BAILII is celebrating 24 years of free online access to the law! Would you consider making a contribution?
No donation is too small. If every visitor before 31 December gives just £5, it will have a significant impact on BAILII's ability to continue providing free access to the law.
Thank you very much for your support!
[Home] [Databases] [World Law] [Multidatabase Search] [Help] [Feedback] | ||
The Law Commission |
||
You are here: BAILII >> Databases >> The Law Commission >> A New Homicide Act For England And Wales? (Consultation Paper) [2005] EWLC 177 (20 December 2005) URL: http://www.bailii.org/ew/other/EWLC/2005/177.html Cite as: [2005] EWLC 177 |
[New search] [Printable PDF version] [Help]
The Law Commission
Consultation Paper No 177
A NEW HOMICIDE ACT FOR ENGLAND AND WALES?
A Consultation Paper
The Law Commission was set up by section 1 of the Law Commissions Act 1965 for the purpose of promoting the reform of the law.
The Law Commissioners are:
The Honourable Mr Justice Toulson, Chairman
Professor Hugh Beale QC, FBA
Mr Stuart Bridge
Dr Jeremy Horder
Professor Martin Partington CBE
The Chief Executive of the Law Commission is Steve Humphreys and its offices are at Conquest House, 37-38 John Street, Theobalds Road, London WC1N 2BQ.
This consultation paper, completed on 28 November 2005, is circulated for comment and criticism only. It does not represent the final views of the Law Commission.
The Law Commission would be grateful for comments on its proposals before 13 April 2006. Comments may be sent either –
By post to:
David Hughes Law Commission Conquest House 37-38 John Street Theobalds Road London WC1N 2BQ
Tel: 020-7453-1212 Fax: 020-7453-1297
By email to:
It would be helpful if, where possible, comments sent by post could also be sent on disk, or by email to the above address, in any commonly used format.
All responses will be treated as public documents in accordance with the Freedom of Information Act 2000, and may be made available to third parties.
This consultation paper is available free of charge on our website at:
http://www.lawcom.gov.uk/murder.htm
THE LAW COMMISSION
A NEW HOMICIDE ACT FOR ENGLAND AND WALES?
CONTENTS
PART 1: WHY IS A NEW HOMICIDE ACT NEEDED? | PART 1 |
The terms of reference for the Review of Murder | 1 |
How is the Law Commission taking forward these terms of reference? | 2 |
The existing law and the problems with it: a brief guide | 3 |
Offences | 4 |
Problems with these offences | 5 |
Partial defences | 6 |
Problems with these partial defences | 7 |
Missing defences | 8 |
Sentencing and reform of the law of murder | 9 |
Our provisional proposals: an overview of the structure | 10 |
Why is a new Homicide Act needed? | 11 |
The definition of murder is badly out-of-date | 12 |
Defences to murder lack coherence and are too wide or too narrow in scope | 13 |
Provocation | 14 |
Excessive force in self-defence | 15 |
Duress | 16 |
Suicide pacts and depressed carers who kill | 17 |
Why can't the judges be left to make the necessary changes? | 18 |
What has Parliament done up until now? | 19 |
The Criminal Justice Act 2003 and the law of homicide | 20 |
Our philosophy: promoting coherence in the law | 21 |
PART 2: CHANGING THE STRUCTURE OF THE LAW OF HOMICIDE | PART 2 |
Questions and provisional proposals | 1 |
Our provisional view of how the law of homicide should be restructured | 2 |
Should murder remain a separate offence, or offences? | 3 |
Some advantages of confining "first degree murder" to intent-to-kill cases | 4 |
Keeping the offence of "murder": the proposals of the CLRC | 5 |
The "sanctity of life" argument | 6 |
The "sanctity of life" argument | 6 |
The argument of Sir Louis Blom-Cooper and Professor Terence Morris | 7 |
Should "first degree murder", and the mandatory penalty, be further restricted? | 8 |
Premeditation | 9 |
Should "first degree murder" extend beyond intent-to-kill cases? | 10 |
Should there be a further category of murder? "Second degree murder" | 11 |
A radical alternative: abolish all partial defences | 12 |
There is no coherence to the way defences and partial defences interrelate | 13 |
Defence rules have become over-complex and are applied inconsistently | 14 |
Schedule 21 to section 269 of the Criminal Justice Act 2003 | 15 |
Fault elements and the structure of the law of homicide | 16 |
PART 3: THE FAULT ELEMENT IN MURDER | PART 3 |
Questions and provisional proposals | 1 |
An overview of the issues and our proposals | 2 |
"First degree murder" and the intention to kill | 3 |
"Second degree murder" and the intention to do serious harm | 4 |
"Second degree murder" and reckless indifference | 5 |
Summary | 6 |
The "serious harm" rule and liability for reckless murder: a first look | 7 |
The "serious harm" rule | 8 |
Murder by reckless indifference | 9 |
The two kinds of fault element in "second degree murder" | 10 |
The serious ("grievous bodily") harm rule | 11 |
Background considerations | 12 |
The "wide" view of grievous bodily harm | 13 |
The "ordinary meaning" view of serious harm | 14 |
The "potentially lethal harm" view of serious harm | 15 |
Defining serious harm | 16 |
Previous recommendations: the "fully subjective" approach | 17 |
The views of the Irish Law Reform Commission | 18 |
Reforming the "serious harm" rule | 19 |
A radical alternative categorisation? | 20 |
Murder by reckless indifference to causing death | 21 |
Supplementing the "serious harm" rule, within "second degree murder" | 22 |
Alternatives to "reckless indifference" | 23 |
Should killing by reckless indifference replace, or supplement, the "serious harm" rule? | 24 |
Should the scope of murder though reckless indifference be further restricted? | 25 |
Fault in manslaughter | 26 |
Gross negligence manslaughter | 26 |
Unlawful act manslaughter: the Government's proposals | 27 |
PART 4: INTENTION | PART 4 |
Questions and provisional proposals | 1 |
The First Model | 2 |
The Second Model | 3 |
Structure of this Part | 4 |
Introduction | 5 |
The First Model: previous Law Commission recommendations for a definition of "intentionally" | 6 |
Clause 18(b) of the Draft Criminal Code (1989) | 7 |
Shortcomings identified in relation to clause 18(b)(ii) of the Draft Code | 8 |
Danger of blurring the distinction between "intention" and "recklessness" | 9 |
The requirement that an event will occur in the ordinary course of events | 10 |
A result which it is the actor's purpose to avoid | 11 |
Doubts about the standard formulation | 12 |
Our views about the shortcomings and doubts | 13 |
Clause 1(a) of the Draft Criminal Law Bill | 14 |
Shortcomings identified in respect of clause 1(a) of the draft Criminal Law Bill | 15 |
Does the phrase "If he were to succeed in his purpose of causing some other result" make the definition of "intentionally" too narrow? | 16 |
Is the word "purpose" unsuitable for a definition of an intentional result? | 17 |
Our views about the shortcomings with clause 1(a) of the Criminal Law Bill | 18 |
Scope of the definition | 19 |
"Purpose" | 20 |
Our views on the definition of "intentionally" | 21 |
A new definition based on Clause 18(b)(ii) – "intentionally as to a result" | 22 |
Is it just to equate foresight of a virtually certain result with intention? | 23 |
A proviso to exclude counter-intuitive findings from the definition of "intentionally" | 24 |
Other approaches to avoiding counter-intuitive outcomes | 25 |
The phrase "would occur in the ordinary course of events" | 26 |
Conclusion | 27 |
The First Model: proposal based on Clause 18(b)(ii) | 28 |
The Second Model: based on codification of the common law | 29 |
Our views | 30 |
The Second Model: proposal based on codification of the common law | 31 |
Conclusion | 32 |
The doctrine of double effect | 33 |
The basis of this doctrine | 34 |
The distinction between intended results and side-effects | 35 |
The distinction between intention and emotional desire | 36 |
A definition of murder suggested by Finnis, adopting a narrow meaning of intent | 37 |
Adams | 38 |
Glanville Williams | 39 |
How should the law of murder address the doctrine of double effect? | 40 |
Conclusion | 41 |
PART 5: COMPLICITY IN "FIRST DEGREE MURDER" | PART 5 |
Questions and provisional proposals | 1 |
Introduction | 2 |
Secondary liability and murder at common law | 3 |
D's conduct – the general rule | 4 |
D's state of mind – the general rule | 5 |
D's conduct and state of mind – joint enterprises | 6 |
Secondary liability for murder – our proposals | 7 |
A new doctrine of secondary liability | 8 |
(a) D "intended" that "first degree murder" should be committed | 9 |
(b) D and P were parties to a joint venture to commit "first degree murder" | 10 |
(c) D and P were parties to a joint venture to commit another offence | 11 |
"First degree murder" rather than "second degree murder"? | 12 |
A special defence for secondary participants in murder? | 13 |
A partial defence of duress for participants in murder? | 14 |
A new homicide offence for some parties to a joint venture | 15 |
PART 6: DIMINISHED RESPONSIBILITY AND PROVOCATION | PART 6 |
Questions and provisional proposals | 1 |
Diminished responsibility | 2 |
Introduction | 3 |
Our previous position on whether diminished responsibility should be retained as a partial defence to murder | 4 |
Our current position | 5 |
A partial defence to "first degree murder"? | 6 |
Should diminished responsibility reduce "first degree murder" to "second degree murder" or to manslaughter? | 7 |
A partial defence to "second degree murder"? | 8 |
Reformulating the definition of diminished responsibility | 9 |
Our provisional proposal, and the New South Wales solution | 10 |
Other reform options and alternative definitions of diminished responsibility | 11 |
German law | 12 |
The Mental Health Act 1983 | 13 |
Children who kill | 14 |
Reform of the partial defence of diminished responsibility | 15 |
An alternative solution? | 16 |
The role of the expert witness | 17 |
Procedure in diminished responsibility cases | 18 |
General considerations | 19 |
The 'Queensland' model | 20 |
The relationship between insanity and diminished responsibility | 21 |
Provocation and defensive homicide | 22 |
Our previous proposals | 23 |
The proposals of the Victorian Law Reform Commission | 24 |
The relationship between provocation and diminished responsibility | 25 |
PART 7: DURESS AS A DEFENCE TO MURDER | PART 7 |
Questions and provisional proposals | 1 |
Introduction | 2 |
Duress under common law | 3 |
Duress by threats | 4 |
Duress of circumstances | 5 |
History of the Law Commission's view on duress and murder | 6 |
The arguments of principle | 7 |
Summary of the main arguments against extending the defence to cover murder | 8 |
Summary of arguments in favour of extending duress to cover murder | 9 |
The need for consultation | 10 |
Our proposed framework | 11 |
The position of duress within the overall structure of homicide | 12 |
Provisional proposal that duress should be a partial defence to a charge of "first degree murder" | 13 |
Duress and "second degree murder" | 14 |
Duress as a partial defence compared with the other partial defences | 15 |
The basis of a plea of duress | 16 |
Characteristics of the defendant | 17 |
Reasons for recommending that common law rule as to the defendant's characteristics should be altered | 18 |
The need for the defendant's view of the nature of the threat to be objectively reasonable | 19 |
The previous view of the Law Commission | 20 |
The plea should be objectively based | 21 |
Reconciling the need for reasonable grounds with the decision in Martin (David Paul) | 22 |
Other requirements necessary in order to establish a plea of duress | 23 |
The conduct of the defendant must be directly related to the threats | 24 |
The rule in Safi and Ors 190 Official protection | 25 |
Voluntary exposure to duress | 26 |
The decision in Hasan | 27 |
Duress and attempted murder | 28 |
The requisite test as to characteristics of the defendant in cases of attempted murder | 29 |
The burden of proof | 30 |
Our former view | 31 |
Additional reasons for making the defence available in some types of murder cases | 32 |
Juveniles | 33 |
Complicity | 34 |
PART 8: KILLING WITH CONSENT AND DIMINISHED RESPONSIBILITY | PART 8 |
Questions and provisional proposals | 1 |
Suicide pacts | 2 |
Killing with consent, when the killer's responsibility is diminished | 3 |
Our Terms of Reference and the scope of our consultation | 4 |
How the argument proceeds | 5 |
A brief introduction to the existing legal provisions | 6 |
Should section 4 of the Homicide Act 1957 be retained? | 7 |
'Mercy Killing': the proposals of the Criminal Law Revision Committee | 8 |
'Mercy Killing': the Nathan Committee Report | 9 |
Depressed carers who kill: some empirical evidence | 10 |
Murder-suicide, suicide pacts and gender differences | 11 |
Expanding section 2 of the Homicide Act 1957: our proposals | 12 |
Joint suicide and complicity in suicide | 13 |
PART 9: INFANTICIDE | PART 9 |
Questions and provisional proposals | 1 |
Introduction: a unique offence | 2 |
Historical background | 3 |
Infanticide and diminished responsibility under section 2 of the Homicide Act 1957 | 4 |
Retaining but reforming the offence of infanticide: minimal, moderate and radical reform options | 5 |
Criticisms of the offence | 6 |
The psychiatric basis of the offence | 7 |
The Act only applies to the biological mother | 8 |
The age limit of the victim | 9 |
The morally unsustainable mitigation of child killing | 10 |
Degrees of child killing | 11 |
Summary of previous proposals for reform | 12 |
The common factors | 13 |
The Butler Report | 14 |
The Fourteenth Report of the CLRC | 15 |
The Law Commission: Draft Code | 16 |
The present legislative context: Domestic Violence, Crime and Victims Act 2004 237 Options for Reform | 17 |
The abolitionist position | 18 |
The minimal reform position | 19 |
The moderate reform position | 20 |
The radical expansionist position | 21 |
Merger with diminished responsibility | 22 |
Application to "first degree murder" and "second degree murder" | 23 |
Charging and procedure at trial | 24 |
PART 10: LIST OF PROVISIONAL PROPOSALS AND CONSULTATION QUESTIONS | PART 10 |
The structure of homicide offences | 1 |
Provisional proposal | 2 |
Questions | 3 |
The general homicide offences that we are proposing | 4 |
"First degree murder" | 5 |
Provisional proposal | 6 |
Questions | 7 |
"Second degree murder" | 8 |
Provisional proposals | 9 |
Questions | 10 |
Manslaughter | 11 |
Provisional proposals | 12 |
Questions | 13 |
The meaning of intention | 14 |
The First Model | 15 |
The Second Model | 16 |
Complicity in "first degree murder" | 17 |
Provisional Proposals | 18 |
Questions | 19 |
The definition of the partial defence of diminished responsibility | 20 |
Provisional proposal | 21 |
Questions | 22 |
The partial defence of provocation | 23 |
Provisional proposal | 24 |
Questions | 25 |
Duress 255 Provisional proposal | 26 |
Questions | 27 |
Killing with consent and diminished responsibility | 28 |
Provisional proposal | 29 |
Questions | 30 |
Infanticide | 31 |
Provisional proposal | 32 |
Questions | 33 |
APPENDICES | |
APPENDIX A: REPORT ON PUBLIC SURVEY OF MURDER AND MANDATORY SENTENCING IN CRIMINAL HOMICIDES | APPENDIX A |
APPENDIX B: SUMMARY FINDINGS OF SURVEY OF CROWN PROSECUTORS | APPENDIX B |
APPENDIX C: SUBMISSIONS FROM JUDGES ON THE FAULT ELEMENT IN MURDER | APPENDIX C |
APPENDIX D: THE LAW OF HOMICIDE IN OTHER JURISDICTIONS | APPENDIX D |
APPENDIX E: ANALYSIS OF "LIFER" CASES | APPENDIX E |
APPENDIX F: A CASE STUDY | APPENDIX F |
APPENDIX G: BACKGROUND INFORMATION ABOUT MURDER AND HOMICIDE | APPENDIX G |
APPENDIX H: ALTERNATIVE VERDICTS IN HOMICIDE CASES | APPENDIX H |
APPENDIX I: PERSONS AND ORGANISATIONS | APPENDIX I |
PART 1 THE TERMS OF REFERENCE FOR THE REVIEW OF MURDER 1.1 In July 2005, the Government announced a review of the law of murder in England and Wales, with the following terms of reference: WHY IS A NEW HOMICIDE ACT NEEDED?
(1) To review the various elements of murder, including the defences and partial defences to it, and the relationship between the law of murder and the law relating to homicide (in particular manslaughter). The review will make recommendations that:
(a) take account of the continuing existence of the mandatory life sentence for murder;(b) provide coherent and clear offences which protect individuals and society;(c) enable those convicted to be appropriately punished; and(d) be fair and non-discriminatory in accordance with the European Convention of Human Rights and the Human Rights Act 1998.
(2) The process used will be open, inclusive and evidence-based and will involve:
(a) a review structure that will look to include key stakeholders;(b) consultation with the public, criminal justice practitioners, academics, those who work with victims' families, parliamentarians, faith groups;(c) looking at evidence from research and from the experiences of other countries in reforming their law.
(3) The review structure will include consideration of areas such as culpability, intention, secondary participation etc inasmuch as they apply to murder. The review will only consider the areas of euthanasia and suicide inasmuch as they form part of the law of murder, not the more fundamental issues involved which would need separate debate. For the same reason abortion will not be part of the review.
How is the Law Commission taking forward these terms of reference?
1.3 Issues we will not be addressing include:
(1) Justifications for killing: abortion, necessity and self-defence.
(2) The prohibited conduct element: causation, the legal criteria governing when life begins and when life ends and child destruction (the offence of killing a child in the womb capable of being born alive).
(3) The defences of insanity and intoxication.
(4) Aggravating features of a murder, such as an especially evil motive or the fact that a child or law officer on duty was intentionally targeted. We have also left these out of consideration as we regard them as having been adequately addressed by Parliament through the guidance that it has recently given on sentencing in murder cases (see paragraphs 1.27-1.29 and 1.104-1.123 below).
THE EXISTING LAW AND THE PROBLEMS WITH IT: A BRIEF GUIDE
1.5 This state of affairs should not continue. The sentencing guidelines that Parliament has recently issued for cases where someone has been convicted of murder[1] presuppose that murder has a rational structure, a structure that properly reflects degrees of fault and provides defences of the right kind and with the right scope. Unfortunately, the law does not have, and never has had, such a structure. Putting that right is an essential task for criminal law reform.
Offences
1.10 Manslaughter can be committed in one of four ways:
(1) Conduct that the defendant knew involved a risk of killing, and did kill, is manslaughter ("reckless manslaughter");
(2) Conduct that was grossly negligent given the risk of killing, and did kill, is manslaughter ("gross negligence manslaughter");
(3) Conduct, taking the form of an unlawful act involving a danger of some harm, that killed, is manslaughter ("unlawful and dangerous act manslaughter");
(4) Killing with the intent for murder but where a partial defence applies.
The term "involuntary manslaughter" is used to describe a manslaughter falling within (1) – (3) while (4) is referred to as "voluntary manslaughter".
Problems with these offences
1.11 The current definitions of these offences are largely the product of judicial law making in individual cases over hundreds of years. They are not the products of legislation enacted after wide consultation and research into alternative possibilities. Moreover, from time to time the definitions have been altered by the courts,[2] each new case sometimes generating further case law to resolve ambiguities left behind by the last one.
1.12 The inclusion within murder of cases in which the defendant killed, but intended only harm that the jury regards as serious, is highly controversial.[3] On this basis, even someone who positively believed both that no one would be killed by their conduct and that the harm they were inflicting was not serious, can find themselves bracketed with the "contract" or serial killer as a "murderer".
1.14 At the most serious end of the involuntary manslaughter spectrum, the law may be too generous to defendants who kill by reckless conduct. The worst kinds of reckless killer may deserve to be convicted of murder.[4]
EXAMPLE 1: D is seeking to steal a large book from the fourth floor of a library whose windows face on to a busy street. Seeing the librarian coming towards him, D quickly drops the book out of the window. It lands on V's head as she walks underneath the window, killing her.
1.16 D's theft of the book should not be sufficient to convict D of the manslaughter of V even though, in the circumstances, there was an obvious risk of some harm arising from D's action. The need to narrow the crime of involuntary manslaughter has already been accepted by Government.[5]
Partial defences
Problems with these partial defences
1.22 The partial defence of provocation is a confusing mixture of judge-made law and legislative provision. The basic rule has been clear enough for a long time: it is manslaughter, not murder, if the defendant, having been provoked, lost his or her self-control and killed in circumstances in which a reasonable person might also have done so. However, the highest courts have disagreed with one another on a number of occasions about the scope of the defence. Consequently, not only has its scope been left unclear, but there is no end in sight to the disagreement. In 2004 we recommended reform of the partial defence of provocation and we set out how we thought the defence should be reformed.[6] We return to this topic in Part 6.
Missing defences
1.25 One such claim arises when the defendant, fearing serious violence from an aggressor, goes too far in deliberately killing the aggressor in order to repel the feared attack. We have already recommended that the defendant's fear of serious violence should be the basis for a partial defence to murder, through reform of the provocation defence.[7]
Sentencing and reform of the law of murder
1.27 All persons convicted of murder are sentenced to imprisonment for life. The sentence comprises three periods, one of which is the minimum term. This is the period that the offender must spend in prison before he or she is eligible for release. The length of the minimum term is set by the trial judge. In deciding upon the length, he or she must refer to guidelines that Parliament provided in the Criminal Justice Act 2003 ("the 2003 Act"). Under the guidelines, the length of the minimum term will depend on the gravity of the murder. For example, suppose the defendant takes part in a plan to murder two (or more) persons and then participates in their murders. If the defendant is aged 21 or over, that should ordinarily be met with a sentence indicating that the defendant must spend the rest of his or her life in prison.[8] The setting down of such recommended minimum terms makes the argument for reform of the law of murder very strong.
OUR PROVISIONAL PROPOSALS: AN OVERVIEW OF THE STRUCTURE
1.38 "First degree murder" (mandatory life penalty):
(1) Intentional killing.
1.39 "Second degree murder" (discretionary life maximum penalty):
(1) Killing where the offender did not intend to kill but did intend to do serious harm.
(2) Recklessly indifferent killing, where the offender realised that his or her conduct involved an unjustified risk of killing, but pressed on with that conduct without caring whether or not death would result.
(3) Cases in which there is a partial defence to what would otherwise be "first degree murder".
1.40 Manslaughter (fixed term of years maximum penalty):
(1) Killing through gross negligence;
(2) Killing through an intentional act intended to cause injury or involving recklessness as to causing injury.
1.41 Other offences:
(1) Infanticide; complicity in suicide.
1.42 Defences reducing "first degree murder" to "second degree murder":[9]
(1) Provocation (gross provocation or fear of serious violence).
(2) Diminished responsibility.
(3) Duress (threat of death or of life-threatening injury).
1.45 We will also be concerned with other general principles that run alongside the "ladder" principle. One such is the "fair labelling" principle.[10] Offenders should not be labelled as guilty of murder, or of manslaughter, unless their conduct is sufficiently blameworthy to deserve that label. For example, we will be raising the question whether someone who killed when they intended to do only what the law regards as serious harm, and did not intend to kill, is fairly labelled as a 'murderer'. Is it right that such a person is regarded as a murderer, but someone provoked into killing intentionally by (say) his or her partner's unfaithfulness can be convicted only of manslaughter?
1.48 We must now turn to the justifications for these changes.
WHY IS A NEW HOMICIDE ACT NEEDED?
The definition of murder is badly out-of-date
1.51 Although they knew that this assertion was wrong, such was later judges' high regard for Lord Coke that they did not use their powers to correct the error. Lord Coke's word subsequently became law in the criminal codes of most states in the United States of America (USA), where it remains in a modified form to the present day. It was not finally erased from English law until 1957 when Parliament intervened.[11] Over the centuries, the error must have led to the execution of hundreds of people in England and Wales and across the USA who should really have been convicted of manslaughter.
1.52 This is how Lord Coke defined murder:
Murder is where a man of sound memory, and of the age of discretion, unlawfully killeth within any country of the realm any reasonable creature in rerum natura under the King's peace, with malice aforethought, either expressed by the party or implied by law, so that the party wounded, or hurt, etc die of the wound or hurt, etc within a year and a day after the same.[12]
1.54 They did this, for example, in the recent case in which the Court of Appeal ordered that conjoined twins could be separated to save the life of the stronger twin, even though that would mean the weaker twin died.[13] The question was whether the weaker twin was a "reasonable creature", protected by the law of murder, as defined by Lord Coke.
1.55 Even if it was broadly accurate at the time it was given, however, Lord Coke's definition is now seriously misleading and out-of-date in a number of respects.[14]
1.59 Secondly, "malice" is in itself a term of very uncertain scope. Even as recently as the 1970s, judges disagreed over whether, for the purposes of the law of murder, it included causing death through some kinds of reckless conduct.[15] Finally, in 1985 they agreed that it was confined to cases where the offender "intended" to do the relevant harm.[16] Yet what was the relevant harm? The answer to this question turned on the meaning of "acting 'maliciously' in causing another's death". Surprisingly, the judges held that it was not confined to death or the risk of killing.
1.60 Instead, acting "maliciously", in causing another's death has been held to cover not only those who intend to kill, but also those who kill when only intending to do harm the jury regards as serious.[17] This remains the law to the present day. So, in the following example D is guilty of murder because he acts "with malice aforethought":
EXAMPLE 2: D and V have been arguing over access to a parking space. V blocks D's way as D is trying to drive into the space in his large van. In order to get into the space, D drives over V's foot knowing he will break it in so doing. Complications set in when V is being treated in hospital for his broken foot, leading to his death.
1.61 There is little or no doubt that a broken foot is "serious harm", and it is that harm that, in the eye of the law, D intentionally inflicts on V.[18] As V dies in consequence, D may be convicted of murder. If convicted, D will receive the mandatory life sentence. In our view, this is the wrong result. D should be guilty of, at most, what we will call "second degree murder", and is probably better regarded as having committed manslaughter.[19]
Defences to murder lack coherence and are too wide or too narrow in scope
Provocation[20]
1.65 However, the exact scope of the defence is still a matter of great controversy. Decisions of the two highest judicial bodies in England and Wales, the House of Lords and the Privy Council, are – not for the first time – currently in conflict over a key element of the defence.[21] This is the question whether all, or only some, of a person's individual characteristics should be taken into account in judging whether their reaction to the provocation might have been a reaction of a reasonable person. That a disagreement between these judicial bodies over the scope of the defence (a dispute that might seem arcane to many) still rumbles on after four centuries of legal development shows the law up in a poor light.
1.66 Moreover, a defendant can avail him or herself of the defence in wholly unmeritorious cases. Possibly as a result of Parliamentary oversight when the law was partially reformed in 1957, a judge became obliged to put the defence to the jury as one to be considered even when the evidence that the defendant had been provoked was unpersuasive, and the matter was not even raised by defence counsel. We have already recommended changes to these rules in our Report, Partial Defences to Murder.[22]
Excessive force in self-defence[23]3
1.68 To be successful in the plea, however, the defendant must (amongst other things) have used no more than "reasonable force". If the jury find that the force used was unreasonable, because it was excessive, the defence fails altogether. In that event, there is unlikely to be any other defence available and he or she will be convicted of murder.[24] In law, there is no legal "halfway house" for those who over-react, even when they are facing a threat of serious violence. There is, in other words, no legal basis for convicting of manslaughter in such cases.
1.70 If a plea of provocation can reduce murder to manslaughter (the "half-way house"), then it should be possible to reach this result when a jury decides that there has been an excessive, but not greatly excessive, reaction to a threat of serious, unlawful force. This is what we recommended as part of our recommendations for reform of the provocation defence.[25]
Duress[26]
EXAMPLE 3: P threatens D with death unless D immediately drives P to a house that P wishes to burgle. D, knowing that P is capable of violence, realises that P may kill if P encounters a householder, V, during the burglary. D drives P to the house, and then speeds off. D kills V during the burglary.
1.75 The courts have resisted the application of a defence of duress to such cases on the grounds that, in some instances, a form of secondary participation in a crime can be more blameworthy than the actual killing.[27] This might be the case, say, where D (under threat of death from another) orders one of his or her sons to kill another person, which the son does. What the courts overlook is that, in such cases, the jury is not obliged to accept that the defence excuses D's involvement in his or her son's offence. The jury should be trusted to accept or reject the defence on the merits of the individual case.
1.76 It is a legal requirement that, for the defence to be successful, a person of ordinary courage and self-restraint might have done as the person acting under duress did.[28] The jury is perfectly entitled to take the view that the greater someone's involvement in murder, the less persuasive the case for permitting the defence to succeed.
EXAMPLE 4: A psychopathic father compels his eleven-year-old son through threats of death to participate in the murder of one of the father's rivals.
Suicide pacts and depressed carers who kill[29]
1.82 Finally, an example of the narrowness of existing defences concerns the much debated case of killing by consent. "Euthanasia" is, in law, murder. Even so, if someone kills another person as part of a suicide pact, but then does not (for whatever reason) kill themselves, they are only guilty of manslaughter.[30] If they simply helped the other person to die they may be convicted of the lesser offence of "assisting suicide", contrary to section 2 of the Suicide Act 1961.
EXAMPLE 5: D and V are terrorists trapped in a building during a shoot-out with the police. Seeing that their position is hopeless, D and V agree that D will blow them both up as the building is stormed, 'to take some police with us'. D detonates the bomb as the building is stormed but it kills only V.
EXAMPLE 6: D agrees with V that he will kill V. D conceals from V his intention to kill himself immediately thereafter, because he knows V very much wants him to make a new life for himself when she is gone. D kills V, then tries to kill himself but fails.
(1) Is the defence of diminished responsibility currently wide enough to capture cases where D is moved to act through depression?
(2) Should the fact that the victim also consented in such cases be regarded as providing an element of double mitigation, so that the offence should now be lower down the ladder of offences than it would be if diminished responsibility was the only mitigating factor?
Why can't the judges be left to make the necessary changes?
(1) If the solution is doubtful, the judges should beware of imposing their own remedy;
(2) Caution should prevail if Parliament has rejected opportunities for clearing up a known difficulty, or has legislated leaving the difficulty untouched;
(3) Disputed matters of social policy are less suitable areas for judicial intervention than purely legal problems;
(4) Fundamental legal doctrine should not lightly be set aside; and
(5) Judges should not make a change unless they can achieve finality and certainty.[31]
What has Parliament done up until now?
(1) It substantially narrowed the scope of the death penalty in murder cases (the death penalty was abolished entirely for murder in 1965).
(2) It abolished the arbitrary rule that someone is automatically guilty of murder whenever they kill – even accidentally – in the course of a "felony" (a more serious kind of criminal offence).
(3) It created the partial defences to murder of "diminished responsibility", and of killing in the course of a suicide pact.
(4) It also broadened the defence of provocation to cover provocation by words (as well as by blows or the threat of violence).
The Criminal Justice Act 2003 and the law of homicide
1.109 The approach adopted in schedule 21 has advantages over comparable provisions in the USA. Like schedule 21, it is common in states in the USA to identify for especially severe treatment "worst case" murders, such as the murder of a child, a judge or a police or prison officer. However, many states in the USA do this by dividing murder into a number of categories defined by law as separate offences for the purpose of justifying especially severe (or, indeed, lenient) treatment.[32] In contrast, the categories in schedule 21 only apply to sentencing.
1.118 A further point needs to be made about the way in which the 2003 Act relates to the law of homicide. It does not adequately address the most controversial of the remaining judge-made aspects of the law of murder. For example, the 2003 Act does not seek to change the definition of "murder", even though, for certain types of murder, it introduces such high starting points for fixing the minimum term of the life sentence. At common law, however, murder is committed not only when there was an intention to kill but also when there was an intention to do only serious harm to the victim.[33] It is inappropriate to treat someone who did not intend to kill, say, a child or a police officer in the same way as someone who did intend to kill such a person when deciding how long they should spend in prison before being eligible for release. This is so even if a very serious crime is committed in both cases. Consequently, the 2003 Act treats the fact that there was only an intention to do serious harm as a "mitigating factor" which can justify setting a lower minimum term.
1.119 Yet, it seems that it was only a misunderstanding between Parliament and the judiciary, prior to the passing of the 1957 Act, that resulted in an intention to do serious harm ("grievous bodily harm", as it is sometimes known) remaining an element of culpability sufficient to convict of murder when death resulted. The Royal Commission on Capital Punishment 1949-1953 ("the Royal Commission"), whose recommendations in 1953 formed the basis for the reforms in the1957 Act, was strongly influenced by evidence about the fault element of murder that it received from the then Lord Chief Justice. The Lord Chief Justice told the Royal Commission that to be guilty of murder in law, "a person who wittingly inflicts grievous bodily harm must know that he is endangering life" (our emphasis). He assured the Royal Commission he would direct a jury to that effect.[34]
1.120 Accordingly, the Royal Commission explicitly declined to make any recommendation for change to the mental element in murder, believing it to be satisfactory. However, shortly after the passing of the 1957 Act, the Lord Chief Justice himself gave the leading judgment in a case, Vickers,[35] which was at odds with what he had told the Royal Commission. The judgment in that case authoritatively established that murder is committed when a defendant who has killed intended to inflict serious harm, even in the absence of knowledge or belief that the victim's life would be endangered by his or her actions.
1.122 As in Lord Coke's day, then, a highly controversial piece of judicial law making was causing problems within the law of murder. Subsequently, judges fully acknowledged that there was a discrepancy between what the Lord Chief Justice had told the Royal Commission the fault element in murder was and what he had said it was in Vickers. However, as with Lord Coke's fatal error, later judges did not change the law to make it consonant with what had been the Royal Commission's and Parliament's understanding, even when the opportunity to do so arose.[36]
OUR PHILOSOPHY: PROMOTING COHERENCE IN THE LAW
If there is any case in which the law should speak plainly, without sophism or evasion, it is where life is at stake; and it is on this very occasion that the law is most evasive and most sophistical.[37]
1.130 A few years later, former Prime Minister W E Gladstone indicated his willingness to promote the enactment of a Homicide Act, based on what the Criminal Law Commissioners had proposed, to rationalise the law; but nothing was done.[38] That led one criminal lawyer to remark, at the beginning of the twentieth century, that a belief that a criminal code would be passed in the House of Commons was as naïve as "expecting to find milk in a male tiger".[39]
Note 1 Criminal Justice Act 2003, s 269, sched 21. [Back] Note 2 Eg, on murder see, Woollin [1999] 1 AC 82 (HL); and on manslaughter see, Adomako [1995] 1 AC 171 (HL); (Morgan) Smith [2001] 1 AC 290 (HL). [Back] Note 5 Home Office, Reforming the Law on Involuntary Manslaughter: The Government’s Proposals (2000). Example 1 is not discussed in those proposals. It is based on Franklin (1883) 15 Cox CC 163. [Back] Note 6 Partial Defences to Murder (2004) Law Com No 290, para 3.168. [Back] Note 7 Ibid. See Part 6. [Back] Note 8 Criminal Justice Act 2003, s 269, sched 21, para 4(2)(a). [Back] Note 9 For simplicity’s sake, we are provisionally of the view that the partial defences should all reduce “first degree murder” to the same lesser crime: either “second degree murder”, or manslaughter. Making a distinction between defences that reduce “first degree murder” to “second degree murder” and defences that reduce “first degree murder” to manslaughter would require the jury, in cases where more than one defence is pleaded, to agree which defence has been successfully pleaded. This is highly undesirable because a jury may agree that the crime should not be “first degree murder”, but may disagree on the reason (some jurors favouring, say, diminished responsibility, and other jurors favouring provocation). In such cases, the verdict should be the same whichever defence is successful, so that such disagreements do not result in an inability to reach a verdict. See Appendix H. [Back] Note 10 See A Ashworth, “The Elasticity of Mens Rea” in C Tapper (ed), Crime, Proof and Punishment (1981). [Back] Note 11 Homicide Act 1957, s 1. [Back] Note 13 Re A [2001] Fam 147 (CA). [Back] Note 14 Eg, the rule that death from a wound must occur within a year and a day was abolished by the Law Reform (Year and a Day Rule) Act 1996. [Back] Note 15 Hyam [1975] AC 55 (HL). [Back] Note 16 Moloney [1985] AC 905 (HL), [Back] Note 17 For detailed consideration, see Part 3. [Back] Note 18 For a discussion of “intention”, see Part 4. [Back] Note 19 See the discussion in Part 2. [Back] Note 20 See Partial Defences to Murder (2004) Law Com No 290, Part 3; and Part 6 below. [Back] Note 21 A-G for Jersey v Holley [2005] UKPC 23, 3 WLR 29; (Morgan) Smith [2001] 1 AC 146 (HL). [Back] Note 22 Partial Defences to Murder (2004) Law Com No 290, Part 3. [Back] Note 23 Ibid, Part 4; and Part 6 below. [Back] Note 24 Clegg [1995] 1 AC 482. [Back] Note 25 Partial Defences to Murder (2004) Law Com No 290, Parts 3 and 4. [Back] Note 27 Howe [1987] AC 417 (HL). [Back] Note 28 Graham [1982] 1 WLR 294 (CA); Howe [1987] AC 417 (HL). [Back] Note 29 Homicide Act 1957, s 4. [Back] Note 31 C v DPP (1996) AC 1, 28, per Lord Lowry. [Back] Note 32 A summary of Professor Claire Finkelstein’s analysis of American law is in Appendix D. We intend to publish the full analysis on our website shortly, together with other comparative law papers. [Back] Note 33 As indicated when discussing Lord Coke’s definition of murder, in paras 1.49-1.62. [Back] Note 34 Royal Commission on Capital Punishment, Royal Commission on Capital Punishment 1949-1954: Report (1953) Cmnd 8932, paras 106/472. [Back] Note 35 [1957] 2 QB 664. [Back] Note 36 Hyam v DPP [1975] AC 55; Cunningham [1982] AC 566. [Back] Note 37 Special Report from the Committee on Homicide Law Amendment Bill (1874) 314. [Back] Note 38 See K J M Smith, Lawyers, Legislators and Theorists: Developments in English Criminal Jurisprudence 1800-1957 (1998) 149. [Back]