BAILII is celebrating 24 years of free online access to the law! Would you
consider making a contribution?
No donation is too small. If every visitor before 31 December gives just £5, it
will have a significant impact on BAILII's ability to continue providing free
access to the law.
Thank you very much for your support!
[New search]
[Help]
Democracy, Free Speech and TV: the case of the BBC
and the ProLife Alliance
Tom Lewis
Lecturer, Nottingham Law School, Nottingham Trent
University.
I would like to thank Austen Garwood-Gowers, Catherine Lewis, Marc Stauch,
Adrian Walters and Kay Wheat for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of
this paper. Errors and omissions remain my own.
Copyright © Tom Lewis 2004
First Published in Web Journal of Current Legal Issues
Summary
Freedom of political expression generally receives a
very high degree of protection from the courts. Political expression in the
UK’s broadcast media, by comparison, receives far lower levels of
protection. This has been graphically demonstrated recently by the decision of
the House of Lords in R (on the application of the ProLife Alliance) v BBC
in which a majority of their Lordships upheld a refusal by the BBC and
independent broadcasters to transmit a Party Election Broadcast by the ProLife
Alliance, depicting an abortion, prior to the 2001 general election. It will be
argued that this decision is inconsistent with the jurisprudence underlying the
free speech right and with the Article 10 case law of the European Court of
Human Rights. In particular it will be argued that the court failed to have due
regard to the type of expression at issue in the case resulting in an inadequate
assessment of the proportionality of the restriction.
Contents
1.Introduction
On April 20th 2004, for the first time on terrestrial British television,
graphic footage of an abortion was broadcast in the Channel 4 documentary
My
Foetus (see
The Guardian 20 April 2004; 21 April 2004). Three years
previously similar footage was submitted by the ProLife Alliance to terrestrial
broadcasters to be transmitted in the form of a Party Election Broadcast in
the run up to the 2001 General Election. The broadcasters refused to transmit
it on the grounds of taste and decency and this refusal was upheld by the House
of Lords in
R (on the application of ProLife Alliance) v BBC (2003] UKHL 23; [2003] 1 AC 185.
Freedom of political expression generally receives a
very high degree of protection from the law. This is in large part due to its
central role in maintaining effective political democracy. However, when it
comes to what is arguably the most powerful and effective medium of all,
broadcasting, political speech is accorded lower levels of protection than its
alleged importance would seem to warrant. This apparent paradox has been
highlighted and accentuated recently by the decision in the ProLife
case.
The opportunities for political parties or politically
motivated groups in the UK to use the broadcast media to communicate directly
with the public are very limited. Broadcast advertising - paying for airtime -
for political purposes is prohibited by s 321 of the Communications Act 2003
which retains the former prohibition under s 8 and s 92 of the Broadcasting Act
1990. The only way that a political party can use the broadcast media to
communicate its message directly to the electorate is through the Party
Political Broadcast
(PPB).
(1)
Top | Contents | Bibliography
2.The ProLife Alliance Party Election Broadcast
2001
The ProLife Alliance is a political party registered under the Parties, Elections
and Referendums Act 2000. It campaigns on a platform of ‘absolute respect
for innocent human life from the one-cell embryo stage until natural death’.
One of its primary aims is the prohibition of abortion (see
http://www.prolife.org.uk/about/manifesto.htm).
At the 2001 General Election the Alliance put up enough candidates in Wales
to entitle it to a single Party Election Broadcast (PEB) of up to four minutes
and 40 seconds to be screened only in Wales on all terrestrial channels.
(2)
ProLife supplied the BBC with a video to be transmitted
as its PEB. It consisted mainly of ‘prolonged and deeply disturbing
images’ of aborted foetuses: ‘tiny limbs, bloodied and dismembered,
a separated head, their human shape and form plainly recognizable’ (
R
(on the application of ProLife Alliance) v BBC [2002] EWCA Civ 297;
[2002] 3 WLR 1080 per Laws LJ para 13 whose description was adopted by the House
of Lords).
Section 6(1)a of the Broadcasting Act 1990 imposed on
the Independent Television Commission (ITC) a duty to do all it could to ensure
that every service which it licensed complied with the requirement that
‘nothing is included in its programmes which offends against good taste
and decency or is likely to encourage or incite to crime or to lead to disorder
or to be offensive to public
feeling’.
(3) The BBC operates
under a Royal Charter (Cmnd. 3248, 1 May 1996) but faces very similar
obligations under its governing
Agreement.
(4)
Representatives of the BBC and independent broadcasters
viewed ProLife’s tape and concluded that the footage would not comply with
the ‘taste and decency’ standards. In a letter dated 17th May 2001,
containing the views of all the broadcasters, the BBC informed ProLife
that:
some
of the images are unacceptable in themselves because they are likely to be
offensive to public feeling, in particular the images of aborted foetuses
mostly in a ‘mangled and mutilated state’. . . Some images . . .
could in principle be acceptable depending on the context . . . What is
unacceptable . . . is the cumulative effect of several minutes primarily devoted
to such images . . . None of the broadcasters regarded this as a case at the
margin. (quoted by Lord Hoffmann at para 44)
ProLife offered the concession that the PEB be broadcast after 10 pm, with
a warning for viewers, but the broadcasters judged that the images were ‘so
offensive that it would not be appropriate to take that course in this case’.
ProLife responded by submitting two toned down versions of the video, neither
of which was acceptable on the grounds of taste and decency. Eventually a fourth
version, with a blank screen with only the word ‘CENSORED’ and a
voice over was transmitted on 2 June 2001. In the election on the 7 June the
six ProLife candidates in Wales received a total of 1609 votes, or 0.117% of
the votes cast in the principality (Geddis 2002, p 618).
Top | Contents | Bibliography
3. The ProLife litigation
ProLife applied for judicial review of the
broadcaster’s refusal (
R (on the application of the ProLife Alliance) v
BBC [2001] EWHC Admin 607). Permission was refused on 24 May 2001.
ProLife’s appeal was upheld (
R (on the application of the ProLife
Alliance) v BBC (
[2002] EWCA Civ 297;
[2002] 3 WLR 1080) although only after
the 2001 General Election had taken place (for comment see Geddis 2002). The
Court of Appeal held that both the common law and Article 10 of the European
Convention of Human Rights placed the very highest importance on freedom of
speech at election time and whilst there may be instances, even at election
time, when political speech may be justifiably censored on grounds of taste and
offensiveness, it would take a ‘very extreme
case’.
(5)
A majority of the House of Lords upheld the
broadcaster’s appeal.
(6) The
majority identified two separate and distinct questions arising in the case.
Firstly whether PEBs were subject to standards of taste and decency at all; and
secondly, if they were, whether the broadcasters had properly applied those
standards (see Lord Nicholls at para 9, Lord Hoffmann at para 49 and Lord Walker
at para 125). In their judgment only the second of these questions was properly
before the court, because ProLife had conceded that the offensive material
restriction was not in itself necessarily an infringement of Article 10 (Lord
Nicholls at para 10). A majority of their Lordships found that the Court of
Appeal had fallen into error by failing to distinguish these two questions and
had wrongly considered the first – whether the standards of taste and
decency applied to PEBs at all. It had carried out its own balancing exercise
between the requirements of freedom of political speech and the protection of
the public from being unduly distressed in their own homes. That was not a
legitimate exercise for the courts in this case. Parliament had decided where
the balance should be held and had decreed that the offensive material ban
applied without distinction to all television programmes, including party
broadcasts. In the absence of a successful claim that the offensive material
restriction was not compatible with the Convention rights of the ProLife
Alliance, it was not for the courts to find that the broadcasters acted
unlawfully when they did no more than give effect to their legal obligations
(Lord Nicholls at para 16). Indeed they should be accorded a degree of
deference due to their expertise and the fact that they carried out audience
research and were in touch with the expectations of their likely audience (Lord
Hoffmann at para 80).
It will be argued below that the House of Lord’s decision undervalues
the importance of freedom of political expression in a way which runs counter
to the philosophy which underpins the free speech right and the clear jurisprudence
of the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR). To this end the philosophical
underpinnings of the free speech right and the ECHR jurisprudence will briefly
be summarized. Thereafter the House of Lord’s decision will be critiqued.
Top | Contents | Bibliography
4. Freedom of expression: the philosophical
underpinnings
Various arguments have been advanced justifying the
existence of a right to freedom of expression over the last 150 years. Foremost
amongst these have been the arguments from truth, self-fulfilment and democracy
(see Schauer 1980; Barendt 1985, ch 1). The argument from truth is famously
associated with John Stuart Mill’s
On Liberty of 1859. Mill argued
that the pursuit of truth was of overriding importance for the development of
society and the best way to arrive at the truth is to allow freedom of
discussion and debate (see Mill 1980; Schauer 1980, ch 2; Barendt 1985, pp
10-14).
(7)
The argument from self-fulfilment asserts that freedom
both to impart and receive ideas and arguments is a vital part of each
individual’s right to self-development and fulfilment. People will only
be able to maximise their potential as human beings if they are free to express
and have expressed to them, ideas, beliefs and arguments (Schauer 1980 ch 4;
Barendt 1985 pp 14 – 20; Scanlon
1977).
(8)
Perhaps the most accessible and powerful argument is
that from democracy. In its historical origins it is particularly associated
with Alexander Meiklejohn. (Meiklejohn 1961;1965) He argued that in order for
citizens in a democracy to be able effectively to exercise their democratic
responsibilities they must have free access to information and arguments about
politicians and their policies. Furthermore it is only the freedom to criticise
government that makes it effectively accountable to the electorate.
It is the argument from democracy that has found most
favour in the courts in the USA under the First Amendment (see for example
New York Times v Sullivan 376 US 254 (1964)), in the case law of the
ECHR and in the UK (see for example
Derbyshire County Council v Times
Newspapers Ltd [1993] AC 534). Lord Steyn in
R v Secretary of State for
the Home Department ex parte Simms [2000] 2 AC 115 at p 126 put it
thus:
Freedom
of speech is the lifeblood of democracy. The free flow of information and ideas
informs political debate. It is a safety valve: people are more ready to accept
decisions that go against them if they can in principle seek to influence them.
It acts as a brake on the abuse of power by public officials. It facilitates the
exposure of errors in the governance and administration of justice of the
country.
Thus one of the main justifications for a strong free speech right is that
it is seen as a
sine qua non of democratic society.
Top | Contents | Bibliography
5. Article 10 ECHR – The Right to Freedom of
Expression
Article 10 of the ECHR protects freedom of expression.
The European Court has repeatedly stressed its importance. For example in
Handyside v UK (1979-80) 1 EHRR 737 para 49 it stated:
Freedom
of expression constitutes one of the essential foundations of [democratic]
society, one of the basic conditions for its progress and for the development of
every man.
Thus the justifications for strong protection of freedom
of expression stressed by the Strasbourg jurisprudence centre on its role in the
protection and fostering of democracy and in its role as a necessary
prerequisite of individual self-fulfilment.
It is clear from the case law of the European Court that
the degree of protection afforded will very much depend on the subject matter of
the expression at issue. There is an apparent hierarchy or gradation of
expression, with political or journalistic expression involving the public
interest at the top (see for example
Lingens v Austria (1986) 8 EHRR 103;
Castells v Spain (1992) 14 EHRR 445;
Thorgeir Thorgeirson v Iceland
(1992) 14 EHRR 843), artistic expression somewhere below this (see for
example
Muller v Switzerland (1991) 13 EHRR 212;
Otto-Preminger-Institute v Austria (1995) 19 EHRR 34;
Wingrove v UK
(1997) 24 EHRR 1) and commercial speech towards the bottom (see for example
Markt Intern Verlag GmbH and Klaus Beerman v Germany (1989) 12 EHRR
161).
This spectrum is evident in the degree to which states
are permitted to restrict expression. Paragraph 2 of Article 10 permits the
state to impose restrictions as long as they conform to the tripartite
requirements set out within it: that they are ‘prescribed by law’;
are intended to meet one of the legitimate aims listed; and are ‘necessary
in a democratic society’ in that they correspond to a pressing social
need, are proportionate and the reasons given for the restrictions are relevant
and sufficient.
The Strasbourg organs have afforded states a margin of
appreciation, or a degree of latitude, on the question of what limitations they
decide to impose on expression under Article 10(2). A degree of discretion is
left to the state as to what restrictions on freedom of expression are
‘necessary in [its] democratic society’ (see Jones 1995; Yourow
1996; Mahoney 1997; Lester 1998). In Handyside para 48 the Court stated
that this doctrine is based upon the premise that:
(b]y
reason of their continuous contact with the vital forces of their countries,
State authorities are in principle in a better position than the international
judge to give an opinion on the exact content of these requirements as well as
on the ‘necessity’ of a ‘restriction’ or
‘penalty’ intended to meet them.
The doctrine has been applied in a variable way
depending on what type of expression is at issue. This in turn is dictated by
whether there exists a pan-European consensus on the importance of the
expression. Thus in cases of artistic expression in which restrictions have been
imposed for the protection of morals (for example Muller) or to protect
the ‘rights of others’ (for example Otto-Preminger) or to
control commercial speech (for example Markt Intern) where such consensus
is apparently lacking, the margin afforded to states has been
wide.
Where there is a Europe wide consensus the margin
afforded to the state will be narrow. Political expression is said to be vital
to the maintenance of that democratic society that is central to the whole ethos
of the Convention itself (see Mowbray
1999).
(9)
Political speech has received a very high degree of
protection from the European Court due to its importance in maintaining
democracy. The Court has stressed repeatedly that ‘freedom of political
debate is at the very core of the concept of democratic society which prevails
throughout the Convention’ (see for example Lingens para
42).
Expression at election time is of particular importance.
In
Bowman v UK (1998) 26 EHRR 1 para 42, a case concerning expenditure
limits placed on persons other than candidates at election time, the Court
said:
Freedom
of expression is one of the ‘conditions’ necessary to ensure the
free expression of the opinion of the people in the choice of the legislature .
. . For this reason, it is particularly important in the period preceding an
election that opinions and information of all kinds are permitted to circulate
freely.
It is not just narrow, party political expression which
falls within this higher echelon. The Court stated in Thorgeirson para
64 that ‘there is no warrant in its case law for distinguishing . . .
between political discussion and discussion of other matters of public
concern’.
The European Court of Human Rights has recently
considered the question of broadcast political expression, in the form of
advertising, in
VgT Verein Gegen Tierfabriken v Switzerland (2002) 34 EHRR 4. Swiss law contained a prohibition on broadcasting political advertising
(Federal Radio and Television Act s 18). The applicant, a vegetarian
organisation, produced a short film contrasting the lives of pigs living in the
forest with those kept under factory farming conditions, followed by the
injunction ‘eat less meat, for the sake of your health, the animals and
the environment’. The Swiss broadcaster refused to screen the film on the
ground that it was a ‘political’ advertisement and the Swiss Federal
court upheld the ban noting inter alia that it helped to prevent financially
powerful groups from obtaining political advantage, to protect public opinion
from undue commercial influence and to protect editorial independence from
‘powerful political advertising sponsors’ (para
21).
The organisation applied to the European Court claiming
a breach of Article 10. On the key question of whether the ban was
‘necessary in a democratic society’ the Court made the point that
the Swiss authorities did have a certain margin of appreciation on the question
of whether there was a pressing social need to restrict the broadcast of an
advertisement. Indeed the margin was ‘particularly essential in commercial
matters, especially in an area as complex and fluctuating as
advertising’(para 69). But the expression here was not regular commercial
advertising in the sense that it was intended to persuade the public to buy a
particular product. Rather it ‘reflected controversial opinions
pertaining to modern society in general’. Indeed the very reason the
advert was banned by the Swiss authorities was because it was regarded as
‘political’ (para 70). Because of this the State’s margin of
appreciation must necessarily be reduced, for what was at stake was ‘not a
given individual’s purely commercial interests, but his participation in a
debate affecting the general interest’ (para 71). Given that the reasons
for the ban were that it was intended to prevent wealthy commercial groups from
skewing the political process, and given that the organisation here was
evidently not such a group, those reasons cannot have been ‘relevant and
sufficient’ to justify this particular restriction (para 75). Further,
there was no prohibition of political advertising in the print media. This
disparity may have been due to the more intrusive nature of the broadcast media
but the Court said that it must mean that the prohibition cannot have been of a
‘particularly pressing nature’ (para 74). Thus the ban constituted
a breach of VgT’s Article 10 rights.
It is interesting to compare the subsequent case of
Murphy v Ireland (2004) 38 EHRR 13 in which the European Court considered
the Irish ban on broadcast religious advertising. The Court noted that a
‘wider margin of appreciation is generally available when regulating
expression in relation to matters liable to offend intimate personal convictions
within the sphere of morals or, especially religion’ (para 67). Indeed it
was this margin which distinguished
Murphy from
VgT and resulted
in the Court finding there to be no violation of Article 10.
Under Article 10, therefore, political expression is afforded a very high
degree of protection by the European Court, over and above that afforded to
other types of speech. Indeed the ideal of pluralist democracy of which freedom
of expression is a vital component is central to the European Convention (Bullinger
1985). It is implicit in the Convention that the courts are the guardians of
democracy. Thus, according to the principles sketched out above, a state is
accorded only a very narrow margin of appreciation when it comes to deciding
what restrictions on political expression are ‘necessary in [its] democratic
society’.
Top | Contents | Bibliography
6. Party Broadcasts, Freedom of Speech and Judicial
Deference
Since the Human Rights Act 1998 (HRA) has been in force
a kind of domestic counterpart of the Strasbourg ‘margin of
appreciation’ doctrine has emerged: a so called ‘doctrine of
deference’ whereby judges will defer either because of the democratic
credentials of the decision maker, or because the decision falls outside their
recognized area of competence, for example in national security, social policy
or economic areas (see
R v DPP ex parte Kebilene [2000] 2 AC 326 per
Lord Hope at 380-1;
International Transport Roth GmbH v Secretary of
State for the Home Department [2002] EWCA Civ 158;
[2002] 3 WLR 344 per
Laws LJ at 376 – 8, Singh 1999; Craig 2001; Edwards 2002; Nicol
2002; Klug 2003).
Given the position at Strasbourg outlined above one
would have expected that the degree of deference to be shown by the court to a
decision maker purporting to restrict political expression would be very
limited. Laws LJ said at the Court of Appeal stage in ProLife para
36:
The
courts owe a special responsibility to the public as constitutional guardian of
the freedom of political debate. This . . . is most acute at the time and in
the context of a . . . general election. It has its origin in a deeper truth,
which is that the courts are ultimately the trustees of our democracy’s
framework . . . Freedom of expression is plainly . . . a constitutional right,
and its enjoyment by an accredited political party in an election contest must
call, if anything for especially heightened protection. (emphasis added)
The majority of the House of Lords disagreed. Both
Lords Hoffmann (at paras 74-77) and Walker (at paras 132-144) commented at
length upon the doctrine of deference. Lord Hoffmann in fact disavowed the use
of the term ‘deference’ with its ‘overtones of servility, or
perhaps gracious concession’. He emphasized that the question ‘of
which branch of government has in any particular instance the decision making
power and what the legal limits of that power are is one of law for the courts
to decide.’ Principles of law dictate which areas are more appropriate
for legislative or judicial decision making. Thus ‘when a court decides
that a decision is within the proper competence of the legislature or executive
it is not showing deference. It is deciding the law’. (For comment on this
aspect of the case see Jowell 2003). With regard to the taste and decency
obligations, he said (at para 77):
the
decision to make all broadcasts subject to taste and decency requirements
represents Parliament’s view that . . . ‘public opinion
cannot be totally disregarded in the pursuit of liberty’. That seems to me
an entirely proper decision for Parliament as representative of the
people to make. (emphasis added)
However Lord Hoffmann did not explain why this is an
appropriate area for Parliament to have the last word or, indeed, what
‘principle of law’ dictated that it was. In fact it is at least
arguable that in this type of case the views of Parliament should not be
absolutely determinative. If the role of the court as ‘constitutional
guardian of the freedom of political debate’ is to be taken
seriously,
(10)
indeed if it is to have any such role at all, the views
of Parliament cannot be determinative in all situations. If Parliament, in
modern British society, does indeed derive its legitimacy from its democratic
credentials then there must be some decisions which are off limits: in short
ones inimical to the very underlying principles of democracy itself (see Laws
1993; Woolf 1995; Allan 2001; cf Griffith 2000; Ekins
2003).
The approach of the Court of Appeal was criticized as
being ‘fundamentalist’ (Lord Hoffmann at para 72). There were hints
of accusations that unelected male judges were ‘rewriting’
Parliamentary instructions to meet their personal and idiosyncratic
views.
(11) Nonetheless, as the Court
of Appeal recognized, this was a case in which the legislature had required
(albeit obliquely) broadcasters to restrict the way in which a registered
political party put its message across to the electorate at election time.
Parliament, dominated as it is by the old traditional monolithic groupings with
scant representation by single issue parties, is hardly a disinterested mover in
this area. If ever there was an example of a subject area where courts should
show a minimum of deference to legislative action then the interference with
freedom of speech at election time is surely one.
As noted above, the Strasbourg case law points clearly
to a hierarchy of expression. The degree of protection to be afforded, and the
degree of deference to be accorded, to those seeking to restrict it depends on
the type of speech at stake and the precise context of the case. The approach
of the Court of Appeal (Laws LJ at para 37 and Simon Brown LJ at para 63) and
Lord Scott acknowledges this. Lord Scott, in his dissenting speech, put it thus
(at para 65):
The
[taste and decency restrictions] were drafted so as to be capable of application
to all programmes, whether light entertainment, serious drama, historical or
other documentaries, news reports, party political programmes or whatever. But
material that might be required to be rejected in one type of programme might
be unexceptionable in another. The judgment of the decision maker would
need to take into account the type of programme of which the material formed
part as well as the audience at which the programme was directed. (emphasis
added)
The adoption of such a nuanced approach was precluded by
the majority of the House of Lords by their finding that the Court of Appeal had
‘fallen into error’ by failing to distinguish the questions of,
firstly, whether PEBs were subject to standards of taste and decency at all and,
secondly, if they were, whether the broadcasters correctly applied those
standards. It had considered the first of these questions but, their Lordships
held, should not have done so because ProLife had not sought to argue that PEBs
could never be subject to such standards at all (Lord Nicholls paras 9 -10; Lord
Hoffmann para 49). The only question that was properly before the court was
whether the broadcasters had applied the right standards. Given that
‘Parliament [had] imposed this restriction on broadcasters and [had]
chosen to apply this restriction as much to party broadcasts as to other
programmes’ (Lord Nicholls para 12) then the broadcasters did not have any
choice but to apply them. Thus the majority said that, because the taste and
decency standards were not a breach of Article 10 per se, it simply
became a question of whether the broadcasters applied their legal instructions
correctly (Lord Nicholls para 16; Lord Hoffmann para 50).
But just because ProLife did not claim that the
application of standards of taste and decency to PEBs was a beach of
Article 10 per se, did not mean that it could not potentially be on this
particular occasion. As Lord Scott put it, the case is ‘fact
sensitive’ and it was the specific application of the standards to this
particular broadcast that was being challenged (para 92):
The
requirement that broadcasts should not offend good taste and decency or be
offensive to public feeling is not necessarily an Article 10 breach in relation
to party election broadcasts any more than it is in relation to programmes
generally. The issue therefore is . . . a narrow one. It is whether the
rejection by the broadcasters of this particular programme, the purpose
of which was to promote the cause of the Alliance at the forthcoming general
election was a lawful application by the broadcasters of the conditions by which
they were bound. To put the point another way, was their rejection of the
Alliances’ desired programme necessary in a democratic society for the
protection of the right of homeowners that offensive material should not be
transmitted into their homes? (emphasis added)
The majority applied Article 10 globally in deciding
whether the standards were a breach of Article 10 at all. The decision that
they were not, (or that they did not need to decide because the issue was not
argued before them) meant that it became simply a question of whether the
broadcasters applied the standards as they saw fit (taking due account of their
expertise) with scant recognition given to the category of expression with which
they were dealing. The approach of the majority in effect allowed the context
and type of expression to be ignored – an approach surely at odds with the
well established jurisprudence of the European Court.
It may be that the expression in ProLife was
difficult to categorise in simple terms - for the graphic depiction of foetuses
might more usually be associated with shocking art than political speech as in
the case of R v Gibson [1990] 2 QB 619 (see Lewis 2002). This indeed may
explain some of the judicial unease reflected in the starkly different
approaches adopted by the courts. However, whilst there was a superficial
similarity to other categories of speech, it is clear that the video in
ProLife was of an essentially political nature in exactly the same way
that the pig film in VgT, whilst superficially an example of commercial
expression, was found by the European Court to be in substance,
political.
There are hints in their Lordship’s speeches that
the PEB in this case was not really bona fide political expression; that somehow
ProLife had perpetrated an underhand manoeuvre in order to be able to secure a
platform – the highly prized PEB (Lord Hoffmann at paras 68 – 70;
Lord Walker at para 124). Lord Hoffmann said that the ProLife PEB was (para
68)
quite
unrelated to the specific policy of encouraging an informed choice at the ballot
box. Their views were of electoral concern, at any rate theoretically, to
voters in only six of the Welsh constituencies. And the results, which were not
wholly unpredictable, showed that they were of concern to very few of those
voters. In any case, abortion is not, in this country, a party political issue.
It has, for many years been the practice to allow members of Parliament a free
vote on such issues . . . The Alliance broadcast had virtually nothing to do
with the fact that a general election was taking place. The election merely gave
it an opportunity to publicise its views in a way which would have been no more
or less effective at any other
time.
(12)
There is a certain irony in this suggestion. In particular, as noted above,
the majority of the House of Lords criticized the Court of Appeal for second
guessing the views of the broadcasters – of acting in the capacity of
primary decision maker thus overstepping their proper constitutional role in
a ‘fundamentalist’ way. But surely Lord Hoffmann’s approach
runs the risk of the court second guessing the views of the electorate themselves.
How is the court equipped to determine what is and what is not a relevant issue
to be put before the electorate in a general election? Lord Hoffmann made the
point that ProLife received only a very few votes and secured no seats –
but so what? This is simply to use hindsight to evidence the lack of nexus between
the election and the views of ProLife. Moreover there is something of a ‘chicken
and egg’ problem posed by this approach. Small political parties campaign
on single issues which nevertheless are of major public concern – but
without access to the mass media at election time to put their views across
in the most effective manner possible it is difficult to see how they will ever
be able to garner a greater share of the vote than that recounted by Lord Hoffmann.
Top | Contents | Bibliography
7. Double jeopardy in broadcast speech?
One of the major changes supposedly effected by the HRA
has been the adoption of proportionality as a ground of judicial review in human
rights cases (see
R (o/a Daly) v Secretary of State for the Home Department
[2001] UKHL 26;
[2001] 2 WLR 1622 especially the comments of Lord Steyn at
paras 27-8). Thus, as noted above, where the right to freedom of expression is
interfered with by a public authority this must be necessary in a democratic
society in the pursuit of a legitimate aim. It must correspond to a
‘pressing social need’ and the reasons given for the interference
must be ‘relevant and sufficient’. Lord Scott and the Court of
Appeal adopted this approach holding that any restriction or interference with
the ProLife Alliance’s election broadcast must meet the requirements of
Article 10(2). Lord Scott reasoned as follows (paras 85-87) - Article 10
guarantees the right to freedom of expression which includes ‘freedom . .
. to . . . impart information and ideas without interference by public
authority’. Paragraph 1 expressly permits the licensing of broadcasting
by the state. Therefore it was ‘not open to anyone to make private
arrangements for the programmes of their choice’. If the context were
purely that of private law, the Article would not apply - thus those who write
books or plays cannot use Article 10 to insist on them being published or
performed. But broadcasting is different – licenses are required by public
authority and ‘licenses are granted on conditions that impose restrictions
as to the contents of programmes that can be broadcast. So Article 10 is
engaged’. Therefore the restrictions that may be imposed must meet the
criteria set down in 10(2) - they must be necessary in a democratic society and
be in the interests of one of the specified aims – otherwise they will
breach Article 10.
It was generally accepted by both the Court of Appeal
and the House of Lords that a restriction in order to prevent offence to public
feeling could fall within the ‘rights of others’ category in 10(2)
– these rights need not be legal rights still less Convention
rights.
(13) And it was accepted
that there was nothing to exempt PEBs from standards of taste and decency. So
the question hinged on whether the specific restriction in the case - the
rejection of the ProLife Alliance’s desired broadcast, was
‘necessary in a democratic society for the protection of the right of
home-owners that offensive material should not be transmitted into their
homes?’(Lord Hoffmann para 92). In Lord Scott’s opinion it was not.
For the broadcaster’s decision could not have been reached without fatally
undervaluing two factors: firstly the fact that the programme was to be a party
election broadcast; and secondly the fact that the only relevant criterion for a
justifiable rejection on offensiveness grounds was that it was necessary for the
protection of the right of homeowners not to be subjected to offensive material
in their own homes. It was factually accurate and not sensationalized and was
relevant to a lawful policy upon which candidates were standing for
election.
The recent European Court cases of VgT and
Murphy would seem to lend support to this approach. In referring to its
own ‘supervisory jurisdiction’ in VgT the Court stressed that
its supervision was not (para 68)
limited
to ascertaining whether the respondent state exercised its discretion
reasonably, carefully and in good faith; what the Court has to do is to look at
the interference . . . in the light of the case as a whole and determine whether
it was proportionate to the legitimate aim pursued and whether the reasons
adduced by the national authorities were relevant and
sufficient.
In Murphy para 66 the Court said
that
(n]o
restriction on freedom of expression . . . can be compatible with Article 10
unless it satisfies, inter alia, the test of necessity as required by the second
paragraph of that Article.
This then is the self-perceived role of the European
court – an international tribunal distanced from what it described in
Handyside as the ‘vital forces’ of countries (para 48).
The approach of the majority of the House of Lords
however was fundamentally at variance with this approach. Lord Hoffmann said
that the primary right protected by Article 10 is the right of ‘every
citizen not to be prevented from expressing his opinions’ (para 55). In
this case the primary right was not engaged at all. For ProLife was not
actually prevented from doing anything. ‘It enjoyed the same free speech
as every other citizen’ (para 57). Indeed by virtue of its access to PEBs
it had more opportunities than most to get its views across - Parliament had
required that broadcasters allow political parties to have air time for PEBs
subject to conditions as to qualification and contents - but there was ‘no
human right to use a television channel’(para
57).
(14) Article 10 may have some
application – but it was not so as to confer a right to a PEB in the first
place (para 58):
The
nature of the right in such cases . . . instead of being a right not to be
prevented from expressing one’s opinions, . . . becomes a right to fair
consideration for being afforded the opportunity to do so; a right not to have
one’s access to public media denied on discriminatory, arbitrary or
unreasonable
grounds.
(15)
The Court of Appeal had treated the case as if it
involved the primary right not to be prevented from expressing one’s
political views and had concluded that questions of taste and decency were not
adequate ground for censorship. This approach was mistaken. The correct
approach was to ask whether the requirements of taste and decency were a
discriminatory, arbitrary or unreasonable condition for allowing a political
party free access at election time to a particular medium, namely television
(para 62).
Lord Hoffmann was therefore able elegantly to sidestep
the need to undertake a full proportionality review of the
broadcaster’s actions – of whether the restrictions they imposed
were really necessary in a democratic society to prevent people being offended
in their homes. Instead the standard of review was the lower one of
reasonableness, rationality and absence of discrimination. Thus he was able to
adopt a ‘business as usual’ approach and easily consign the decision
making power to the broadcasters.
The problem with this approach is that it tends to
relegate broadcast expression to a kind of second division in which it can be
restricted on less pressing and convincing grounds than other forms of speech.
This is an area which is already subject to strict state licensing requirements.
After all no one is free to set up and operate their own broadcasting system. So
there is something of a double jeopardy here. If you want to communicate via
the broadcast media you cannot do so without a licence. Thus your freedom of
expression is restricted. But then, according to Lord Hoffmann, by virtue of
this very restriction, the degree of protection to be derived from Article 10 is
reduced still further. If the state wants to restrict broadcast expression it
only needs to show that it has not acted unreasonably, arbitrarily or in a
discriminatory manner, rather than showing that the restriction was
‘necessary in a democratic society’.
Lord Hoffmann summed up his position with the aphorism
that there was ‘no human right to be invited to the party and it [was] not
unreasonable for Parliament to provide that those invited should behave
themselves’ (para 73). It might be ventured that this is only because the
state had already stepped in to prevent people holding their own parties! (Or
perhaps, to push the analogy a little too far, allows certain political groups
to hold their own parties [in that it allows them broadcast time] but does not
allow them to have music and dancing of their choice [in that they are
restricted as to how they convey their message!])
The Strasbourg cases VGT and Murphy
concerned access to broadcasting facilities in the first place and in them the
European Court saw its role as ascertaining whether the government’s bans
on political and religious advertising were proportionate – were they
necessary in a democratic society? ProLife concerned not access in the
first place but restriction once access had, in principle, been granted.
Indeed stress was placed by the majority upon the fact that ProLife were not
prevented from expressing themselves (indeed they were given more opportunities
than most to do so). Rather, they were prevented from expressing themselves in
the way they wanted. But it is difficult to see why this should have the
consequence of denying ProLife the benefit of full proportionality review.
After all the European Court has repeatedly stressed that ‘Article 10
protects not only the substance of the ideas and information expressed but also
the form in which they are conveyed’ (see Oberschlick v Austria
(1994) 19 EHRR 389 para 57; Jersild v Denmark (1994) 19 EHRR 1 para 31;
News Verlags GmbH & CoKG v Austria (2001) 31 EHRR 246 para 39).
The judges in the Court of Appeal put the point
forcefully:
There
is nothing gratuitous or sensational or untrue in the appellants intended PEB.
It is certainly graphic; and as I have said, disturbing. But if we are to take
political free speech seriously, those characteristics cannot begin to justify
the censorship that was done in this case. Here the image is the message, or a
least an important part of it. Certainly I would accept that the pictures do
not answer the deep philosophical questions which the abortion debate generates.
But they do show what actually happens. I see no answer to the claim that the
appellant is entitled to show - not just tell - what happens. (Laws LJ para
43)
To
campaign for the prohibition of abortion is a legitimate political programme.
The pictures are in a real sense the message. Words alone cannot convey
(particularly to the less verbally adept) the essentially human character of the
foetus and the nature of its destruction by abortion. This video provides a
truthful, factual and . . . unsensational account of the process. (Simon Brown
LJ para 57)
At beginning of the 21st century ‘virtually all significant speech
is mass speech. The soap box orator, the pamphleteer and individual canvassers
now play little part in forming public opinion’ (Barendt 1998). To say
that broadcast speech does not fully engage the primary right to freedom of
expression significantly diminishes the potential efficacy of the broadcast
medium for those who wish to use it to put forward political views.
Top | Contents | Bibliography
8. A ‘tyranny of pleasure’?
Article 10 ECHR ‘is applicable [subject to para 2]
not only to “information” or “ideas” that are favourably
received or regarded as inoffensive or as a matter of indifference, but also to
those that offend, shock or disturb the State or any sector of the population.
Such are the demands of pluralism, tolerance and broadmindedness without which
there is no ‘democratic society”’(Handyside v UK
(1979-80) 1 EHRR 737 para 49).
In Castells v Spain (1992) 14 EHRR 45 (para 42)
the European Court held that this was particularly the case in respect of
elected representatives of the people. By the same token it is arguable that the
expression of those standing for election must also be
protected.
In a mature democracy it is surely right that difficult
and offensive, yet valid, political messages are put to the electorate as free
as possible from anaesthetizing constraints. As Lord Scott put it (para
98):
Voters
in a mature democracy may strongly disagree with a policy being promoted by a
televised party political broadcast but ought not to be offended by the fact
that the policy is being promoted nor, if the promotion is factually accurate
and not sensationalized, by the content of the programme. Indeed in my opinion,
the public in a mature democracy are not entitled to be offended by the
broadcasting of such a programme. A refusal to transmit . . . based on the
belief that it would be ‘offensive to a very large number of
viewers’ (letter of 17 May 2001) would not in my opinion be capable of
being described as ‘necessary in a democratic society . . . for the
protection of . . . rights of others’. Such a refusal would be, on the
contrary, be positively inimical to the values of a democratic society, to which
values it must be assumed that the public adhere.
Indeed it should be remembered that Article 10(1)
expressly protects the right of people to ‘receive information and ideas
without interference’ as well as impart them.
Lord Hoffmann stated (para 70) that the rationale for
the standards of ‘taste and decency’ applying to political as well
as all other broadcasts was that these standards are ‘part of the
country’s cultural life and have created expectations on the part of the
viewers as to what they will and will not be shown on the screens in their
homes’ (see also Lord Nicholls at para 21). In its letter of 17th May 2001
the BBC stated reason for disallowing the broadcast was that it would be
‘offensive to very large numbers of viewers’. Lord Hoffmann (para
32) put store by the fact that the broadcasters do research into their
audience’s tastes – they are in touch. The area of abortion is one
about which ‘public opinion is diverse, sometimes unexpected and in
constant flux’. Therefore broadcasters who take audience surveys are in a
better position than ‘elderly male judges’ to make the call that the
images would be offensive (para 80).
There is surely at least a risk here of instituting what
Professor Barendt has termed a ‘tyranny of pleasure’ (Barendt 1998):
that broadcasters only permit to be transmitted into homes that which is anodyne
and sanitised or, if the material is potentially shocking, that which shocks for
the purpose of providing some kind of thrill. The result of all this is that the
majority only get shown what they want to see.
It is said that there is something different in kind
about the broadcast media in that there is an implied contract between the
viewer and broadcaster – that viewers only let images into their homes on
the understanding that they will not be offended by them (see Lord Hoffmann at
paras 21-22 citing the opinion of Stevens J in Federal Communications
Commission v Pacifica Foundation 438 US 726 (1978)). But in the age of the
remote control and ‘surfing’ between multiple channels the idea of
an unwanted programme bludgeoning its way into the private sanctity of the
living room is anachronistic. This rationale tends to depict viewers as passive
recipients, frozen like rabbits in headlights, unable to turn off images they do
not want to see. Broadcast after 10.00pm, with a prior warning and perhaps a
warning displayed on the screen throughout the transmission there is no reason
why a viewer need be subjected to these images for longer than a few seconds.
One of the broadcaster’s stated reasons for not allowing the broadcast
was the ‘cumulative effect of several minutes’ of the material (BBC’s
letter of 17th May 2001). But if it were prevention of offence that was the
rationale for the refusal to screen the video the ‘cumulative effect’
argument can surely have very little weight. For any viewer likely to be offended
would certainly turn off or switch channels long before the effect became ‘cumulative’.
Top | Contents | Bibliography
9. The Separate but Related Issue of Broadcast
Political Advertising
On 27 July 2003 the Communications Act 2003 received
Royal Assent. In addition to retaining the taste and decency standards, s 321
of the Act also retains the UK’s long standing prohibition on broadcast
‘political’
advertising.
(16)
The Government was adamant that it wished to retain the
ban as it denies ‘powerful interests the chance to skew political debate,
safeguards the public and democratic debate, and protects the impartiality of
broadcasters’ (Tessa Jowell MP, Secretary of State for Culture, Media and
Sport (2002) HC Deb vol 395, col. 788, 3 December
2002).
(17) However, given the
decision of the European Court in
VgT the Government felt unable to make
a statement of compatibility under s 19(1)(b) of the HRA. Instead, very
unusually, a section 19(1)(b) statement had to be made to the effect that the
Government wished to proceed with the Bill even though it was not possible to
make a statement of compatibility.
An analysis of the consequences of the ban on political advertising is beyond
the scope of this paper (for a critique of the arguments used to justify the
ban see Scott 2003). Suffice it to say that it presents a powerful incentive
to challenge by any disgruntled group that wishes to put its (even loosely)
political message across in the broadcast media. Furthermore the continuation
of the ban makes the decision in
ProLife even more objectionable. For
one of the features of the UK system which, it has been argued, distinguishes
it from the Swiss system which was found wanting in
VgT is the fact that
whilst ‘political advertising’ is prohibited in both countries,
the UK has free Party Political Broadcasts which means that it is more likely
to be found to be Article 10 compliant than the Swiss system which does not
(see Electoral Commission Report 2003, p 17).
(18)
But
ProLife now shows that the party broadcast is no more immune from
restriction than any other type of expression. It is questionable therefore
whether a court examining the system as a whole would be likely to find that
it adequately compensates for the blanket ban on political advertising.
Top | Contents | Bibliography
10. Conclusion
The consequences of the ProLife decision are far
more wide-ranging than the ongoing debate about abortion: a party wishing to
campaign on an anti-war stance by showing the horrors of war; or a pro-war
stance by showing the evils perpetrated by the target regime; or vegetarianism
by showing the butchery of the abattoir; or the death penalty by showing the
actuality of execution are all denied the ability to use the broadcast media
to its full effect to convey their message.
In recent years broadcasters have pushed the boundaries
of taste and decency by broadcasting graphic images of taboo subjects. Notable
examples include an autopsy of a human body (
The Autopsy, Channel 4, 20
November 2002 ),
(19) genital
mutilation (
Dirty Sanchez, MTV, 27 February
2003)
(20) and images of artists
cannibalising a baby and smearing blood on the dead bodies of conjoined twins
(
Beijing Swings, Channel 4, 2 January
2003).
(21) Explicit sexual material
is depicted after the 9.00 pm ‘watershed’ on too regular a basis to
recount. In some of these cases complaints are upheld by the regulatory
authorities. In others they are not. Usually the broadcasters mount vigorous
defences. In many of these programmes the aim is to provoke thought and debate
– although in some it may be simply to provide a frisson in viewers. But
in
ProLife political expression, which, according to the jurisprudence
ought to be accorded the highest level of protection, was subjected to prior
restraint (see Barendt 1985 and 2003; Mill
1980).
(22) Their broadcast was not
even allowed onto television screens – the debate was not even entered
into. Indeed it might be said that the broadcasters showed noticeably more
reluctance to take risks on behalf of a party broadcast than they tend to in
respect of their own programmes.
ProLife presents the ironic spectacle
of broadcasters, so often to be seen wielding the sword in defence of freedom of
expression, acting as censors.
Modern Britain is a place notorious for its political
apathy, at least in party political terms. The turnout at the 2001 general
election was 59% - the lowest since 1918. Among 18 – 24 year olds the
turnout was 39% (The Independent, 4 July 2001). The House of Commons Public
Administration Select Committee has described the situation as one of
‘civic crisis’ (First Report 2001, para 4). It is perhaps not too
great an exaggeration to suggest that people would rather vote on ‘Big
Brother’ than in a general election (The Guardian, 23 May
2001).
Television is the most pervasive (and arguably the most
powerful) means of mass communication. It is one of the media by which
enthusiasm could potentially be re-injected into civic and political life. The
Electoral Commission has recommended the retention of Party Broadcasts for these
very reasons saying that the ‘principle that political parties should
freely be able to publicise their platforms and policies to voters and that
voters should be able to receive such information is a vital one’
(Electoral Commission Report 2003, p 3). It further urged that parties should
be ‘innovative in their design and production of PPBs’ (p 36).
Lord Scott said in ProLife (at para
99):
In
an era of voter apathy a mind set of broadcasters which rejects a PEB on an
undeniably important issue, on the ground that it would be offensive to large
numbers of the voting public denigrates the voting public, treats them like
children who need to be protected from the unpleasant realities of life,
seriously undervalues their political maturity and can only promote . . . voter
apathy.
The decision in
ProLife is a poor one for many reasons – but
particularly so because extremely difficult material is regularly shown for
the purposes of news and current affairs reporting, creating a frisson, toying
with a taboo or, in some cases, merely providing titillation. But put similarly
difficult images in an election context, where individuals might actually be
presented with the stark reality of having to exercise democratic responsibility,
and broadcasters baulk at the thought of breaching regulations that they otherwise
seem quite prepared to flout. And the House of Lords, it seems, is unwilling
to stand up for free speech in the medium were it could be most influential
and where the subject matter ought to be most jealously guarded.
Top | Contents
Bibliography
Allan, T R S (2001) Constitutional Justice: A Liberal
Theory of the Rule of Law (Oxford: Oxford University
Press).
Barendt, E (1985) Freedom of Speech (Oxford:
Clarendon).
Barendt, E(1998) The First Amendment and the
Media in Importing the First Amendment Ian Loveland (ed.) (Oxford:
Hart).
Barendt, E (2003) , “Free Speech and
Abortion” Public Law 580.
Bullinger, M (1985) “Freedom of Expression and
Information: an essential element of democracy” Sevilla Colloquy 6 Human
Rights Law Journal 339.
Craig, P (2001) ‘The Courts, The Human Rights Act
and Judicial Review’ 117 Law Quarterly Review 589.
Dworkin, R (1977) Taking Rights Seriously
(London: Duckworth).
Dworkin, R (1996) Why must speech be free? in
Freedom’s Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Edwards, R (2002) ‘Judicial Deference under the
Human Rights Act’ 65 Modern Law Review 859.
Ekins, R (2003) ‘Judicial Supremacy and the Rule
of Law’ 119 Law Quarterly Review 127.
First Report (2001) House of Commons Public Administration Select Committee
Public Participation: Issues and Innovations: The Government’s Response
to the Sixth Report of Session 2000-2001. HC 334. <
http://www.publications.parliament.uk>
Geddis, A (2002) ‘What future for political
advertising on the United Kingdom’s television screens?’ Public Law
615.
Geddis, A (2003) ’”If Thy Right Eye Offend
Thee, Pluck it Out”: R v BBC , ex p ProLife Alliance’
66 Modern Law Review 885.
Griffith JAG (2000) ‘The Brave New World of Sir
John Laws’ 63 Modern Law Review 159.
Jones, J (1995) ‘The Devaluation of Human Rights
Under the European Convention’ Public Law 430.
Jowell, J (2003) ‘Judicial Deference: Servility,
Civility or Institutional Capacity’ Public Law 592.
Klug, F (2003) ‘Judicial Deference under the Human
Rights Act 1998’ 2 European Human Rights Law Review 125.
Lavender, N (1997) ‘The Problem of the Margin of
Appreciation’ 4 European Human Rights Law Review 380.
Laws, Sir J (1993) ‘Is the High Court the Guardian
of Fundamental Constitutional Rights?’ Public Law 59.
Lester of Herne Hill, Lord (1998) ‘Universality
versus Subsidiarity: A Reply’ 1 European Human Rights Law Review
73.
Lewis, T (2002) ‘Human Earrings, Human Rights and
Public Decency’ 1 Entertainment Law 50.
Mahoney, P (1997) ‘Universality versus
Subsidiarity in Strasbourg Case Law on Free Speech: Explaining Some Recent
Judgments’ 4 European Human Rights Law Review 364.
Mahoney, P (1998) ‘The Doctrine of the Margin of
Appreciation under the European Convention on Human Rights: Marvellous Richness
or Invidious Cultural Relativism’ 19 Human Rights Law Journal
1.
Meiklejohn, A (1961) ‘First Amendment is
Absolute’ Supreme Court Review 245.
Meiklejohn, A (1965) Free Speech and its Relation to
Self Government, reprinted in Political Freedom: The Constitutional
Powers of the People (New York: Oxford University Press).
Mill, J S (1980) On Liberty and Other Writings
ed. S Collini (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Mowbray, A (1999) ‘The role of the European Court
of Human Rights in the promotion of Democracy’ Public Law
703.
Nicol, D (2002) ‘Convention Rights a no-go Zone
for Parliament? Public Law 438.
Scanlon, T (1977) A Theory of Free Expression in
The Philosophy of Law ed. Dworkin, R (Oxford: Oxford University
Press).
Singh, R (1999) ‘Is there a Role for the
‘Margin of Appreciation’ in National law after the Human Rights
Act’ 1 European Human Rights Law Review 15.
Schauer, F (1980) Free Speech – A Philosophical
Enquiry (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Scott, A (2003) ‘”A Monstrous and
Unjustifiable Infringement”? Political Expression and the Broadcasting Ban
on Advocacy Advertising’ 6 Modern Law Review 224.
Woolf of Barnes, Lord (1995) ‘Droit Public English
Style’ Public Law 1995 57.
Yourow, H (1996) The Margin of Appreciation in the
Dynamics of the European Human Rights Jurisprudence (The Hague and London:
Kluwer Law International).
(1)
The Broadcasting Act 1990, s 36(1)a provided that any licence granted to any
independent broadcaster had to contain conditions requiring the broadcaster to
include ‘party political broadcasts’ (PPBs) in its service. The
Communications Act 2003 s 333 retains this requirement. Such licenses were
granted by the Independent Television Commission. Whilst the BBC has no such
obligation it has voluntarily made airtime available for PPBs since the 1950s as
part of its obligation to provide a ‘public service for disseminating
information, education and entertainment’.
(2)
There is no special definition of PPBs and PEBs; the latter is simply a PPB made
before an election. Prior to the 2001 general election the BBC and independent
broadcasters agreed rules for the allocation of PEBs to political parties such
that a party would secure airtime in a particular region if it fielded
candidates in one-sixth of the seats in that area.
(3)
The Communications Act 2003 s 319 imposes the duty to set standards on the new
Office of Communications (OFCOM). S 319 (2) (f) requires that one of the
‘standards objectives’ be ‘that generally accepted standards
are applied to the contents of television and radio services so as to provide
adequate protection for members of the public from the inclusion in such
services of offensive and harmful material’.
(4)
The 1996 Charter provides in clause 7(1)b that the Governors must satisfy
themselves that all activities of the Corporation are carried out in accordance
with any agreement which may be made between the Corporation and the Secretary
of State. The current Agreement, Cmnd. 3152 (25 January 1996) provides in
clause 5(1)(d) that all programmes it transmits do not ‘ . . . include
anything which offends against good taste or decency’. In order to try
and ensure some degree of harmonisation in the application of ‘taste and
decency’ standards broadcasters had to produce a code – the
ITC’s version being called the ‘ITC Programme Code’
(Broadcasting Act 1990, ss 6(3), 90(5)) and the BBC’s ‘The BBC
Producer’s Guidelines’ (BBC Agreement para. 5.3 ). The Broadcasting
Act 1996 set up the Broadcasting Standards Commission (BSC). Under s 108 it
had a duty to draw up a code giving guidance as to standards of taste and
decency. Under s 109 it was under a duty to monitor programmes in relation to
taste and decency. The Communications Act 2003 transfers the powers and duties
of the BSC to OFCOM. Section 319 requires OFCOM to set standards for programme
contents.
(5)
Laws LJ stressed the common law’s recognition and protection of
fundamental constitutional rights, especially freedom of speech at election time
(para 36). Simon Brown LJ based his approach more directly on Article 10 ECHR
(para 50).
(6)
The majority comprised Lords Nicholls, Hoffmann, Millett, and Walker. Lord
Scott was the sole dissentient. Lord Millett, who did not give a full speech,
said that whilst he had ‘for a long time been of the contrary view’
was persuaded by the reasons given in the speech of Lord Nicholls.
(7)
A variation on the argument from truth can be seen in the American First
Amendment case law, particularly in the ‘free market of ideas’
jurisprudence of Oliver Wendell Holmes. See
Abrams v United States 249 US
616 (1919) (dissent of Holmes J). See also
Schenk v United States 249 US
47 (1919) (judgment of Holmes J).
(8)
A distinct but related argument is that from moral autonomy (Dworkin 1977;
1996).
(9)
The Preamble to ECHR stresses the importance of ‘effective political
democracy’. Several Articles provide that rights can only be restricted if
‘necessary in a democratic society’.
(10)
Lord Walker did seem to cast some doubt on this proposition (at para
137).
(11)
Lord Hoffmann cited with approval Andrew Geddis’ article (Geddis 2003) in
which he says ‘apart from the confident assertion by Laws LJ of the
courts’ – his – role as “constitutional guardian”,
what else really justifies unelected judges making decisions as to how the
country’s electoral processes will be shaped?’
(12)
Lord Hoffmann cited (at para 69) the fears of the Electoral Commission voiced in
its January 2003 Report – that there would be an ‘incentive for
organisations to register as political parties and field sufficient candidates
in order to qualify for PPBs which would not only provide access to the media
that would not otherwise be available but would enable material to be broadcast
that would not otherwise be allowed’.
(13)
In
Chassangno v France (1999) 29 EHRR 615 para 113 the European Court
said that ‘only indispensable imperatives can justify interference with
enjoyment of a Convention right’. It might be questioned whether the
avoidance of offence to a potentially small number of viewers would constitute
an ‘indisputable imperative’ (see Barendt 2003).
(14)
Lords Nicholls and Walker made the same point at paras 8 and 126 respectively.
(15)
Lord Hoffmann cited several cases in support of this proposition:
Benjamin v
Minister of Information and Broadcasting [2001] 1 WLR 1040; the European
Commission on Human Rights decisions in
Haider v Austria (1995) 83 DR 66
and
Huggett v UK (1995) 82A DR 98.
(16)
The previous ban was under s 8 and s 92 of the Broadcasting Act 1990. The term
‘political’ had been interpreted very widely to include even a radio
advertisement by Amnesty International designed to bring attention to the
unfolding genocide in Rwanda in 1994 (
R v Radio Authority ex parte Bull
[1996] 2 All ER 501). Section 321(3) a-g defines the terms ‘objects
of a political nature’ and ‘political ends’ to include for
example ‘bringing about changes in the law’ and ‘influencing
the policies of local regional or national
governments’.
(17)
Note the similarity to the reasons advanced by the Swiss government in VgT
(2002) 34 EHRR 4 para 21.
(18)
As a response to the Electoral Commission Report the Government has recently
published a consultation paper soliciting public views on the future of PPBs:
Party Political Broadcasting: Public Consultation (Consultation Paper
2004).
(19)
Broadcast at 11.05 pm. Complaint to BSC not upheld - Bulletin 56. See
The
Guardian 21 November 2002.
(20)
Complaint to BSC upheld - Bulletin 66.
(21)
Broadcast at 11.45 pm. Found by the ITC to be in breach of s 1.1 of its
Programme Code. Bulletin 10 (10 March 2003). Channel 4 refused to accept the
ruling citing its right to present challenging material. See
The Guardian
10 and 11 March 2003.
(22)
The European Court of Human Rights has stressed that prior restraint calls for
‘special scrutiny’
Observer and Guardian v UK (1991) 14
EHRR 259 para 60. For the ProLife Alliance this was critical because, by the
time the case reached the Court of Appeal, the General Election had taken
place.
BAILII:
Copyright Policy |
Disclaimers |
Privacy Policy |
Feedback |
Donate to BAILII
URL: http://www.bailii.org/uk/other/journals/WebJCLI/2004/issue5/tlewis5.html