might sometimes specify a very long one, such as 30 or 40 years. If an offender has to be kept in prison for a long time it is probably better that the sentence should be indeterminate, in order that it can be reviewed periodically in a state of detachment.80 |
10.56
A fourth option, adopted in New South Wales, is to provide sentencers with restricted discretion in the sentencing of murderers. The New South Wales reforms retain the murder/manslaughter distinction and current definitions thereof; retain the maximum penalty of penal servitude for life as the sentencing response which the judge will initially consider; allow restricted discretion to mitigate the penalty in appropriate circumstances; but do not permit the imposition of extraordinarily long sentences.81
10.57
Finally, it should be observed that the objections to mandatory sentences do not carry the same weight in courts of summary jurisdiction (the District Court), since they deal with minor offences. Since minor offences carry much slighter consequences upon conviction than serious crimes, the court requires much less discretion to allow for the particular characteristics of the offender and the offence. Consequently there may be a significant gain in efficiency of enforcement of the law in the case of certain minor offences if the use of mandatory sentences were more widespread. The most obvious example of the effective application of a mandatory sentence for minor offences is the parking ticket scheme. The benefits of such an efficient system have been shared in England with over 250 other road traffic offences by Part III of the Transport Act, 1982.82 Also in England, the case for mandatory sentences in minor offences is enhanced by the adoption of the Magistrates' Association's list of Suggestions for Traffic Offence Penalties, which, although they lack legislative force, set down a scale of fines for different motoring offences by average offenders of average means.83 Whilst there does not appear to be any similar type of provision in Irish legislation, it would appear that there is a tendency for District Judges to establish their own rules of thumb in the absence of a fixed legal scale for the imposition of sentence for some minor offences. Naturally, not all summary offences are necessarily suitable for the application of mandatory scales of sentence, but often there is a good case for doing so.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=319 |
10.58
Because of the generally low level of available fines, the sentencing discretion of District Judges is severely restricted at the moment and much could be achieved immediately by implementing the recommendations in the Commission's Report on the Indexation of Fines84 and bringing fines up to date.
10.59
We have studied already in this paper the various efforts in other jurisdictions to combine reason and fairness in a sentencing policy. In general, the favoured solution is a just deserts approach which takes account of both aggravating and mitigating factors. The mandatory sentence is a blunt instrument which could not be tolerated in any sentencing scheme with the slightest sensitivity to a just deserts approach.
10.60
No doubt, the mandatory sentence has great emotional appeal to the public, as evidenced by the recent debate in the British Parliament.85 But the public need little or no convincing that some murders or rapes are more serious than others. They would or should also be aware of the unreality of the mandatory life sentence for murder in the light of the Minister for Justice's power and practice of earlier release.
10.61
In spite of this awareness, there is continued support for mandatory or minimum sentences as we have seen in the reaction to recent sentences for rape and sexual abuse. This is fuelled by distrust of judges whose sentencing practice is perceived to be preoccupied to such an extent with mitigating factors that the just deserts element, merited in the light of the offences committed, is significantly displaced in the sentences ultimately imposed. This is a particularly galling perception for rape victims who undergo the impersonal ordeal of a rape trial in order to ensure that rapists are seen to get their just deserts. The continuing existence of this perception only goes to underline the importance of securing the primacy of the just deserts approach by statute, with due regard for mitigating factors, at the heart of a new sentencing scheme and of supporting this approach by giving the prosecution the right of appeal against inadequate sentences.
10.62
We provisionally recommend the abolition of mandatory sentences for indictable offences.
10.63
We provisionally recommend that the question of mandatory sentences for minor crimes be examined in more detail with a view to improving the efficiency of the administration of justice in the District Court.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=320 |
11.1
Generally speaking, the greater the restriction which is placed on judicial discretion in sentencing, then the greater is the importance of reliable fact-finding. Current sentencing practice is quite informal or flexible. Particular facts rarely have a formal and predictable sentencing consequence. Under a guidelines system, on the other hand, the resolution of disputed sentencing factors will often have a definite and possibly quite substantial impact on the sentence. Greater formality than presently exists could be expected were a more coherent scheme to be adopted.
11.2
The US Sentencing Commission gives as an example the rule that an offender who causes serious bodily injury in the course of a robbery should receive an upward severity adjustment of 4 levels.1 The sentencing process would be undermined if the 4-level adjustment were made when bodily injury was not serious; or if it was serious, but the adjustment was ignored.2
11.3
The requirements of rigorous and definitive fact-finding procedures must be balanced against the countervailing consideration of workability and administrative efficiency ie. a compromise must be sought between the individual's and the government's interest.3
11.4
A jury, in determining guilt or innocence, may be presented with many complex factual issues, but ultimately, a relatively small number may suffice to be resolved to support conviction. But sentencing can require attention to many more, discrete factual issues, especially in a more structured system, so that a
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=321 |
fact-finding process for sentencing decisions which had all the attributes of a formal trial could consume many times the resources devoted to the resolution of guilt or innocence.4
11.5
Some state guidelines systems seek to evade this problem by permitting very few factual elements to affect the sentence, basing it almost entirely on the literal offence of conviction. However, a superficial uniformity is thereby achieved only at the price of substantively inappropriate sentences in far too many cases. Nonetheless, for this reason (as well as that of complexity of calculation, and the invitation to disparity of having a surfeit of relevant variables), the US Commission tried to focus on a relatively manageable number of frequently-occurring factors. The sentencing factors also tend to be those closely tied to the elements of the offence (e.g. nature of injury, amount of loss) which, as well as being linked to just deserts notions of culpability, also help ensure that evidence relating to them will be adduced in the event of a trial.
11.6
A second feature of the US approach is the provision for factual stipulations to be reached by the parties, subject to court supervision stipulations must be accurate and not misleading, and may not omit or misstate facts. All stipulations are subject to review by the sentencing judge, who will have a pre-sentence report against which to check its accuracy and reasonableness.5 This should, hopefully, limit recourse to fact-bargaining by the parties.6
11.7
In any case, the court is expected to place primary reliance on the pre-sentence report.7 Each party must indicate in advance of the sentencing hearing its position with respect to all relevant sentencing factors.8 This helps frame disputed issues for resolution by the court. A pre-hearing conference is also permissible to further this aim.
11.8
The US Commission did not develop a set of procedural rules for dealing with issues which remain in dispute these were left for development by sentencing courts. Some of the issues which will arise, whether or not a guidelines scheme is adopted, include: When is a sentencing factor reasonably in dispute? To what extent should the formal rules of evidence apply to exclude the kinds of evidence which may be introduced? Which party bears the burden of persuasion (i.e. is it sufficient to prove the asserted factor by a preponderance of the evidence or is a higher degree of certainty required)?9
11.9
In Canada, on the contrary, a legislative provision of sentencing rules and procedures has been favoured. Both the Standing Committee on Justice and the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=322 |
Canadian Sentencing Commission noted how sparse and unevenly applied were fact-finding rules governing the sentencing decision, compared to those in respect of the adjudication of guilt.10 No mere re-enactment of the latter is intended, however. The considerations that apply in protecting the rights of a person presumed to be innocent, that are relevant to the conduct of a trial, will not necessarily apply to the conduct of a sentencing hearing.11 But the offender is still acknowledged to have important procedural rights, and the public has an interest in the sentence imposed complying with the statement of the purpose and principles of sentencing. Therefore, the Canadian Federal Government has proposed a Code of Evidence and Procedure for Sentencing. This will give the offender a right to speak to sentence (failure to offer which can invalidate the sentence).12
11.10
Rules are also set out regarding the burden of proof and the leading of evidence at the sentencing hearing. Both the prosecution and the defence will be asked for submissions on the facts relevant to the sentence, and if disputed, the court is to hear evidence.13 The party adducing such facts must prove their existence beyond a reasonable doubt a standard of proof which may seem too high to those concerned with the administrative burden of a sentencing hearing,14 though it appears to be that also prevailing in Ireland.
11.11
At the same time, the proposed Code is quite lax in allowing (though not, apparently, compelling) the court to accept as proved any facts agreed upon by the prosecutor and the offender.15 This may allow the sort of unsupervised fact-bargaining which is sought to be prevented by the more inquisitorial approach of the US Federal Guidelines. The provision in the same sub-section for the acceptance as proved of all facts essential to the finding of guilt seems unexceptionable. A problem remains, of course, where a jury returns a verdict of guilt whose factual basis is ambiguous.16 The present disapproval of questioning the jury after its verdict seems justified, but the putting of questions to the jury when it retires to consider its verdict may have some merit.17 If such a course is adopted, care should be taken to ensure that the jury is alive to the fact that disagreement on the answer to such questions need not preclude a verdict of guilt.
11.12
In general, it is thought that the provision of rules of procedure would be useful in this jurisdiction, as there is little judicial authority to guide judges.18 These might be a little more comprehensive than those proposed in Canada. In particular, an indication of the degree of applicability, at this stage, of restrictive
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=323 |
rules of evidence (e.g. re: hearsay, corroboration, etc.) would be beneficial, as there is little precedent on the matter.
11.13
The Australian Law Reform Commission notes that in respect of facts considered relevant by the court after conviction, the rules of admissibility are not applied strictly by sentencing courts to evidence adduced to prove those facts.19 To apply such rules, it is suggested, would transform the sentencing hearing into an adversarial proceeding, with increased costs and delays. It might also exclude some useful evidence eg. of remorse, or that the offence was out of character. On the other hand, the Commission is alive to the possibility of decisions being based on inaccurate or unfairly prejudicial material, but ultimately does not recommend the imposition in all cases of exclusionary evidentiary rules where facts relevant to sentence are in dispute.20The reasons for requiring strict proof, by admissible evidence, of all relevant facts not admitted by the other party, do not apply to the sentencing hearing.21
11.14
The Commission is of the view that if a particular factual dispute assumes specific significance, the court's findings should be based on strict proof. It should be for the Court to determine whether a particular fact falls into this category, either on application or of its own motion. In all other instances, of course, decisions as to evidence would still have to be made rationally and fairly.22
11.15
In respect of the burden of proof, the approach, generally adopted in Australia, is that any dispute as to matters beyond the essential ingredients of the offence admitted by the plea must be resolved by ordinary legal principles, including resolving relevant doubt in favour of the accused.23 If there is a dispute as to a fact crucial to the severity of the offence, the standard of proof may be beyond reasonable doubt. Facts of less significance may require a correspondingly lower level of proof. This position is summed up by the Victorian Supreme Court in R v Chamberlain:
It follows that when forming his own view of the facts for the purpose of passing sentence a trial judge cannot be required to be satisfied beyond a reasonable doubt of every fact which he considers relevant. To require a judge to be satisfied beyond reasonable doubt of every relevant fact might lead in some cases to quite undue weight being given to self-serving statements offered by an accused during interrogation or evidence. Moreover, a judge may have to sentence an accused where he does not personally agree with the verdict of the jury. On the other hand, to allow the finding of fact which is critical to the determination of the sentence to be imposed upon a basis that admits of the existence of a reasonable doubt about the existence of that fact would plainly be |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=324 |
unfair. Between those two extremes a large number of possibilities exist.24 |
11.16
The Australian Law Reform Commission makes a proposal similar to that for evidentiary rules: that this proper balance between flexibility and the need, in some circumstances, to prove important and significant facts to a higher standard of proof be maintained, with the judge determining which facts fall into the latter category. It recommends that legislation in the area should do no more than require that the court be satisfied of the relevant facts.25
11.17
There is no clear Irish authority on how factual disputes should be resolved at the sentencing hearing. English precedent suggests that the judge may either reach a conclusion based on counsel's submissions, or hear evidence from both sides (with witnesses, cross-examination, etc.). In the latter case, proof beyond reasonable doubt appears to be necessary, and restrictive evidentiary rules seem to apply. The position is less clear in the former case, but the English decisions state that the benefit of any doubt must be given to the defence.26
11.18
If this is indeed the applicable law in Ireland, it may be comparable to the Australian position save that different procedures as well as (or instead of) differing standards of proof or evidentiary rules apply in respect of factual disputes of greater or less significance. For the moment, we reserve judgment on the desirability of such an arrangement.
11.19
We provisionally recommend the adoption of a code of procedure and evidence for the sentencing hearing, on Canadian lines.
11.20
We provisionally recommend judicial scrutiny of the accuracy and completeness of evidence agreed by both parties at the sentencing hearing, on US lines.
11.21
We seek views on the desirability of applying restrictive and exclusionary rules of evidence to factual disputes at the sentencing hearing.
11.22
We seek views on the most appropriate standard of proof for the resolution of factual disputes at the sentencing hearing.
11.23
There is considerable debate on two issues of evidence and procedure:
|
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=325 |
11.24
As was earlier adverted to, prosecuting counsel must not attempt by advocacy to influence the court in regard to sentence in this jurisdiction,27 and there is English authority, motivated by a similar rule, requiring the prosecution to take care not to depart from factual stipulations when giving evidence of character and antecedents.28
11.25
Zellick has identified five possible roles for prosecuting counsel in the sentencing process, of which that presently prevailing is the most minimal:
|
11.26
There are a number of arguments for the extension of the prosecutorial role into at least some of the fields described immediately above.
|
11.27
Considerable arguments can also be mustered against such an extension of the prosecutorial role.
|
11.28
Evidence of this is afforded by the recent decision of the Northern Ireland Court of Appeal in R v Orr.43 Hutton LCJ, remarked, reducing a sentence in pursuance of two English guideline judgments, that these and other authorities had not been cited to the trial judge:
If he had been assisted in this regard by counsel his Lordship had no doubt that a sentence in the range of three years [rather than the four imposed] would have been imposed. Whilst it was usually inappropriate for counsel to make submissions to a judge as to the length of sentence which he should impose in respect of a common type of offence which comes before him frequently, in an unusual case counsel should carry out research to see whether the Court of Appeal in Northern Ireland or in England had laid down guidelines, and if such guidelines have been laid down counsel should refer the judge to those decisions before he passed sentence.44 |
11.29
Whether this decision will prompt a further relaxation of the prohibition on a wider prosecutorial role in sentencing remains to be seen, though it is quite cautious in its tone.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=328 |
11.30
The jurisdictions in Ireland and Britain are quite unusual in their maintenance of this prohibition. Submissions on sentence are the norm in the USA, and are permitted in Canada.45 The Australian Law Reform Commission has recommended a more active role in the sentencing hearing for prosecution counsel, which it believes can be achieved without compromising their duties to be fair and to assist the court.46 Prosecution submissions on sentence seem also to be common in civil jurisdictions on the continent, and to be an important aid to judges.47
11.31
With the present incoherent state of sentencing principles, an extension of the prosecution's role in the sentencing process seems unlikely to be helpful. If, however, a set of principles were adopted like those proposed elsewhere in this paper, the sentencing decision could more legitimately be considered a domain where legal argument would be constructive. Prosecution and defence could then seek to promote the proper interpretation of sentencing norms and their attendant jurisprudence. Precisely this point is made by the Victorian Sentencing Committee.48 Advocating the introduction of prosecution appeals of sentence, it remarks as follows:
It seems quite absurd that a prosecutor should sit quietly and not make any submissions during the course of a court considering the appropriate sentence to be passed in a particular case, and then turn around and criticise the judge on appeal for failing to take account of various factors or failing to give adequate weight to relevant factors.49 |
11.32
It is not envisaged by that Committee, nor by this Paper, that particular sentences be sought; rather, an opinion might be offered on the range of sentences or nature of the penalty. Prosecutors would assist the court to ensure that the principles of sentencing provided for in legislation were adhered to, by bringing to its attention any relevant facts (as at present), any relevant principles, and any relevant information about sentences passed by other courts.50
We provisionally recommend that prosecution counsel be permitted at the sentencing stage to make submissions to the court not just on the facts of the case, but also on relevant legal principles and precedents. We do not recommend that he or she make specific submissions on the appropriateness of a particular sentence.
11.33
Throughout the last decade there has been a growing interest in how victims of crime are treated by the criminal justice system. Many of the demands for improvement are couched in the language of victims' rights. Historically, in
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=329 |
for improvement are couched in the language of victims' rights. Historically, in common law systems compensation or restitution have not been seen as functions of the criminal law but of the civil law, therefore there is no coherent body of law on victims' rights in the criminal law because the criminal law has not been analysed in those terms. However, it has been frequently observed that the criminal justice system revolves around the offender, that the concerns of victims of crime have been largely ignored and that there is no official recognition of the victim's interest in the prosecution of a defendant.
11.34
These arguments have been made not just by victim support groups and academic lawyers but also by the United States Congress, state legislatures and the Supreme Court.51 What maybe seen as evidence of recognition of the concept of victims' rights in Ireland was the request by the trial judge in The People (D.P.P.) v. Thornberry52 for a victim impact statement prior to sentencing. Further recognition is evidenced by section 5 of the recently introduced Criminal Justice Bill, 1992.
11.35
Three important issues concerning victims in the criminal justice system have emerged:
First, the issue of the victim's right to information about the progress of the case. It has been argued that victims are not always paid the fundamental courtesy by police and prosecutors of being informed of significant events and developments in the prosecution of those cases in which they have a personal and legitimate interest in the outcome. Second, the issue of victim's right to compensation, adequate orders for restitution by the courts and the right to appropriate support services. Third, there is the role, if any, of victims in the sentencing process. The fundamental question here is: to what extent should the impact of a crime on a victim be taken into account when sentencing the offender? |
It is the third issue which we will consider here.
11.36
Formalized victim participation in sentencing is usually through the procedure known as the victim impact statement. Moves have been made in many jurisdictions to introduce this procedure. For example, since 1978, many US states have implemented a wide range of legislation that allows victims a more active role in judicial proceedings. Congress mandated the inclusion of the victim impact statement in federal pre-sentence reports. The relevant section states that the pre-sentence report shall contain:
|
11.37
The various kinds of legislation underpinning victim impact statements differ in two major ways: (a) in the type of information allowed for consideration and (b) in the type of victim participation.
11.38
Four types of information are allowed: (i) the circumstances and manner of the crime (ii) the identity and characteristics of the victim (iii) the effects of the crime on the victim and the victim's family and (iv) the opinion of the victim or the victim's family opinion of the defendant and of the appropriate sentence. The last three form the core of victim participation at sentencing, as the first type of information is normally provided during the trial phase. Advocates of victim participation tend to define the 'circumstances of the crime' somewhat more broadly than do opponents. In general such evidence is similar to that provided by an ordinary witness and thus does not require new legislation.
11.39
With regard to the victim's identity and characteristics, most victim impact statement legislation requires the victim's identity to be included in the statement, but vary in how much additional information is required. Specific characteristics that render the victim particularly vulnerable to the defendant, such as age or handicap, or being in a dependant role in relation to the defendant might be relevant. Some jurisdictions allow information on the victim's background but courts have warned that this might lead to the judge and jury basing their decision unduly on the victim's 'social worth'. Thus, victim impact statements should exclude information going beyond the victim's identity unless it clearly establishes the circumstance of the crime, or is relevant to an aggravating factor.
11.40
With regard to the level of victim harm, the critical issue here is how victim harm should relate to punishment, which in turn raises the question as to whether the consequences of a crime should affect sentencing at all. One view is that the consequences should effect the sentence. Others argue that it is the defendant's frame of mind, or intention that determines guilt and responsibility. For example, a homicide could be intentional, reckless, negligent or innocent. In each case, the harm caused to the victim is the same, but the penal consequences will be different in each case.
11.41
One approach is to ask whether the defendant could reasonably expect such harm to occur as a consequence of his/her acts. Such a question very often
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=331 |
harm suffered by a victim is an unexpected consequence? For example, the 'commonsense' view up until very recently, was that victims of crime 'got over it'. This was, and to some extent is, particularly evident in cases of child sexual abuse since the 'commonsense' view was that children forget things that happen them. It was only by presenting evidence as to the long term negative emotional consequences of such crimes on victims that this 'commonsense' view was challenged.
11.42
With regard to the victim's opinion of the defendant and of what sentence should be handed down, this is undoubtedly the most controversial type of information; This aspect was rejected by the United Nations Victims' Charter in 1985. The rationale for this type of information is that it restores dignity to the victim by giving him/her a real say in what happens the offender. It could also act as a deterrent since the knowledge that a potential victim might to the smallest degree determine the severity of sentence could prevent much of the gratuitous violence and humiliation visited on victims in the course of the crime. It is hardly surprising that victim support groups might favour such a development, since the victim could reflect society's moral outrage at the small amount of attention given heretofore to the victim, who has been described as 'the forgotten link in the chain of justice'.53
11.43
However, there are a number of troublesome aspects to such information. It may divert sentencing from its primary object of determining the most appropriate sentence in accordance with the agreed goals of sentencing and towards satisfying the victim's personal wishes. It is also argued that it would introduce an unnecessary degree of personal conflict and tension into the proceedings.
11.44
Statutes vary considerably in the type of victim participation permitted. Some statutes require the inclusion of a victim's statement in the pre-sentence report only when the victim is willing to cooperate, while others allow the statement only when ordered by the sentencing court. If the defendant waives his/her right to a pre-sentence report, the victim's right to a statement is effectively nullified. Some allow the victim to write the statement and allow much latitude with regard to format, while others mandate that a probation officer should be responsible. As mentioned earlier, some statutes insist on objective measurement of harm. Some statutes allow the victim to speak at sentencing proceedings.
11.45
As we have seen, Section 5 of the Criminal Justice Bill introduced by the previous government made it mandatory for the court to take into account, any affect (whether long term or otherwise) of the offence on the victim in determining the sentence. The Court could if necessary receive evidence or
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=332 |
determining the sentence. The Court could if necessary receive evidence or submissions concerning such effect. We would hope this Paper will be published before the Dail debates the Bill or, if it lapses, any succeeding Bill and that it will assist the debate. A disadvantage, from the Commission's point of view, is not knowing exactly what the Government had in mind in certain instances. For example, in providing for submissions, did the Government envisage separate legal representation for complainants? The Explanatory Memorandum is silent on this point.
11.46
|
11.47
|
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=335 |
11.48
|
11.49
As for the desirability of providing for mandatory victim impact statements, opinion in the Commission is at present divided. We would be glad to obtain as many views as possible on the subject before making our final recommendations.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=337 |
12.1
It is probably a mistake to construct a model of sentencing for this, or most other common law jurisdictions, which assumes that it is after a trial that a conviction takes place. In the majority of cases in Ireland,1 sentence is imposed subsequent to a plea of guilty by the defendant to at least some charges. While no verifiable figures exist, practitioners suggest that very many of these pleas are the result of negotiations with the prosecution what is generally known as plea-bargaining, but which will be described in this treatment of the subject by the more neutral terms plea agreements or plea discussions.2 They have been defined by the Canadian Law Reform Commission as any agreement by the accused to plead guilty in return for the prosecutor's agreeing to take or refrain from taking a particular course of action.3 In a recent article, Gareth Williams QC, Chairman of the Bar, describes two forms of plea-bargaining. One is the acceptance by the prosecutor and sometimes the judge, of guilty pleas to offences less than those that have been or could be laid. The other is an arrangement by which the defendant knows what sentence is likely.4
12.2
The types of agreements which might be reached subsequent to such discussions in the various jurisdictions studied, include the following:
A reduction in the charge to a lesser offence; |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=338 |
The withdrawal of other outstanding charges; A promise not to institute or proceed with other possible charges; An undertaking to list other offences on a schedule to be taken into account on sentence but which does not expose the accused person to the risk of a greater maximum penalty; A reduction or withdrawal of charges in exchange for the accused person's testimony against the co-accused, or for information which might assist in the arrest or prosecution or other offenders; A promise not to charge another person, particularly a friend or family member who might be peripherally involved in the offence; A promise to proceed summarily rather than on indictment where the prosecution has such a choice; An undertaking by the prosecution that it will not make submissions contrary to those put by the accused person in support of a particular type of penalty. In some cases this may involve the prosecution in expressly supporting submissions made by the accused person as to the appropriate penalty;5 An undertaking to have the matter listed for hearing at a time and place convenient to the accused person; A promise that if a certain penalty is imposed the prosecution will not recommend that there should be an appeal against the inadequacy of the sentence;6 A promise to delete references to aggravating factual circumstances of the offence;7 A promise not to oppose release on bail pending the determination of the case.8 |
12.3
Also, Boyle has remarked that in Ireland there exists a structured feature of the courts system which constitutes a form of statutory plea bargaining. Nearly all offences can be tried summarily if the defendant is willing to plead guilty, so that the restricted sentencing powers and wide jurisdictional competence of the District Court provide an inducement to enter such a plea.9
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=339 |
However, a District Judge must not deal with any indictable offence summarily unless he is satisfied it is a minor offence fit to be so tried.10
12.4
It is necessary for the success of the model of sentencing policy propounded in this paper that it be consistent with such of these practices as prevail in Ireland.
12.5
It is not uncommon for plea discussions to be viewed as an evil-improper, unjust, secretive, unfair and irrational though most would accept them as necessary, given the existing strain on the trial capacity of our courts. But we concur with the Canadian Commission in its view that it would be a mistake to dismiss plea negotiation as a distasteful practice made necessary only by the unhappy reality of an overburdened criminal justice system.11 In particular, it should not be seen, on a theoretical level, as entirely unprincipled, as it embodies complementary principles of efficiency and restraint. Nor is efficiency characterised solely by expediency it can also entail the goal of accuracy, which requires that any offence to which the accused pleads guilty be a realistic reflection of his or her criminal conduct (to the extent it can be proved).12 Also, the principle of efficiency demands an acknowledgement that the concept of cost has moral and human (not just monetary) dimensions.13
12.6
Byme summarises in more pragmatic terms some of the practical benefits conferred by plea agreements. For public agencies, they include the following:
Time and labour are saved; In serious cases, the expense of a jury trial is averted; The result is certain and may be preferable to the possibility of the accused person being acquitted of a number of charges or of a more serious charge; The higher the ratio of guilty pleas to contested cases, the less strain is imposed on court time. Put simply, guilty pleas reduce the congestion of the criminal lists, thus allowing contested cases to be heard earlier than they otherwise might be; In some cases, it may allow the investigating and prosecuting authorities to obtain information about other, often more serious offenders; It may be used to avoid the impact of provisions of the substantive criminal law which would be unjustifiably harsh in the circumstances of the case; |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=340 |
Witnesses, and particularly the victims of criminal offences, are not subjected to the ordeal and inconvenience of giving evidence.14 |
12.7
For the accused person, the advantages of a plea of guilty vary, but may include the following:
The likely penalty is less than if the accused person were convicted of all charges or of a more serious charge;15 The case will be disposed of relatively quickly without the need to suffer the ordeal of a trial; The speedy disposition of the case by a guilty plea will probably make it less likely that the case will attract publicity; The accused person will not suffer the stigma of having a conviction recorded for the more serious offence or for a greater number of offences; Where the accused person is paying for his or her legal representation, the costs incurred in proceedings where there is a plea of guilty are considerably less.16 |
12.8
A number of regulatory issues arise in respect of plea discussions, which will be dealt with below. First, however, two fundamental issues of policy need to be addressed. These concern the role of the courts in plea negotiations and the place of plea agreements in a just deserts system of sentencing.
12.9
Three models of judicial involvement in plea discussions and agreements will be discussed below. They are:
|
12.10
A fourth possible model is, of course, that of the abstention by the courts from any role at this stage, the situation which obtains at present. However, such
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=341 |
is the importance of plea agreements to the ultimate sentencing stage, and the importance of likely sentence to the conduct of plea discussions, that the establishment of some system of interaction between judiciary, prosecution and defence to ensure that all parties are fully informed and that policies pursued at the two stages are consistent should be considered.
12.11
At the moment, judges do not play a part in plea discussions in Ireland. The Victorian Court of Criminal Appeal spoke, in R v Marshall of a form of plea bargaining in which counsel for an accused and counsel for the Crown attend the judge in his private chambers and discuss an arrangement whereby, upon the judge indicating the probable sentence and the Crown indicating that it will accept a plea of guilty to a particular charge, the accused through counsel indicates that he or she will plead guilty.18 This it strenuously opposed:
Anything which suggests an arrangement in private between a judge and counsel in relation to the plea to be made or the sentence to be imposed must be studiously avoided. It is objectionable because it does not take place in public, it excludes the person most vitally concerned, namely the accused, it is embarrassing to the Crown and it puts the judge in a false position which can only serve to weaken public confidence in the administration of justice.19 |
12.12
This statement seems to take no account of the fact that counsel for the accused should be assumed to act in his or her client's interest. Such meetings between counsel and judge are common in US jurisdictions, and an argument has been made for permitting them in this jurisdiction. It has been pointed out that one of the perils of plea agreements for prosecutors is that judges often impose quite low sentences even for the lesser charge to which a defendant pleads guilty, even though the prosecution might expect that it be close to the maximum, given the circumstances of the case. One means of avoiding this would be to include the judge in the negotiation process.
12.13
Certainly, if plea agreements are to be made which are in all respects justifiable, it is to be hoped that they would not be undermined by sentencing judges. But this can probably be achieved by less radical means. The arguments against actual judicial participation in discussions are considerable. One is that suggested by Ferguson and Roberts, that such participation is inconsistent with the judge's role as impartial adjudicator.20 Besides impairing the court's image as a dispassionate overseer, judicial plea negotiation may, in practice, cloud the perception of the presumption of innocence in any trial which might follow the breakdown of negotiations, in which the accused had indicated willingness to plead guilty.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=342 |
12.14
Another reason not to adopt such a procedure is that judicial negotiation may amount to an improper inducement for accused persons to plead guilty.21 Given the unequal relationship between the accused and the trial judge, the procedure might exert pressure on an accused to plead guilty rather than be tried by a judge whose suggested agreement he or she has rebuffed.22 It is highly improbable that an independent judiciary would take such an active role in the proceedings as would give rise to pressure on the accused. Again, it would be the duty and role of counsel for the accused to divert such pressure from his or her client.
12.15
Byrne adds that it is preferable that plea agreements should not bind or be seen to bind the court in the determination of the penalty for the offence.23 We believe, that it is desirable that such agreements be observed by the courts.
12.16
One means of reaching a plea agreement with a good chance of observance by the court is to seek in advance a sentence indication by the prospective trial judge. This is advocated by Byrne, who says that [r]ather than being seen as an inducement to a plea of guilty, this procedure can fairly be described as affording the accused person the opportunity to make a more informed decision as to the plea to be entered.24 He suggests that the court be bound by the indication given unless the facts of the case prove to be materially different to those initially outlined to it. Such an approach would commend itself to us. However, it was disapproved of by the Victorian Court of Criminal Appeal in Marshall:
If a judge is asked to give an indication of the sentence which is likely to be imposed following a plea of guilty he is likely to feel inhibited from subsequently passing a more severe sentence. If he succumbed to the inhibition, he would fail to pass the appropriate sentence. If he did pass a sentence more severe than he had previously indicated, the accused would undoubtedly, and in most cases with justification, harbour a feeling of injustice. He would in the colloquial sense have got more than he bargained for. Moreover, notwithstanding that the course could not preclude an appeal by the Attorney-General, an accused person who received from this court after an appeal a sentence greater or more severe than that previously indicated ... would also be justified in feeling that he had been unjustly treated.25 |
12.17
We are not convinced by this reasoning. So long as the judge is adequately informed of the evidence available in the case, by both sides, such changes of mind by the judge should be rare. It is unlikely that the prosecution would withhold material which might lead to an increase in the severity of the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=343 |
predicted sentence; and if the accused is less than honest at this stage, and is later exposed, he or she can hardly complain if the actual sentence imposed is greater than that initially indicated.
12.18
It appears that the practice of defence counsel seeking an indication of likely sentence does exist in England, but only in exceptional cases. Prosecution counsel should be present during such a consultation.26 However, the information which the judge may impart only relates to the type of sentence he is minded to give, and not to the actual quantum:
The judge should, subject to ... one exception ..., never indicate the sentence which he is minded to impose. A statement that on a plea of guilty he would impose one sentence but that on a conviction following a plea of not guilty he would impose a severer sentence, should never be made. This could be taken to be undue pressure on the accused, thus depriving him of that complete freedom of choice which is essential ... The only exception to this rule is that it should be permissible for a judge to say, if it be the case, that whatever happens, whether the accused pleads guilty or not guilty, the sentence will or will not take a particular form, eg. a probation order or a fine, or a custodial sentence. Finally, where any such discussion on sentence has taken place between judge and counsel, counsel for defence should disclose this to the accused and inform him of what took place.27 |
12.19
One judge of the State of Victoria, Mr Justice Hampel, has argued for a more detailed indication of intentions to be the norm, in these terms:
When considering whether to plead guilty and attempting to assess the likelihood of acquittal and the possible sentence on a plea of guilty or upon conviction, the accused is often in the dark about the very matter he wants most to know; what will be the likely end result of each course open to him. Yet, unlike in the case of predicting the result of a trial, there is a source of better information as to the likely result of a plea of guilty. That source is an informed sentencing judge.28 |
12.20
This proposal is in accordance with our own thinking on the matter. It might be remarked that the fears expressed above by the English Court of Criminal Appeal in Turner29 would be of little substance if the normal practice of giving a discount after a plea were expressly acknowledged and if sentencing were normally a fairly predictable process. The Court's anxiety to preserve the confidentiality and uncertainty of sentencing until sentence is in fact handed
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=344 |
down is more consonant with the present incoherent lottery quality of sentencing in many jurisdictions.
12.21
An alternative means of ensuring judicial observance at the sentencing stage of the expectations of both parties to a plea agreement is to institutionalise judicial supervision of such agreements in advance of this stage.30
12.22
At present such supervision is not possible. The terms of plea agreements are not publicised, and the trial judge is not in a position to question the entry of a nolle prosequi by an independent public prosecutor in respect of the more serious charge in return for a plea to an offence of lesser gravity.31
12.23
This brings us to the second fundamental issue of policy which was mentioned at the outset the place of plea agreements in a sentencing system with just deserts and proportionality of punishment as its objectives. There is a danger that agreements are, or will be, reached on the acceptance of a guilty plea to charges which do not fully reflect the seriousness of the offender's behaviour. This may be acceptable up to a point, first due to the other gains made thereby (in saving victims and witnesses the trauma of a trial, etc.32); and secondly because, dependent upon the quality of the State's evidence, the prosecution can, by assessment of probabilities, weigh the certainty of conviction of a lesser offence against the likelihood or possibility of acquittal or conviction of a more appropriate charge. Nonetheless, it is desirable that the ultimate offence of conviction be reasonably closely related to the conduct for which the defendant was responsible.
12.24
It is also necessary to consider the evidence which is made available by the prosecution at the sentencing stage. It appears that, in practice, evidence of offences other than that for which a guilty plea is accepted, or of aggravating circumstances which might suggest that a more serious charge would have been more appropriate, can be withheld by agreement.33 This, indeed, is consistent with the maxims derived from the principle nulla poena sine lege which are outlined above, e.g. that where an offender pleads guilty to some counts, but not to others, he or she must be sentenced only on the charges in relation to which there has been a plea of guilty.34
12.25
As appears from the treatment of the Federal Guidelines, the position in the US is rather different. Factual stipulations agreed by the parties must be accurate and not misleading (and can be checked by the judge by comparing
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=345 |
them to the pre-sentence report).35 However, this should not result in the imposition of sentences which breach the principle nulla poena sine lege because it attempts to ensure that the charges reflect the actual seriousness of any criminal conduct of which the State has evidence. In federal courts, the terms of all plea agreements are to be disclosed and justified. The trial judge reviews charge reduction agreements to ensure that, under the circumstances presented, an appropriate sentence may be imposed that will not undermine the purposes of sentencing.36 In order for the prosecution to dismiss any charges, the court must find and state on the record that the remaining charges adequately reflect the seriousness of the actual offence behaviour.37
12.26
In Canada, the trial judge may be justified in refusing to accept a plea of guilty to any offence other than the one initially charged.38 In respect of plea agreements, it has been remarked, in R v JEJ, that the discretionary powers of the Crown are not so 'unfettered' as to preclude the Court from exercising its inherent powers to control those powers should that be seen as necessary to prevent an abuse of the Court's process.39 Nadeau J went on to disapprove the systematised sham of withholding evidence on matters which the Court might consider relevant to sentence:
Where the Crown intentionally suppresses circumstances which cannot but aggravate the seriousness of the offence, in order to persuade the court of the appropriateness of the sentence which he has as a result of negotiations with the accused's counsel agreed to advance as appropriate, he is in breach of his obligation both to the Court and to the community.40 |
12.27
However, there does not exist in Canada the same obligation on the prosecutor to justify a plea agreement as exists in the US, though such an innovation has been recommended.41
12.28
If a trial judge were to examine and accept a charge reduction pursuant to an agreement, and to approve of that agreement, it is then to be expected that in sentencing he or she will be mindful of the terms of that agreement. It is likely, in most cases, that a sentence close to the maximum available for the lesser charge will be warranted, with a discount, where appropriate, for a guilty plea. The defendant will still probably benefit from that maximum being lower than that for the more serious offence for which he or she might have been prosecuted.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=346 |
12.29
If such a procedure of judicial supervision were to be introduced, it would presumably be necessary to amend s12, Criminal Justice (Administration) Act, 1924, which was held by the Supreme Court in the The State (Killian) v AG to give the Attorney General an unreviewable power to enter a nolle prosequi.42 A positive requirement that the existence and terms of any plea agreement be revealed for the scrutiny of the court, in advance of the entry of any nolle prosequi or guilty plea, would also be necessary.43
12.30
Such judicial supervision might reduce the degree to which plea agreements cause disparity in sentencing. Empirical research in jurisdictions where there is greater public awareness of the prevalence of plea negotiation tends to confirm that people are more likely to expect that a sentence imposed following a negotiated guilty plea and joint submission will be appropriate if they are assured that the presiding judge has been apprised, in open court, of the process by which the agreement was reached.44 As well as being perceived as fair and rational, public scrutiny makes it more probable that the decisions of participants in the criminal trial process will in fact be fair and rational, by ensuring accountability.45
12.31
We wonder, however, whether such a step is really necessary or desirable. Arguments for judicial supervision of plea agreements are predicated almost entirely on the need, in a just deserts system, to ensure that charges (and therefore sentences) reflect adequately the gravity of offending conduct. While the situation may be different in other jurisdictions, we are satisfied that the prosecution authorities in Ireland are not under such pressure that they habitually allow accused persons to get away with what Professor Robinson calls free harms. In theory, the prosecution is not concerned with the sentence. It follows, again in theory, that the prosecution should not engage in plea negotiation either. Given that plea negotiation is a fact of life and that the prosecution engages in it, prosecutors must ensure that a penalty, adequate on the facts, is available for the accused when he or she is convicted. In general, a prosecutor would only undersell from the point of view of available penalty in order to ensure a conviction for some offence, e.g. in a case where a young witness could be spared the ordeal of giving evidence or where a witness might be nervous and not likely to do him or herself justice when giving evidence.
12.32
Except, perhaps, to indicate the sentence he or she has in mind, the judge should not become embroiled in the plea bargaining process. The DPP should be free to prosecute or not to prosecute for an offence without permission
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=347 |
or supervision. It is felt that adopting a scheme which requires or predicates judicial participation or intervention in plea negotiations might be both unnecessary and inimical to the independence which both the judiciary and the prosecution must maintain.
12.33
Judicial indication of likely sentence would enable both sides (defence and prosecution) to reach an agreement of whose outcome they could be reasonably certain, as the judge would find it difficult later to depart from his or her indication. At the same time, it would preserve the role of the judiciary outside the plea discussion process. As Williams says:
The defendant often wants and may need certainty, the ability to put his affairs in order, the knowledge that he can wipe the slate clean and a reasonable idea of what will happen to him. My experience is that many defendants would plead guilty if they knew what the sentence was to be. A great number would plead guilty if they were certain of community service, probation or a suspended sentence. So why do we adamantly prevent it?46 |
12.34
If sentencing is a fairly consistent process, a judge cannot be accused of influencing the discussions unduly, or of pressurising the defence, merely by outlining his or her likely response to certain charges and evidence.
12.35
Another argument in favour of the judge's involvement is to ensure at least a degree of acceptability of the plea agreement system by the victims of crime. It is fair to say that, in general, the victims of crime or the next of kin of deceased victims do not wish to see any reduction in the seriousness of the charges to be met by the accused. When there is a plea to a less serious offence followed by a very light sentence, victims are very discomfited indeed. Bearing the understandable and justifiable feelings of victims in mind, the prosecution would like to know that a sentence of reasonable severity will be imposed before committing itself to a bargain.
12.36
It may be thought necessary or desirable that an accused who decides, after discussions and a sentence indication, not to plead guilty should have his or her case heard by a different judge. If this course were followed, it is suggested that, if convicted, the sentence indication be furnished to the second judge to guide his or her decision on sentence. Otherwise, the offender might indeed get more than was bargained for.
12.37
Having the case heard by a different judge would present significant problems outside Dublin, i.e. in one judge Districts and Circuits. The Commission is satisfied that judges would be able to proceed to try a case absolutely fairly having earlier indicated the sentence they would give on a plea
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=348 |
of guilty. Judges proceed with trials every day having ruled out statements of admission. The ability to clear the mind of matter already disclosed is part of the judicial art. We would certainly not favour a defendant's seeking a sentence indication from one judge after another until finding the sentence that suited him or her. However, we appreciate that it might be difficult to secure and maintain public acceptance of a judge's ability to clear his or her mind after giving a sentence indication.
12.38
The Commission, for all the reasons set out above47 is in favour of some system of plea agreement, whatever effect it might have on the purity of a sentencing schema. The Commission would rather maintain the system as it is than risk its losing acceptability by involving the judge. In any event, the more coordinated and consistent sentencing becomes, the less advantage would be derived from involving the judge in the procedure.
12.39
While the substance of plea agreements need not be the object of judicial scrutiny, in order to facilitate both prosecution and defence in reaching acceptable plea agreements, guidelines could be formulated in respect of the procedure to be followed. Such guidelines have been promulgated by the Commonwealth DPP in Australia, and have been recommended for the Australian States.48
12.40
It has been suggested, for example, that there should be no initiation of plea negotiations by the prosecution; and that a comprehensive system of compulsory disclosure of evidence in the possession of the prosecution should create an atmosphere in which the probable plea to be made by the accused is more likely to be indicated at an early stage in the proceedings, and would enable plea negotiations to be conducted in a more informed manner.49
12.41
If it were thought necessary to do so, the prosecution's pre-trial negotiating procedures could be strictly regulated. The American Law Institute has provided a persuasive precedent.50 Three prosecutorial negotiating tactics are prohibited:
|
12.42
The ALI Code seeks to ensure, generally, that plea discussions are conducted in a manner that is consistent with the type of prosecutorial practices that would normally be engaged in if the conclusion of a plea agreement were not a goal.54 This seems a good basis on which to construct a scheme of prosecutorial guidelines. Improper inducements pose a particular danger because they threaten the genuineness and factual accuracy of guilty pleas. For the same reason, defence counsel should be careful not to pressurise the accused into pleading guilty to an offence of which he or she protests innocence. In order to maintain what in civil law jurisdictions is called equality of arms, the prosecution should negotiate only with defence counsel and not with the defendant personally.
12.43
In Ireland, while no written guidelines for plea negotiation exist, there is, in fact, a strict prosecution code. The code is that:
|
12.44
If it were thought necessary to reproduce the code and perhaps, elaborate it in written guidelines, this could be done.
12.45
Our provisional recommendation is to leave things as they are and not interfere with present practice, although we would welcome views on sentence indication by the judge.
12.46
The more detailed recommendations of the Canadian Law Reform Commission, are contained in Appendix D with annotations; extracts from other relevant codes and reports are also contained there.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=350 |
13.1
Not surprisingly strong objection can be taken to any judicial reluctance to state reasons for choice of sentence. Four independent grounds of objection are apparent.1
13.2
First, for the defendant, the failure to state reasons may well amount to a breach of natural justice and the rule of audi alteram partem.2 One might conclude that any important decision made in a court of law should be supported by a careful and accurate statement of the reasons for that decision. If reasons are not given then the defendant is deprived of the opportunity to challenge the reasoning of the sentencer. It has been observed of the giving of reasons that
It is of assistance to the defendant both in accepting what has happened and, where he does not accept it, in preparing his appeal.3 |
13.3
Secondly, the failure to provide reasons hinders the rationalisation of sentencing generally. The mystery of the sentencing decision where reasons are not given does little to promote confidence in the sentencing process in which people are entitled to expect that the decision will be made on a rational and just basis. There are a number of people besides the defendant who need to know the reasons for sentence:4
|
13.4
Thirdly, the failure to state reasons has the conspicuous disadvantage of hampering and distorting the review of sentence by the appellate courts. The end result may be a reluctance to interfere with the findings of the lower courts. In The People (Attorney General) v Poyning7 the Court of Criminal Appeal refused to interfere with the sentence imposed on the appellant -even though more severe than that imposed on two co-accused not because it agreed that the reasons for the sentence were correct, but because they might have been correct. The Court of Criminal Appeal had tried to uncover the reasons for the trial court's choice of lighter sentence for the co-accuseds, but met with some difficulty, as Walsh J explained:8
With a view to informing itself, as well as it could, on the background and antecedents of the co-accused and of the factors which moved the High Court to impose sentences which were very much lighter than those imposed by the Circuit Court, this Court directed the Registrar of the Court of Criminal Appeal to apply to the County Registrar of Dublin for a transcript of the shorthand note of the proceedings in the case of [the co-accused] dealing with the sentences, the evidence given there and the considerations which were applied ... As no appeal was pending in the case of [the co-accuseds] the President of the High Court [the trial judge] was not in a position to sanction the issue of a transcript in relation to the proceedings heard before him. Unfortunately the lapse of time has made it undesirable for this Court to prolong this matter further by inquiring into this aspect of the case ... Unfortunately this course leaves this Court without the benefit of the views expressed by |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=352 |
the learned President of the High Court when dealing with the case. |
13.5
If the President of the High Court, the trial judge in the case of the co-accused, had given reasons pronouncing sentence, then the Court of Criminal Appeal would not have found itself without the benefit of the views expressed by the learned President of the High Court when dealing with the case, and the final result might arguably have been very different.
13.6
Finally, the lack of reasons does little to promote consistency within the sentencing process. Other sentencers in similar cases do not have the benefit of a colleague's reasoned experience, so they may rely on a wholly different set of reasons. They are not even afforded the opportunity to consider the opinions of other judges as to what reasons are relevant even if they do not agree with them because those opinions are nowhere to be found.
13.7
If an obligation was placed on sentencers to give reasons for their choice of sentence, then not only would these problems be diminished but there would also be the added advantage that sentencers would be forced to give more careful consideration to the various decisions made at the sentencing stage, since they would have to disclose publicly their reasoning in due course.9
13.8
The only objection to an obligation to give reasons is that it would cast an intolerable burden on the courts and cause excessive delays.10 However, we should be loath to sacrifice fairness and accuracy at the altar of speed. Nonetheless, in the District Court this objection may carry more weight, at least in relation to the more trivial summary offences punishable by small fines, and such cases could safely be exempted from the requirement, as could any cases in which the sentence is mandatory and fixed by law.
13.9
We provisionally recommend that there be a statutory obligation on sentencers to give reasons for the choice of sentence in all cases apart from trivial cases where the penalties are slight or cases where the penalty is mandatory and fixed by law.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=353 |
14.1
As has been seen, there is at present no general prosecution right of appeal against either acquittal or sentence upon conviction in the Irish criminal justice system. An exception exists under Article 34.7.3 of the Constitution, whereby such appeals may be made against acquittals from the Central Criminal Court to the Supreme Court. This facility has been undermined, however, by the latter court's reluctance to disturb the findings of lower courts a policy rather less justified (if followed) in respect of sentences than it is with regard to verdicts.1 There is no prosecution appeal from verdicts in the Circuit Court. It must now be asked whether the prosecution should be afforded in all cases, including Circuit Court cases, the opportunity to appeal sentences which it believes to be too lenient.
14.2
Two options are possible for an appeal to take place simply to clarify principles for the future, without altering the instant sentence; or for the Court of Criminal Appeal actually to increase (or decrease) the sentence under consideration. If prosecution appeals are to be permitted, the latter course may seem more in keeping with present practice, in so far as appellant defendants may have their sentences remitted, reduced or increased or otherwise varied by the Court of Criminal Appeal, under s34, Courts of Justice Act, 1924 this jurisdiction does not adhere to the principle of prohibition of reformatio in peius which prevails on the continent.2 It might be argued, on the other hand, that any general prosecution right of appeal against sentence should mirror the provisions of s34 of the Criminal Procedure Act, 1967, which allows the prosecution to make a case stated without prejudice to the verdict. It has been argued that such a procedure would be worthless it would aggravate rather than relax public disquiet, by drawing attention to injustices which cannot be
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=354 |
remedied, to the grave dissatisfaction not only of the community at large, but also of crime victims, and of convicted people who had received appropriate sentences.3
14.3
The Criminal Justice Bill, 1992 introduced by the last Government gave the Director of Public Prosecutions a power to appeal any sentence on conviction. Section 2 provided inter alia:
|
14.4
Discussion will, therefore, be concentrated on an appeal procedure which includes a power to vary sentences.
|
14.5
The arguments in favour of prosecution appeals against sentence are more persuasive. In general, where mistakes are capable of being made, they should be capable of being corrected.20 The effect of unduly lenient sentences throughout society can be such as to make it imperative that some remedy be made available:
[U]nduly lenient sentences cause outrage to the victims of crime, they blunt the deterrent effect of the criminal law, they demoralise law enforcement and prosecuting agencies, engender bitterness in those who have received more severe but at the same time appropriate sentences for offences of a similar kind, undermine public confidence in the administration of justice and in some cases create a real risk to the public by the premature release into the community of a dangerous offender.21 |
14.6
Perhaps more pressing of all is the point that the absence of the right of the prosecution to appeal promotes the development of an unhelpful set of sentencing precedents, as appeal courts have little occasion to give guidance as to what is inappropriately lenient in a given case. The result is what Ashworth calls a lop-sided set of precedents:
The Court hears appeals only against sentences which are thought by the offender to be too severe, with the result that there are myriad precedents on the aggravating features of serious offences but very few decisions at all on non-custodial sentences or the least serious kinds of manslaughter, rape and robbery. It is hardly too much to say that the more frequent the type of case, the less appellate guidance there is likely |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=358 |
to be.22 |
14.7
Ashworth suggests that even when it formulates guideline judgments based on ranges of hypothetical facts less serious than the case before it, the Court of Appeal's palate is so affected by a continuous diet of heavy sentences that the guidance is sometimes over-severe.23 Ultimately, these arguments seem more convincing than those against.
14.8
We provisionally recommend the introduction of a prosecution right of appeal against sentence.
14.9
Should prosecution appeals be allowed from the District Court? All of the arguments rehearsed above apply in this case as in any other, and one should of course aim for consistency of principle and practice throughout the criminal justice system. Nonetheless, there is an argument that prosecution resources might be better employed than in pursuing appeals at this level. In respect of an equivalent debate in New South Wales about extending the right of prosecution appeal to the magistrates' courts, Byrne remarks as follows:
We have seen that a Court of Criminal Appeal will only interfere on an appeal by the prosecution where it is satisfied that the penalty imposed at first instance is manifestly inadequate. Because the range of the sentencing discretion available to a magistrate is so confined when compared with a judge dealing with a matter on indictment, it may be argued that whatever penalty is imposed by a magistrate, it can never be so far removed from the appropriate penalty as to be fairly described as manifestly inadequate.24 |
14.10
Difficult policy questions of resource allocation arise in this respect. We seek views on whether a right of prosecution appeal should be extended to the District Court.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=359 |
15.1
Once a more coherent sentencing policy is put in place, the legislature will need to take a close look at its penal policy to see what changes are necessary in order to co-ordinate penal policy with sentencing policy. While a comprehensive review of the changes necessary is outside the ambit of this Paper, we can nonetheless point to some of the issues which will merit detailed examination. Two matters which are of vital concern are (i) a review of the sentencing options which are available to the courts and (ii) an examination of the law and procedure relating to the administration of sentence.
15.2
The range of sentencing options presently available to the sentencing courts and the difficulties which follow them in practice have been set out in detail elsewhere in this Paper.1 In 1985 the Whitaker Committee of Inquiry into the Penal System issued its Report.2 The Committee made a number of recommendations on the reform of the law in relation to existing sentencing options and proposed some further sentencing options. The Committee's proposals, which are supported in principle by this Commission, deserve immediate legislative attention.
15.3
We provisionally recommend that the legislature undertake a comprehensive review of the law and procedure in relation to the present range of sentencing options with a view to better co-ordination of penal and sentencing policy. The recommendations of the Committee of Inqiry into the Penal System in this regard should be given special consideration.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=360 |
15.4
One matter which could be disposed of immediately is the abolition of penal servitude and imprisonment with hard labour in favour of imprisonment simpliciter.3 Although these sentences effectively amount to sentences of imprisonment, the residual disqualifications which attach to them and the inabilty to order a sentence of penal servitude which operates from some time in the past mean that offenders who receive them are treated differently to other, often more serious, offenders.
15.5
We provisionally recommend that penal servitude and imprisonment with hard labour be abolished and imprisonment substituted in their place.
15.6
Once the court has pronounced its sentence and all appeals against conviction or sentence are concluded, the sentence becomes final and the courts lose their seisin of the case. Thereafter it is the executive, acting through the Minister for Justice and the penal authorities, which is responsible for the administration of sentence. Any decisions in relation to the sentence are then made by the executive. It has been held that:
It is part of the judicial function to determine the nature and extent of the sentence, whenever the general rule laid down by statute or by common law gives a range of choice. Thereafter it is within the power of the Government, or the Minister for Justice as its delegate, to commute or remit, in whole or in part, any punishment imposed by a court exercising criminal jurisdiction.4 |
15.7
During the administration of sentence, the executive, acting through the Minister for Justice, may alter the sentence imposed by the sentencing court in two ways:
|
15.8
It should be noted that the executive has no power to increase a sentence imposed by a court.5 The methods listed here are, thus, ways in which the executive can reduce a sentence imposed by a court exercising criminal jurisdiction.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=361 |
15.9
The basis for this power is to be found in Article 13.6 of the Constitution, which provides:
The right of pardon and the power to commute or remit punishment imposed by any court exercising criminal jurisdiction are hereby vested in the President, but such power of commutation or remission may, except in capital cases, also be conferred by law on other authorities. |
15.10
Section 23 of the Criminal Justice Act, 1951 conferred such power of commutation or remission on the Government and the Minister for Justice. The power to pardon seems to have been implicitly reserved for the President. There would appear to be no set of rules or guidelines which governs the power to commute sentence, but in capital cases the power is exercisable only by the President on the advice of the Government.6
15.11
The President may commute any other punishments, and so may the Government and the Minister for Justice except for disqualification from holding a driving licence7 which may only be lifted by the President.
15.12
As regards remission, the Prisons Act, 1907 enabled provisions to be made for prisoners undergoing a sentence of imprisonment to earn remission of a portion of their sentences by special industry and good conduct. The Rules for the Government of Prisons, 19478 set out the maximum periods of remission which may be granted for industry and which may be granted for industry and good conduct to prisoners serving custodial sentencers. There is no provision for a maximum amount of remission in respect of other forms of sentence. A person undergoing a sentence of imprisonment in excess of one calendar month may earn a remission of up to 25% of his or her imprisonment, provided such remission does not result in the sentence being discharged in less than one month.9 A male undergoing any term of penal servitude may earn up to 25% remission of sentence,10 and a female undergoing penal servitude may earn up to 33 1/3% remission.11 The power of remission does not apply to disqualification from holding a driving licence, which, thus, can only be reduced by the President.12
15.13
The Whitaker Committee recommended that the present standard remission for good conduct, which is 25% for sentences in excess of one month, should be raised to 33.33% in line with European standards.13
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=362 |
15.14
The rationale for remission appears to be that it provides an incentive for prisoners to obey prison rules.14
15.15
In 1988 11.3% of those serving custodial sentences were discharged upon remission of a proportion of their sentences.15
15.16
The system of temporary release is a flexible system which has been developing since the 1960s. Section 2 of the Criminal Justice Act, 1960 empowers the Minister for Justice to:
make rules providing for the temporary release, subject to such conditions (if any) as may be imposed in each particular case, of persons serving a sentence of penal servitude or imprisonment, or of detention.16 |
15.17
However, the Act provides only the barest of outlines for the temporary release scheme, and the Prisoners (Temporary Release) Rules, 1960,17 merely set out the formalities which a prisoner undergoing temporary release must comply with such as the temporary release which he or she must sign, and the penalties for breach of conditions.
15.18
It would appear that the provision of temporary release was intended originally as a compassionate measure to be exercised only sparingly,18 but now has grown to be a full-blown parole system. The professed basis for the system as it exists today is rehabilitation; The Annual Report on Prisons and Places of Detention, 1982 said:
The objectives of temporary release, generally, are to enable the offender to keep in touch with his family and the community and, in the latter stages of the sentence, to reintegrate him into society on a gradual and phased basis. There are various forms of temporary release. On daily temporary release the offender leaves the prison or place of detention each morning to attend work or training and returns each evening. On full temporary release the prisoner is released outright subject to conditions, one of which may be that he be supervised by a Probation and Welfare Officer. |
15.19
However, in truth, the situation with pressure on prison accommodation is such that a high proportion of short term offenders have to be released on full
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=363 |
temporary release without supervision. In, 1988 those numbers were as follows:
Full Temporary releases for the year 198819
Number Released |
Number supervised by Probation & Welfare Service |
Number un-supervised by probation & Welfare Service |
1504 |
32 |
1472 |
15.20
Decisions in regard to temporary release are made following discussion at the inter-service review meetings which are held at all prisons regularly to review each offender's case. Those meetings may be attended by prison staff, probation and welfare officers, chaplains, psychologists, and, normally, an official from the Department of Justice. It is also usual to consult the Garda Sνochαna in relation to the prisoner in question. These meetings do not have any decision making function, and their primary value lies in allowing the views of the various participants as to how the cases of individual offenders might best be dealt with to be explored fully. The aim of the meeting is to come up with a recommendation for or against temporary release. The Report on Prisons and Place of Detention, 1982 continues:
Following recommendations made at local review meetings a prompt decision on the grant or refusal of temporary release may be made having regard to general guidelines which have been established and accepted by successive Ministers for Justice. |
15.21
The substance of these guidelines is not clear, but The Report on Prisons and Places of Detention, 1988 comments:
Among the factors taken into account in assessing cases for release are nature of offence, previous record, length of sentence served, behaviour while in custody and a Garda assessment of the likely risk which may be posed to the community by a release. As indicated in previous reports an over-riding factor in reaching decisions must be the need to protect the public. |
15.22
Commutation, remission and temporary release clearly have some positive values, not the least of which is the possibility of inducement to reform which may result from their operation. However, from the sentencing point of
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=364 |
view, they may have lead to a number of undesirable consequences:
|
15.23
We provisionally recommend that the legislature undertake a detailed review of the law and procedure governing the administration of sentence with a view to ensuring close co-ordination with sentencing policy. Particular attention should be paid to the provision of express guidelines on commutation and remission of sentence and temporary release. The Report of the Whitaker Committee of Inquiry into the Penal System is useful in this respect.
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=365 |
16.1
Two discrete but connected tasks remain to be considered. One is the compilation of information on sentencing, whether descriptive or quasi-descriptive, and its dissemination to the judiciary, counsel and the public. The other is the institution of what in England are called judicial studies. Both of these functions could be undertaken by a distinct body. The matter of information-gathering has already been considered at length above, so discussion will be concentrated for the moment on the second potential function of such a body. According to one's preferences, it might be known as a judicial studies board, a sentencing commission or council, or a judicial centre. For consistency's sake, it will be referred to throughout as a judicial studies board this has the added advantage of not confining its field of study to sentencing.
16.2
Sentencing is a complex task, which requires knowledge of sentencing principles, law and procedure, and the capacity to select and evaluate relevant facts from a potentially wide range of facts about the offence and the offender. Concern has been expressed in many quarters about the fact that many, or most, judges come to the bench from practices which involved little criminal work, so that their experience of sentencing is limited.1
16.3
Also, qualification for admission to either of the legal professions does not require even the most elementary acquaintance with modern social science as it affects sentencing.2 This may be considered a considerable weakness:
The judge should have a sound understanding of how the various facets of the penal system work in practice, and of those difficult and |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=366 |
controversial fields of knowledge concerned with the springs of criminal behaviour and the likely effects of different penal procedures on the criminal. No one requires of the judge that he be penologist, criminologist, or psychologist; but it is entirely reasonable to expect him to know what penologists, criminologist, and psychologists are thinking.3 |
16.4
Furthermore, in one jurisdiction almost two thirds of the respondents in a Judicial Officer Survey either favoured or strongly favoured formal training as one method of promoting uniformity in sentencing.4 As the application of sentencing policy to specific circumstances is an evolutionary process, a systematic updating process would be beneficial in conjunction with an induction process upon a judge's appointment.5
16.5
Thomas has written in some detail about the sort of educational tasks which should be undertaken in respect of sentencing.6 His syllabus would be comprised of the following areas:
|
16.6
Commentators are eager to point out that all these are areas in which the conscientious judge can, upon appointment, set about acquiring an expertise. But it is clear that an actual process of induction would make this much easier. A
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=367 |
judicial studies board could also take efforts to make relevant material more accessible, and to illustrate to judges the usefulness of the statistical and other sentencing information which it published.
16.7
It might be added that it is not only judges who need such knowledge a lawyer appearing in a criminal case cannot discharge his or her professional responsibilities to a client without it. Greater emphasis on sentencing and criminology at university and professional course level would, therefore, be a boon. But if we rely only on legal education, it will be a long time before we begin to see any practical benefit. Thomas stresses that it is essential to develop simultaneously a series of courses for sentencers and for lawyers involved in criminal litigation a task calling for sophistication and expertise.9 He is particularly anxious to emphasise that such a development should not encroach upon the independence of the judiciary, by indoctrination the object of judicial studies must be to equip the sentencer with the fullest range of available information so that he may exercise his discretion judicially and in an informed manner.10 We would also emphasise that any scheme adopted should have the confidence and support of the judiciary; otherwise it is bound to fail. Judges must see the merit of courses, seminars or conferences, or such innovations will be useless. Therefore, any recommendations in this area should be implemented only in consultation with the judiciary.
16.8
Thomas recommends a course of study composed of the following elements:
|
16.9
Thomas envisages the ultimate foundation of a judicial staff college, on the lines of those which exist in the US for state and federal judges.15 This for the moment seems rather too ambitious for this jurisdiction, and might not be greeted with enthusiasm by those who still see an active practice as the best preparation for judicial office in the common law system.
16.10
The Judicial Studies Board in England reflects some of the ideas cited above and indeed, Dr Thomas is Studies Consultant to the Board.16 It has a number of training functions in respect of family and civil law, and tribunals but we shall concentrate on its dealings with sentencing.
16.11
Some recommendations of the Bridge Committee17 have not been followed for example, the Board has not been attached to an academic base such as a university law faculty.18 However, as well as Dr Thomas, a number of academic lawyers are members of the Board's committees, and assist with lectures and discussions at its seminars. The Board has a staff of 10, but is judge-run19 in that all Board members are judicial officers of the superior courts. Induction courses are largely run by judges, and the form and content of all seminars are decided by the Board's committees, in which judges predominate Senior members of the Bench have a substantial involvement with refresher courses.
16.12
The Induction Course includes a mock criminal trial, which runs throughout the conference in two-hour spells, with adjournments for lectures, seminars and discussions. Periodic refresher courses20 have a higher sentencing content. Also, all members of the judiciary are required to attend a one-day Sentencing Conference each year on his circuit.21
16.13
The Board publishes a quarterly bulletin summarising leading sentencing decisions and occasionally reporting research developments. Recently appointed judges spend a few weeks sitting in with an experienced judge engaged in sentencing.22
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=369 |
16.14
The Victorian Sentencing Committee has recommended a similar body for that jurisdiction.23 The Australian Law Reform Commission has also recommended more formal judicial education, as well as judicial interaction through seminars, etc.24 The Judicial Commission of New South Wales, established in 1986, has as one of its functions the organisation and supervision of continuing education for judicial officers. Part 4 of the Judicial Officers Act, 1986 (NSW) deals with the commission's functions. With regard to sentencing, section 8 of the Act provides that:
|
Section 9, dealing with judicial education, provides that:
|
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=370 |
16.15
In New Zealand, the Penal Policy Review Committee, in its 1982 report (the Casey Report), recommended that a Sentencing Research Council be established on a statutory footing, with the following functions:
to provide judges and others involved in the sentencing process with information about the purpose of specific penal measures as they are introduced; to provide them with information about the content of penal measures and their effectiveness; to provide them with cultural and other relevant information to help in choosing the most effective way of dealing with offenders belonging to minority cultural and ethnic groups or those with special problems; to provide them with statistical and other services to assist them to carry out sentencing functions effectively and to promote an appropriate level of consistency in sentence; to provide such other information and services necessary to or desirable to assist the courts in developing and applying an appropriate penal policy for New Zealand.25 |
16.16
It was recommended that it be a small specialist body, with the following composition:
The Chief Justice (or nominee); The Chief District Court Judge (or nominee); The Secretary of Justice; a member of the Department of Justice 'concerned with penal policy'; a representative of the Law Society; a university representative 'associated with criminal law or criminology'; a person 'having the ability to represent a Maori point of view'; a lay person to represent 'a responsible community view'.26 |
16.17
Sentencing education through seminars and conferences is also among the
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=371 |
recommendations of the Council of Europe27 and the Canadian Sentencing Commission.28
16.18
We provisionally recommend that organised judicial studies in sentencing be initiated by a body charged with the development and supervision of judicial education, and with the compilation and publication of sentencing statistics and other information and materials.
16.19
We seek views on the composition of such a body, and on the precise ambit of the responsibilities and functions which it should undertake. A governing condition must be that judicial independence and dignity not be undermined.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=372 |
1.
We provisionally recommend that a national agency be established for the compilation and dissemination of statistics relevant to sentencing. (Introduction and Chapter 9)
2.
We provisionally recommend that the legislature formulate in statutory form a coherent policy governing sentencing. (Chapter 3)
3.
We provisionally recommend that the legislature set out by way of statute a clear statement that the sentence to be imposed on an offender be determined by reference to the just deserts principle of distribution whereby the severity of the sentence be measured in proportion to the seriousness of the offending behaviour, and the sentence not be more severe than the sentence for more serious offending behaviour nor less severe than the sentence for less serious offending behaviour. The legislative statement should highlight the following concerns:
|
4.
We provisionally recommend that the statutory statement of the principles of distribution of sentence implement a choice of method hybrid for the determination of which of two or more competing sanctions of equal severity should be imposed in individual cases. The statement should highlight the following concerns:
|
5.
We provisionally recommend the introduction of a statutory provision governing sentencing which would highlight the following concerns:
In assessing the harm, culpability and circumstances which tend to aggravate the offence, the sentencer shall give special consideration to:
|
6.
We provisionally recommend the introduction of a statutory provision governing sentencing which would highlight the following concerns:
In assessing the harm, culpability and circumstances which tend to mitigate the offence, the sentencer shall give special consideration to:
|
7.
We provisionally recommend the introduction of a statutory provision governing sentencing which would highlight the following concerns:
Having arrived at a sentence which is proportionate in severity to the seriousness of the offence, the sentencer should give reasonable consideration to whether there are any special reasons, by way of exception to the general principle of proportionality between offence and sentence, why a sentence of lesser severity should be imposed, such as where:
|
8.
We would welcome views on the matter of whether the sentencer should be empowered to allow some reduction in sentence for the fact that the offender has done some spectacular good deed in the past. (Chapter 5)
9.
We provisionally recommend that the statutory lists of aggravating and mitigating factors be reviewed by the legislature from time to time in order to take new developments into account. We recommend that any alterations or amendments be made in consultation with the proposed Judicial Studies Board in order to ensure that they do not undermine or conflict with sentencing policy. (Chapter 5)
10.
We provisionally recommend that the proposed just deserts approach
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=377 |
include a consideration of relevant prior criminal record as a factor aggravating the culpability of the offender. However, we would welcome views on the merits of adopting a progressive loss of mitigation approach in preference to this. (Chapter 6)
11.
We provisionally recommend a statutory provision which confines the role of prior criminal record in the determination of the severity of sentence to situations in which it aggravates the culpability of the offender in committing the offence. The provision should highlight the following concerns:
|
12.
We provisionally recommend that a determinate sentencing scheme not be adopted in this jurisdiction. (Chapter 9)
13.
We provisionally recommend that a scheme of presumptive sentencing guidelines not be adopted in this jurisdiction. (Chapter 9)
14.
We provisionally recommend the formulation of a scheme for the provision of quantitative sentencing information to judges, in the context of a coherent sentencing policy and of sentencing guidance by appellate courts; such information to be compiled over a period after the legislative introduction of a statement of sentencing policy. Information
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=378 |
should be provided on sentences resulting from different combinations of material case factors. (Chapter 9)
15.
We seek views on the design of a sentencing information system. Issues include whether the chosen material factors by which cases are compared should be objectively or subjectively defined; whether a descriptive or quasi-descriptive approach should be adopted; and whether the information compiled should be presented merely in the form of sentence distributions, or in the form of advisory starting points. (Chapter 9)
16.
We seek views on the most appropriate method of compiling quantitative statistical sentencing information or guidance in respect of less serious offences. (Chapter 9)
17.
We provisionally recommend the continued supervision of sentencing practice, and the provision of sentencing guidance, by the appellate courts, in accordance with the proposed legislative statement of sentencing policy. (Chapter 9)
18.
We provisionally recommend that the appellate courts resort to guideline judgments when presented by cases before them with a suitable opportunity to provide more general guidance on the application of sentencing policy to particular offences. (Chapter 9)
19.
We seek views on how such qualitative sentencing data can be better communicated to sentencing judges. (Chapter 9)
20.
We provisionally recommend that the legislature undertake a review of the set of maximum penalties which currently exists in Ireland, and rescales the levels in accordance with modern perspectives on offence seriousness and in accordance with the view that custodial sentences should be regarded as sanctions of the last resort. We provisionally recommend that the set of maximum penalties be diminished -between six and eight levels of maximum penalty would be sufficient. (Chapter 10)
21.
We recommend the implementation of the proposals in our Report on the Indexation of Fines. (Chapter 10)
22.
We provisionally recommend that the legislature refrain from the introduction of minimum sentences in the future, and that those still in force be abolished. (Chapter 10)
23.
We provisionally recommend that mandatory sentences for indictable offences should be abolished and the power to impose a discretionary
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=379 |
23.
We provisionally recommend that mandatory sentences for indictable offences should be abolished and the power to impose a discretionary sentence within the limits of a maximum sentence be substituted in their place. (Chapter 10)
24.
We provisionally recommend that the question of mandatory sentences for minor crimes be examined in more detail with a view to improving the efficiency of the administration of justice in the District Court. (Chapter 10)
25.
We provisionally recommend the adoption of a code of procedure and evidence for the sentencing hearing, on Canadian lines. (Chapter 11)
26.
We provisionally recommend judicial scrutiny of the accuracy and completeness of evidence agreed by both parties at the sentencing hearing, on US lines. (Chapter 11)
27.
We seek views on the desirability of applying restrictive and exclusionary rules of evidence to factual disputes at the sentencing hearing. (Chapter 11)
28.
We seek views on the most appropriate standard of proof for the resolution of factual disputes at the sentencing hearing. (Chapter 11)
29.
We provisionally recommend that prosecution counsel be permitted at the sentencing stage to make submissions to the court not just on the facts of the case, but also on relevant legal principles and precedents. We do not recommend that he or she make specific submissions on the appropriateness of a particular sentence. (Chapter 11)
30
We seek views as to whether provision should be made for mandatory consideration of victim impact statements at the sentencing stage. (Chapter 11)
31.
We provisionally recommend that the conclusion of plea agreements between the prosecution and the accused be specifically permitted. (Chapter 12)
32.
We seek views as to whether judges should participate in plea negotiations to the extent of indicating the sentence they would intend to impose. (Chapter 12)
33.
We provisionally recommend that there be a statutory obligation on sentencers to give reasons for the choice of sentence in all cases apart from trivial cases where the penalties are slight or cases where the
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=380 |
34
We provisionally recommend the introduction of a prosecution right of appeal against sentence. (Chapter 14)
35.
We seek views on whether a right of prosecution appeal against sentence should be available in respect of decisions of the District Court. (Chapter 14)
36.
We provisionally recommend that the legislature undertake a comprehensive review of the law and procedure in relation to the present range of sentencing options with a view to better co-ordination of penal and sentencing policy. The recommendations of the Committee of Inquiry into the Penal System in this regard should be given special consideration. (Chapter 15)
37
We provisionally recommend that penal servitude and imprisonment with hard labour be abolished and imprisonment substituted in their place. (Chapter 15)
38.
We provisionally recommend that the legislature undertake a detailed review of the law and procedure governing the administration of sentence with a view to ensuring close co-ordination with sentencing policy. Particular attention should be paid to the provision of express guidelines on commutation and remission of sentence and temporary release. (Chapter 15)
39.
We provisionally recommend that organised judicial studies in sentencing be initiated by a body charged with the development and supervision of judicial education, and with the compilation and publication of sentencing statistics and other information and materials. (Chapter 16)
40.
We seek views on the composition of such a body, and on the precise ambit of the responsibilities and function which it should undertake. A governing condition must be that judicial independence not be undermined. (Chapter 16)
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=381 |
The document which follows is a merger of the Draft Recommendations on Consistency in Sentencing of the Committee of Ministers of the Council of Europe (prepared by the Select Committee of Experts on Sentencing, document PC-R-SN (90) 12), with the commentary of Professor Ashworth on his immediately preceding draft recommendations (PC-R-SN (90) 11), which were in all material respects the basis of the recommendations quoted.
The Committee is convinced of the value of a consistent approach to sentencing, but is also mindful of the need to retain judicial discretion which allows flexibility in cases which present unusual features. The recommendations do not propose the replacement of judicial discretion with rigid rules: that might create inconsistency through treating different cases as if they were alike. The Committee believes that the best approach to consistency is one of structured discretion: this preserves judicial discretion but establishes clear aims of sentencing and general principles on such matters as aggravation, mitigation and recidivists, supported by requirements to give reasons for sentence. This is the theme of the draft recommendations below, and it will be developed in greater detail in the future work of the Committee.1
1.
A primary aim of sentencing should be declared.
2.
If it is thought that there should be a place for the pursuit of another
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=382 |
aim or other aims, the law should attempt to indicate how to resolve possible conflicts between such aims.
3.
The law should also attempt to indicate the types of case or circumstances in which each of these other aims may or should be pursued.
4.
The aim or aims of sentencing should be reviewed from time to time.
5.
Sentencing aims should be consistent with current policies, in particular in respect of reducing the use of imprisonment and of ensuring the compensation of victims.
6.
Sentences must not discriminate against offenders on account of race, colour, gender, nationality, religion or political belief. Factors such as unemployment, cultural or social conditions of the offender should not influence the sentence in a discriminatory way.
7.
Courts should take into account the probable impact of the sentence on the individual offender.2
The Committee has concluded that to allow courts a relatively free choice to impose sentences motivated by deterrence, reformation, desert, incapacitation, etc, is likely to produce subjective disparity in sentencing. The Committee does not believe that pursuit of a single aim of sentencing is the only way to achieve consistency; nor does it believe that pursuit of a single aim would necessarily achieve consistency, because it might produce disparity by requiring different types of case to be sentenced in a similar way. The Committee recognises that certain types of case might require different approaches, and therefore ... it urges member states to attempt to identify the classes of case which might be approached on different principles.3
1.
Maximum penalties for offences and, where applicable, minimum penalties should be reviewed so that they form a coherent structure which reflects the relative seriousness of different types of offence.
2.
The range of available sentences for an offence should not be so wide as to afford little guidance to courts on its relative seriousness. States, therefore, should consider the grading of offences into degrees of seriousness, provided, however, that minimum penalties, where applicable, should not prevent the court from taking account of particular circumstances in the individual case.4
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=383 |
Examination of the replies to the Committee's questionnaire has shown that many member states have penalty scales which have not undergone systematic revision for 50 or even 100 years. Since penalty scales should give guidance on the relative seriousness of different types of offence, principled revision of maximum penalties could make a significant contribution to greater consistency in sentencing. The Committee has also formed the view that wide penalty scales for offences (e.g., a single offence of theft) may contribute to disparity in sentencing, by allowing sentences for minor offences to escalate within the high overall maximum. The Committee is aware that any revision of penalty scales may have consequences for various procedural provisions which are linked to maximum penalties (e.g., powers of arrest).
The second part of the recommendation deals, in general language, with the two problems of (i) wide penalty scales for individual offences; and, (ii) a wide range of non-custodial sentences the paradox that attempts to find alternatives to imprisonment have often produced a proliferation of new measures and a concomitant reduction in consistency.5
1.
The factors taken into account in aggravation or in mitigation of sentence should be compatible with the declared aim or aims of sentencing.
2.
The major aggravating and mitigating factors should be clarified in law or legal practice. Wherever possible, the law or practice should also attempt to define those factors which should not be considered relevant in respect of certain offences.6
This recommendation aims to reduce inconsistency in sentencing by drawing attention to, and excluding, certain possible sources of disparity which the Committee has noted. It affirms the general connection between the aims of sentencing and the aggravating and mitigating factors.7
1.
Recidivism should not, at any stage in the criminal justice system, be used mechanically as a factor working against the defendant.
2.
Although it may be justifiable to take account of the offender's previous criminal record within the declared aim(s) of sentencing, the sentence should be kept in proportion to the seriousness of the current offence(s).
3.
The effect of recidivism should depend on the particular characteristics
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=384 |
of the offender's prior record. Thus, any effect of previous criminality should be reduced or nullified where:
|
4
There should be a coherent policy with regard to the relevance of discontinued proceedings, foreign judgments, amnesty, pardon or time-barred offences.8
This recommendation aims to promote consistency by ensuring that the principle of proportionality of sentence to the seriousness of the offence prevails over any aggravating effect of previous convictions. The imposition of substantial sentences on recidivists convicted of minor crimes goes against the policy of restraint in the use of imprisonment, as well as fostering inconsistency. The recommendation also states what is now the best practice among judges, which is to carry out a qualitative assessment of the criminal record of each offender before sentencing.9
1.
Courts should in general state concrete reasons for imposing sentences. In particular, specific reasons should be given when a custodial sentence is imposed.
2.
What counts as a reason is a concrete motivation which relates the particular sentence either to the declared aim(s) of sentencing or to the normal range of sentences for the type of crime.10
This recommendation stems from the Committee's conclusion that the obligation to give reasons for sentences may make a significant contribution to greater consistency in sentencing, particularly when combined with greater certainty about the aims of sentencing and with appellate review of sentences. The Committee also regards the giving of reasons for sentence as important in explaining sentences to the public and the offender, and thereby increasing public
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=385 |
understanding of and confidence in sentencing. The Committee does not recommend reason-giving as mandatory for all sentences, since it recognises that the need for speed and efficiency in criminal justice may outweigh the value of reason-giving in some types of case, especially the most minor. It attempts to emphasise the importance of reason-giving to legal values and to consistency in sentencing, whilst recognising the extra burdens it might place upon judges.11
1.
The principle of prohibition of reformatio in peius should be observed so that, where only the defendant appeals against sentence, the court must not increase the sentence on such appeal.
2.
The powers of prosecutors to use their right to appeal should not undermine the principle of reformatio in peius, thereby deterring offenders from appealing.12
This recommendation is designed to eliminate the unfairness which the Committee finds to be inherent in the power to increase sentence on an appeal by a defendant, which may operate to deter the pursuit of justified appeals by offenders. It remains to be discussed whether we should go further in recommending the abolition of accessory appeals by the prosecutor, since they too might place offenders under pressure not to pursue justified appeals. It is to be noted that this recommendation goes against consistency in sentencing (insofar as it prevents an appeal court from rectifying an unduly lenient sentence in this type of case). It does so in order to preserve the higher value of individual fairness, but it may be questioned whether the recommendation lies within our terms of reference.13
In principle, time spent in custody before trial or before appeal should count towards the sentence. There should be a coherent policy with regard to time spent in custody abroad.
Arrangements should be made to ensure that judges are regularly provided with information about the operation of the criminal justice system, and that they have the opportunity to attend seminars and conferences on sentencing, on a regular basis.
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=386 |
1.
Sentencing statistics should be compiled and presented in a way which is informative to judges, particularly in respect of sentencing levels for relatively quantifiable offences (for example, drunk driving, thefts from supermarkets).
2.
Statistics should be compiled so as to ensure that they give sufficient details to measure and to counter inconsistency in sentencing, for example by linking the use of particular penalties to types of offences.
3.
Research into sentencing should be encouraged in order to provide more detailed data, both for the information of judges and in order to identify disparity.14
This recommendation is designed to ensure that the aims and principles of sentencing adopted in a member state are put into effect by a well-informed judiciary. The Committee believes that some of the sentencing statistics which are now available in some member states are not presented in a form which maximises their usefulness to the courts. Collection and compilation of the necessary statistics may require a review of existing arrangements for producing sentencing statistics and may require further empirical research to be carried out, but the Committee believes that these are important steps towards the achievement of greater consistency.15
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=387 |
GUIDELINE PROTOTYPE
I. Offence: |
Manslaughter s219, Criminal Code |
II. Maximum: |
12 Years |
III. Presumptive Disposition: |
Presumption of Custody (IN) |
IV. Guidelines: |
Range: 46 Years |
(These data reflect sentencing under the current system which includes full release on parole as early as one-third and remission based release after an inmate has served two-thirds of sentence. To get an idea of time actually served by inmates, these sentences must be discounted to a greater degree than would the ranges proposed by the Commission).
Criminal Code sections 215, 217, 219.
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=388 |
Percentiles (m = months, y = years)
Source |
25th |
50th (Median)* |
75th |
90th** |
Correctional Sentences Projects |
3.5y |
5y |
10y |
10y |
Sentencing Commission |
|
5y |
12y |
|
|
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=391 |
GUIDELINE PROTOTYPE
I. Offence: |
Break and Enter\Dwelling-House* s306(1)(d) |
II. Maximum: |
6 Years |
III. Presumptive Disposition: |
Qualified Presumption of Custody (QI) (ie. unless it is not a serious instance of the offence and the offender has no relevant record). |
IV. Guidelines: |
|
Offence |
Description |
Range* |
Break and Enter |
Breaking and entering a private dwelling and committing (or intending to commit) an indictable offence therein |
318 months |
|
or |
|
|
breaking out of a private dwelling after having committed or intending to commit an indictable offence therein |
|
|
(These data reflect sentencing under the current system which includes full release or parole as early as one-third and remission based release after an inmate has served two-thirds of sentence. To get an idea of time actually served by inmates, these sentences must be discounted to a greater degree than would the ranges proposed by the Commission).
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=392 |
Criminal Code sections 306, 306(1), 306(1)(a), 306(1)(b), 306(1)(c), 306(1)(c)(i), 306(1)(c)(ii) (Includes break and enter of dwelling and non-dwelling):
Percentiles (m = months, y = years)
Source |
25th |
50th(Median)* |
75th |
90th** |
Correctional Sentences Project (both dwelling and business premises) |
3m |
6m |
1y |
2y |
Sentencing Commission (both dwelling and business premises) |
|
6m |
|
2y |
|
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=395 |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=396 |
|
In determining the sentence to be imposed upon an offender,
|
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=398 |
Where one sentence is passed on a verdict of guilty on two or more counts of an indictment, the sentence is good if any of the counts would have justified the sentence.
|
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=399 |
1.
The term plea agreement should be defined as meaning any agreement by the accused to plead guilty in return for the prosecutor's agreeing to take or refrain from taking a particular course of action.
2.
The term plea discussion should be defined as meaning a discussion directed toward the conclusion of a plea agreement.
3.
|
4.
|
5.
A prosecutor, police officer or defence counsel should not offer any improper inducement to an accused.
6.
No judicial officer before whom proceedings in respect of the accused are or will be held should offer any inducement for the purpose of encouraging an accused to plead guilty to an offence.4
7.
|
8.
|
9.
Counsel for an accused person should not conclude on the accused's behalf any plea agreement that requires the accused to plead guilty to an offence of which the accused maintains he or she is innocent.7
10.
A prosecutor should not suggest, conclude or participate in any plea agreement that:
|
11.
|
12.
|
13.
Upon being informed that the prosecutor and the accused have concluded a plea agreement, the judge should be able, where he or she considers it necessary to do so, to ascertain by questioning whether the accused understands the substance and consequences of that plea agreement.8
14.
No plea agreement or submission should be binding on a judge.
15.
In any case in which the judge, having been informed of the existence and substance of a plea agreement and of the reasons for that agreement, determines that an accused should not be judicially disposed of in the manner contemplated by the plea agreement, the judge should
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=403 |
inform the accused of this fact.9
16.
Before any guilty plea is accepted from an accused, the judge should be able, where he or she considers it necessary to do so, to ascertain by questioning whether any inducement to plead guilty, other than an inducement disclosed as part of a plea agreement, has been offered to the accused.
17.
In any case in which the prosecutor and the accused have concluded a plea agreement, the judge should be able, before any guilty plea is accepted from the accused, to make such inquiry as he or she considers necessary in order to be satisfied that a factual basis for the accused's guilty plea exists.
18.
In determining whether to accept an accused's plea of guilty to any offence other than the offence charged, the judge should consider the substance of, and reasons for, any plea agreement concluded between the accused and the prosecutor.
19.
The judge should reject an accused's guilty plea if, inter alia, he or she has reasonable grounds to believe:
|
20.
An accused who has entered a guilty plea should be entitled to withdraw that plea before sentence, or to appeal against a conviction based thereon:
|
21.
Where an accused has pleaded guilty to an offence and, upon his or her conviction, has received a sentence that is permitted under the Criminal Code in the circumstances and that accords with, or is within the range anticipated by, a plea agreement, the prosecutor should not be permitted to appeal against the sentence received by the accused unless it is shown:
|
22.
In any case in which the accused has pleaded guilty to an offence in accordance with a plea agreement concluded between the accused and the prosecutor, any proceedings taken subsequently against the accused in contravention of that agreement should be prohibited unless the prosecutor
|
23.
Evidence of a guilty plea, later withdrawn, or of an offer to plead guilty to an offence, or of statements made in connection with any such plea or offer, should be inadmissible on the issue of guilt or credibility in any proceedings.
|
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=406 |
|
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=407 |
(e) Plea Agreement Procedure.
|
Standard 14-3.1. Propriety of plea discussions and plea agreements
|
Standard 14-3.2. Relationship between defence counsel and client
|
Standard 14-3.3. Responsibilities of the judge
|
13.1
The Commission recommends that the interests of the victim in plea negotiations continue to be represented by Crown counsel. To encourage uniformity of practice across Canada, the responsible federal and provincial prosecutorial authorities should develop guidelines which direct Crown counsel to keep victims fully informed of plea negotiations and sentencing proceedings and to represent their views.
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=412 |
13.2
The Commission recommends that, where possible, prior to the acceptance of a plea negotiation, Crown counsel be required to receive and consider a statement of the facts of the offence and its impact upon the victim.
13.3
The Commission recommends that the sentencing judge inquire of the defendant whether he or she understands the plea agreement and its implications and, if he or she does not, the judge should have the discretion to strike the plea or sentence.
13.4
The Commission recommends that federal and provincial prosecutorial authorities collaborate in the formulation of standards or guidelines for police respecting over-charging and/or inappropriate multiple charging.
13.5
The Commission recommends that the relevant federal and provincial authorities give serious consideration to the institution of formalized screening mechanisms to permit, to the greatest extent practicable, the review of charges by Crown counsel prior to their being laid by police.
13.6
The Commission recommends that police forces develop and/or augment internal review mechanisms to enhance the quality of charging decisions and, specifically, to discourage the practice of laying inappropriate charges for the purpose of maximizing a plea bargaining position.
13.7
The Commission recommends that the relevant federal and provincial prosecutorial authorities establish a policy (guidelines) restricting and governing the power of the Crown to reduce charges in cases where it has the means to prove a more serious offence.
13.8
The Commission recommends that the appropriate federal and provincial authorities formulate and attempt to enforce guidelines respecting the ethics of plea bargaining.
13.9
The Commission recommends a mechanism whereby the Crown prosecutor would be required to justify in open court a plea bargain agreement reached by the parties either in private or in chambers unless, in the public interest, such justification should be done in chambers.
13.10
The Commission recommends that the trial or sentencing judge never be a participant in the plea negotiations process. This recommendation is not intended to preclude the judge from having the discretion to indicate, in chambers, the general nature of the disposition or sentence which is likely to be
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=413 |
imposed upon the offender in the event of a plea of guilty.
13.11
The Commission recommends that the Criminal Code be amended to expressly provide that the court is not bound to accept a joint submission or other position presented by the parties respecting a particular charge or sentence.
13.12
The Commission recommends the development of a mechanism to require full disclosure in open court of the facts and considerations which formed the basis of an agreement, disposition or order arising out of a pre-hearing conference.
13.13
The Commission recommends that an in-depth analysis of the nature and extent of plea bargaining in Canada be conducted by the federal and provincial governments or by a permanent sentencing commission.
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=414 |
THE LAW REFORM COMMISSION
Ardilaun Centre
111 St Stephen's Green
Dublin 2
Telephone: 715699
Fax No.: 715316
First Programme for Examination of Certain Branches of the Law with a View to their Reform (Dec 1976) (Prl. 5984) [out of print] [photocopy available] 10p Net]
Working Paper No. 11977, The Law Relating to the Liability of Builders, Vendors and Lessors for the Quality and Fitness of Premises (June 1977) [£ 1.50 Net]
Working Paper No. 21977, The Law Relating to the Age of Majority, the Age for Marriage and Some Connected Subjects (Nov 1977) [out of print] [photocopy available]£ 1.00 Net]
Working Paper No. 31977, Civil Liability for Animals (Nov 1977) [£ 2.50 Net]
First (Annual) Report (1977) (Prl. 6961) [40p Net]
Working Paper No. 41978, The Law Relating to Breach of Promise of Marriage (Nov 1978) [£ 1.00 Net]
Working Paper No. 51978, The Law Relating to Criminal Conversation and the Enticement and Harbouring of a Spouse (Dec 1978) [out of print] [photocopy available] [£ 1.00 Net]
Working Paper No. 61979, The Law Relating to Seduction and the Enticement and Harbouring of a Child (Feb 1979)[£ 1.50 Net]
Working Paper No. 71979, The Law Relating to Loss of Consortium and Loss of Services of a Child (March 1979) [£ 1.00 Net]
Working Paper No. 81979, Judicial Review of Administrative Action: the Problem of Remedies (Dec 1979) [£ 1.50 Net]
Second (Annual) Report (1978/79) (Prl. 8855) [ 75p Net]
Working Paper No. 91980, The Rule Against Hearsay (April 1980) [out of print] [photocopy available] [£ 2.00 Net]
Third (Annual) Report (1980) (Prl. 9733) [ 75p Net]
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=415 |
First Report on Family Law Criminal Conversation, Enticement and Harbouring of a Spouse or Child, Loss of Consortium, Personal Injury to a Child, Seduction of a Child, Matrimonial Property and Breach of Promise of Marriage (LRC 11981) (March 1981) [£ 2.00 Net]
Working Paper No. 101981, Domicile and Habitual Residence as Connecting Factors in the Conflict of Laws (Sep 1981) [£ 1.75 Net]
Fourth (Annual) Report (1981) (PI. 742) [ 75p Net]
Report on Civil Liability for Animals (LRC 21982) (May 1982) [£ 1.00 Net]
Report on Defective Premises (LRC 31982) (May 1982) [£ 1.00 Net]
Report on Illegitimacy (LRC 41982) (Sep 1982) [£ 3.50 Net]
Fifth (Annual) Report (1982) (PL 1795) [ 75p Net]
Report on the Age of Majority, the Age for Marriage and Some Connected Subjects (LRC 51983) (April 1983) [£ 1.50 Net]
Report on Restitution of Conjugal Rights, Jactitation of Marriage and Related Matters (LRC 61983) (Nov 1983) [£ 1.00 Net]
Report on Domicile and Habitual Residence as Connecting Factors in the Conflict of Laws (LRC 71983) (Dec 1983) [£ 1.50 Net]
Report on Divorce a Mensa et Thoro and Related Matters (LRC 81983) (Dec 1983) [£ 3.00 Net]
Sixth (Annual) Report (1983) (PI. 2622) [£ 1.00 Net]
Report on Nullity of Marriage (LRC 91984 (Oct 1984) [£ 3.50 Net]
Working Paper No. 111984, Recognition of Foreign Divorces and Legal Separations (Oct 1984) [£ 2.00 Net]
Seventh (Annual) Report (1984) (PI. 3313) [£ 1.00 Net]
Report on Recognition of Foreign Divorces and Legal Separations (LRC 101985) (April 1985) [£ 1.00 Net]
Report on Vagrancy and Related Offences (LRC 111985) (June 1985) [£ 3.00 Net]
Report on the Hague Convention on the Civil Aspects of International Child Abduction and Some Related Matters (LRC 121985) (June 1985) [£ 2.00 Net]
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=416 |
Report on Competence and Compellability of Spouses as Witnesses (LRC 131985) (July 1985) [£2.50 Net]
Report on Offences Under the Dublin Police Acts and Related Offences (LRC 141985) (July 1985) [£2.50 Net]
Report on Minors' Contracts (LRC 151985) (August 1985) [£3.50 Net]
Report on the Hague Convention on the Taking of Evidence Abroad in Civil or Commercial Matters (LRC 161985) (August 1985) [£2.00 Net]
Report on the Liability in Tort of Minors and the Liability of Parents for Damage Caused by Minors (LRC 171985) (Sep 1985) [£3.00 Net]
Report on the Liability in Tort of Mentally Disabled Persons (LRC 181985) (Sep 1985) [£2.00 Net]
Report on Private International Law Aspects of Capacity to Marry and Choice of Law in Proceedings for Nullity of Marriage (LRC 191985) (Oct 1985) [£3.50 Net]
Report on Jurisdiction in Proceedings for Nullity of Marriage, Recognition of Foreign Nullity Decrees, and the Hague Convention on the Celebration and Recognition of the Validity of Marriages (LRC 201985) (Oct 1985) [£2.00 Net]
Eighth (Annual) Report (1985) (P1. 4281) [£1.00 Net]
Report on the Statute of Limitations: Claims in Respect of Latent Personal Injuries (LRC 211987) (Sep 1987) [£4.50 Net]
Consultation Paper on Rape (Dec 1987) [£6.00 Net]
Report on the Service of Documents Abroad re Civil Proceedings the Hague Convention (LRC 221987) (Dec 1987) [£2.00 Net]
Report on Receiving Stolen Property (LRC 231987) (Dec 1987) [£7.00 Net]
Ninth (Annual) Report (19861987) (PI 5625) [£1.50 Net]
Report on Rape and Allied Offences (LRC 241988) (May 1988) [£3.00 Net]
Report on the Rule Against Hearsay in Civil Cases (LRC 251988) (Sep 1988) [£3.00 Net]
Report on Malicious Damage (LRC 261988) (Sep 1988) [£4.00 Net]
Report on Debt Collection: (1) The Law Relating to Sheriffs (LRC 271988) (Oct 1988) [£5.00 Net]
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=417 |
Tenth (Annual) Report (1988) (PI 6542) [£1.50 Net]
Report on Debt Collection: (2) Retention of Title (LRC 281989) (April 1989) [£4.00 Net]
Report on the Recognition of Foreign Adoption Decrees (LRC 291989) (June 1989) [£5.00 Net]
Report on Land Law and Conveyancing Law: (1) General Proposals (LRC 301989) (June 1989) [£5.00 Net]
Consultation Paper on Child Sexual Abuse (August 1989) [£10.00 Net]
Report on Land Law and Conveyancing Law: (2) Enduring Powers of Attorney (LRC 311989)(Oct 1989) [£4.00 Net]
Eleventh (Annual) Report (1989) (Pl 7448) [£1.50 Net]
Report on Child Sexual Abuse (September 1990) (LRC 321990) [£7.00 Net]
Report on Sexual Offences Against the Mentally Handicapped (September 1990) (LRC 331990) [£4.00 Net]
Report on Oaths and Affirmations (LRC 341990)(December 1990) [£5.00 Net]
Report on Confiscation of the Proceeds of Crime (LRC 351991) (January 1991) [£6.00 Net]
Consultation Paper on the Civil Law of Defamation (March 1991) [£20.00 Net]
Report on the Hague Convention on Succession to the Estates of Deceased Persons (LRC 361991) (May 1991) [£7.00 Net]
Twelfth (Annual) Report (1990) (PI 8292) [£1.50 Net]
Consultation Paper on Contempt of Court (July 1991) [£20.00 Net]
Consultation Paper on the Crime of Libel (August 1991) [£11.00 Net]
Report on The Indexation of Fines (LRC 371991) (October 1991) [£6.50 Net]
Report on The Civil Law of Defamation (LRC 381991) (December 1991) [£7.00 Net]
Report on Land Law and Conveyancing Law: (3) The Passing of Risk from Vendor to Purchaser (LRC 391991) (December 1991); (4) Service of Completion Notices (LRC 401991) (December 1991) [£6.00 Net]
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=418 |
Report on The Crime of Libel (LRC 411991) (December 1991) [£ 4.00 Net]
Report on United Nations (Vienna) Convention on Contracts for the International Sale of Goods 1980 (LRC 421992) (May 1992) [£ 8.00 Net]
Thirteenth (Annual) Report (1991) (PI 9214) [£ 2.00 Net]
Report on The Law Relating to Dishonesty (LRC 431992) (September 1992) [£20.00 Net]
Land Law and Conveyancing Law: (5) Further General Proposals (LRC 441992) (October 1992) [£ 6.00 Net]
THIS IS AN ORIGINAL PAGE-BREAK: |
PAGE NUMBER=419 |